Symposium Introduction: Epistemic Vices: Moving Beyond Saints and Sinners

IF 1 Q3 EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH EDUCATIONAL THEORY Pub Date : 2024-03-01 DOI:10.1111/edth.12621
Gerry Dunne
{"title":"Symposium Introduction: Epistemic Vices: Moving Beyond Saints and Sinners","authors":"Gerry Dunne","doi":"10.1111/edth.12621","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Perfect epistemic agents do not exist. People are messy. We make mistakes; we are error-prone. We have limited attention spans, sluggish cognitive processing powers, pedestrian interpersonal skills, inefficient and unreliable memories. At times we struggle to get out of our own way — the vagaries of life, relationships, and responsibilities, both individually and collectively, take a toll, especially in dopamine-seeking, split-attention environments. Such pressures keep us from being the very best version of themselves. More often than not, we are less than we ought to be. Specifically, all of us have flawed intellectual characters to some extent or another, which is to be expected. We are human after all. Flaws are encoded in our DNA. It comes as no surprise then, that there are times when we are defective inquirers — suboptimal or blameworthy epistemic agents. Prejudice, irrationality, superbia, closed-mindedness, epistemic entrenchment, willful ignorance, insouciance, my-side bias, to name but a few, all have the potential to colonize and deleteriously influence our capacities to efficiently and effectively acquire, share, produce, and audit knowledge, or to engage in responsible and effective inquiry. All this leaves us with a choice. Should educationalists pursue a virtue-based account of other-worldly epistemic excellence based on knowledge gained via strictly controlled laboratory conditions, or would it be more profitable to seek richer understandings of the flawed nature, scope, identity, and significance of our intellectual character traits, attitudes, and ways of thinking, and how they systematically, though not invariably, block the path to knowledge?<sup>1</sup></p><p><i>Intellectual vices</i> is a way of talking about those deleterious epistemic character traits, attitudes, and modes of thinking that reflect our imperfect epistemic desires and that get in the way of successful epistemic pursuits. Though various scholars understand the nature of epistemic vice in distinctive ways, there are currently two main perspectives: motivationalism and obstructivism.<sup>2</sup> The former characterizes epistemic vice in terms of imperfect epistemic motivations, while the latter understands it in consequentialist terms: more specifically, that which obstructs the acquisition, retention, and transmission of knowledge.</p><p>Virtue epistemologists pursue normative accounts regarding how prototypical thinkers under ideal conditions <i>should</i> think. Vice epistemologists, on the other hand, take a more true-to-life view of matters. They look to our zetetic failings and present an explanatory account of the way in which corrupted motivations and flawed intellectual character traits get in the way of knowledge. Broadly put, their interests hinge on understanding how, why, and under what circumstances specific vices of the mind (both personal and collective intellectual failings) obstruct the acquisition, retention, auditing, and transmission of knowledge.</p><p>So, what are the epistemic vices? Etymologically, “vice” derives from the Latin word <i>vitium</i>, which is a fault or defect. If we take seriously our epistemic responsibilities, it stands to reason that we must develop a proper account of what goes wrong when we (individually and collectively) fail to acquire, transmit, and audit knowledge in credible ways. In cases where we have a measure of control with respect to remedying our vices, we also require guidance on how to mitigate or overcome them. On this approximation, epistemic vices might be conceptualized as intellectual character failings, vicious attitudes, or corrupted ways of thinking that systematically get in the way of knowledge. Since character traits, in part, explain what people do, scholars maintain that epistemic vices explain, at least to some extent, how people, more often than not, fail to appropriately think, reason, reflect, inquire, or evaluate relevant evidence, and stress-test the strength of competing claims.<sup>3</sup></p><p>The relationship between epistemic vices and character traits is framed in dispositional terms. Vices, whether they are character traits, attitudes, or styles of thinking, first exist as dispositions. For instance, solubility is a disposition. On this view, dispositions are cashed out in terms of subjunctive conditionals. To say that sugar is soluble means that, if sugar were put in water, it would dissolve. Understood this way, dispositions are sensitive to certain stimulus events or conditions specific to them. Epistemic vices that are also character traits comprise tendencies to exhibit certain patterns of perception, feeling, thinking, reasoning, and behavior that obstruct the gaining, keeping, auditing, or sharing of knowledge. Like most robust character traits that are consistently manifested in a wide variety of trait-relevant eliciting conditions (including situations that are not always necessarily conducive to such behavior), they are habits of the heart-mind that are activated when the person comes into contact with the right activating conditions.<sup>4</sup> In other words, they are stable dispositions to act, think, and feel in particular ways.<sup>5</sup></p><p>Here are some examples of how this plays out in the real world. Closed-mindedness is a relatively familiar example of a characterological epistemic vice. First, to be clear: being closed-minded and thinking closed-mindedly represent the difference between a <i>trait</i> (what a person is predisposed toward) and an <i>action</i> (what a person does). Only part of what it is to be closed-minded is to think closed-mindedly. By thinking systematically in ways that are unreasonably entrenched, inflexible, insular, blinkered, irrationally defensive, and unreceptive or unresponsive to evidence that contravenes or threatens preexisting views, irrespective of the objective merits of such, closed-mindedness constitutes “an unwillingness or inability to engage, or engage seriously, with relevant intellectual options.”<sup>6</sup></p><p>Yet this is only part of the story: there is more to being closed-minded than simply thinking closed-mindedly. This is why thinking vices are more basic than character ones. Without a proper grasp of thinking vices, the corresponding character vice remains conceptually elusive. One mistake is to view closed-mindedness as necessitating having already made up one's mind (i.e., forming a prejudgment)<sup>7</sup> about a given topic. Closed-mindedness also pertains to the manner through which one arrives at beliefs or conducts inquiries, or the manner through which one seeks out and interprets the probative force of evidence. In real-world terms, closed-mindedness might manifest itself in exercising preferential treatment for certain select sources. It also might influence the types of questions one asks, how they are asked, the sequence in which they are asked, the time at which they are asked, the environment in which they are asked, and of whom they are asked.<sup>8</sup> Since not all instances of closed-mindedness amount to reductionist instances of dismissing intellectual options, educators require more nuanced and conceptually robust understandings of the concept, including how it plays out in real-world conditions. To explain why, look at another example. Since closed-mindedness need not involve dismissing an option outright, more subtle or stealthy instantiations of the concept exist. Some closed-minded individuals overinflate the valency of other options. Some downplay options they would rather avoid, not to dismiss them per se, but just enough to cast sufficient doubt so that others start to worry about their evidential merits. Likewise, closed-mindedness need not just be about failing to engage with other valid options. Such failures, where blameworthy, come in degrees and are context-dependent. Depending on the particulars of the case at hand, one might interpretively silence others (by unjustly assigning them a credibility deficit or purposively misinterpreting their utterances to suit their own agenda), fail to seek out and marshal discordant perspectives responsibly, flatly ignore nonconformists or malcontents, or be wholly oblivious to some or all of the above at any one time.</p><p>Epistemic vices often do not make much sense without understanding the attitudinal elements animating them. These attitudes express summary evaluations or appraisals of objects. To like or dislike something is to form a perspective on it, based on a particular evaluative description that shapes a perspective about that subject or object — a perspective that invariably comes in terms of degrees. For instance, I like soccer but dislike professional cycling. The extent to which I like soccer and dislike cycling can, in turn, be captured by means of attitudinal scales. Superbia (haughtiness), intellectual arrogance,<sup>9</sup> and insouciance<sup>10</sup> are noteworthy examples. Other paradigmatic cases include “cognitive superiority complex,”<sup>11</sup> “epistemic entrenchment” (imperviousness to contradictory evidence or reasons),<sup>12</sup> “my-world myopia,” and “epistemic malevolence” — a hostility or contempt for the good, including epistemic goods.<sup>13</sup> “My-world myopia” is a phrase I coin to capture situations in which members of elite or dominant demographic groups consciously avoid knowledge about the experiences and lifeworlds of oppressed or marginalized groups<sup>14</sup> in order to preserve psychologically comforting half-truths, to protect untested assumptions, to preserve unchecked privilege, and to evade accountability. For Quassim Cassam, insouciance captures the “casual lack of concern about whether one's beliefs have any basis in reality or are adequately supported by the best available evidence.”<sup>15</sup> Arguably this vice captures the zeitgeist of ameliorative epistemology in educational discourse. Students who engage in bullshit (the primary product of insouciance), at least in Harry Frankfurt's analysis, do not care about facts, evidence, rationality, truth, or falsity. More precisely, since the bullshitter “does not reject the authority of truth; he [simply] pays no attention to it at all,”<sup>16</sup> one can see the importance of educationalists focusing on scholarly conceptualizations of its forebearer, insouciance, framed here as a casual indifference (an epistemic apathy of sorts) to the truth, together with a stoic indifference to the central epistemic obligations to ground one's views in relevant facts, reasons, or evidence.</p><p>The preceding discussion provides a useful context for the papers in this <i>Educational Theory</i> symposium. Understanding epistemic vices is the key to rehabilitation. And since vices can exist in either individual or social settings, each with their own context-dependent particularities, and each with deleterious consequences for inquirers and knowledge, educators require a robust understanding of how, why, and under what conditions such vices operate — and how the individual and social registers relate to and influence each other. The papers in this symposium all speak to the pedagogical dimensions of dealing with epistemic vices.</p><p>David Coady in his paper “Stop Talking about Echo Chambers and Filter Bubbles” takes issue with the pervasive focus on echo chambers and filter bubbles as the cause of epistemic vices. He argues that such ubiquitous concepts and their repurposing by epistemologists<sup>17</sup> suffer from “use-mention confusion” whereby the “emergence and proliferation of new terms has been mistaken for the emergence and proliferation of new phenomena to which these terms putatively refer.”<sup>18</sup> In a sense, he asks, “what's new in the new?”— a question theorists, in his view, fail to answer satisfactorily. The upshot of this conceptual fuzziness is that echo chambers and filter bubbles remain inconsistently defined in the literature and, as a consequence, lack explanatory usefulness. Extrapolating further, Coady presents a compelling argument as to why the pursuit of certain binary characterizations of political views is a fools' errand: the very idea that exposure to the “other side” neatly captures predefined and clearly demarcated opposing ideologies (liberal versus conservative, for instance) is so ingrained in Western culture that we have forgotten to examine these false dichotomies critically. This argument has ramifications for neologisms like “epistemic bubbles” and “echo chambers,” since the former putatively refers to “<i>social epistemic structure[s] which [have] inadequate coverage through a process of exclusion by omission</i>,” while the latter supposedly represents a “<i>significant disparity in trust between members and non-members</i>.”<sup>19</sup> Taking epistemic bubbles to constitute situations in which other voices are not heard, while in echo chambers, “other voices are actively undermined,”<sup>20</sup> both rely on oversimple dichotomies. Getting clear about what precisely constitutes epistemically discordant exchanges requires a deeper and more nuanced consideration of what characterizes a sufficiently rich and varied broad political spectrum, together with an understanding of the particular structures that supposedly foster it. For Coady, the focus on echo chambers and filter bubbles — even those colonized by epistemologists — amounts to a debate as to whether or not most people expose themselves to heterogenous political discourses. That is the issue to focus on; toward this purpose he finds the language of echo chambers and filter bubbles to be not only “unnecessary” but “extremely harmful.”<sup>21</sup></p><p>The second paper in this collection examines whether interventionist epistemic paternalistic practices make us better evidentialist agents. In “Can Epistemic Paternalistic Practice Make Us Better Epistemic Agents?,” Giada Fratantonio looks to the purported benefits of using these as pedagogical tools with students to mitigate or eradicate what she refers to as “evidential vices.”<sup>22</sup> Noting that much of the literature focuses on whether epistemic paternalism is a genuinely epistemic form of paternalism,<sup>23</sup> as well as who is entitled to apply such interferences,<sup>24</sup> there exists a lacuna regarding to what extent, if any, such practices are actually effective in making a student a better epistemic agent. Breaking new ground, she argues, contra Daniella Meehan,<sup>25</sup> that <i>epistemic nudges</i> are both morally preferable and more effective in an instrumental sense. Principally, this argument turns on whether psychological dispositions are fixed or not. On this view, epistemic nudges are a bit like bubble wrap around a vase. Bubble wrap does not change the fragility of the vase; it only masks it. When epistemic nudges are not present and the bubble wrap removed, the vase remains as fragile as before.<sup>26</sup> This leads Meehan to maintain that epistemic nudges are not only ineffective but counterproductive, insofar as they can lead to epistemic laziness. In response, Fratantonio's counterargument posits that repeated nudges can result in long-lasting effects for the epistemic agent, and contrary to Meehan's worry about laziness, nudges do not bypass or hinder one's capacities to reason and think critically. In conclusion, Fratantonio suggests that epistemic nudges might house some unexplored promise in educational contexts.</p><p>The final article, “Epistemic Vice Rehabilitation: Saints and Sinners Zetetic Exemplarism,” by Gerry Dunne and Alkis Kotsonis, surveys a range of pedagogical possibilities for rehabilitating epistemic vices.<sup>27</sup> Rather than individualistic expositions, where vice reduction lies at the feet of each individual, we look instead to an exemplarist animated community of inquiry principles based on defeasible-reasons-regulated processes. We argue that this approach epitomizes a more socially attuned, interdependently calibrated, true-to-life vice-reduction model. Our proposed model comprises four distinct yet complementary components: (1) positive exemplars of epistemic virtue (saints); (2) negative exemplars of epistemic vice (sinners); (3) direct teaching/instruction; and (4) cognitive apprenticeship. Positive exemplars give students role models to admire and emulate. Negative exemplars show how we are all human and that what is important about mistakes is that we learn from them and endeavor not to make them again. Direct teaching tackles epistemic vices head-on by means of using age and stage-appropriate stimuli (Tik Tok videos, Instagram videos, etc.) to unpack the deleterious effects of epistemic vice. Finally, cognitive apprenticeship uses the principles of modeling and expert-guided practice, where students learn via hands-on, real-world tasks to harness and enhance their inquiry processes, such as conceptual mapping, stress-testing reasons, anticipating objections, formulating alternative explanations, and scrutinizing the force of evidential claims.</p><p>Together these papers offer a theoretical elaboration of the problem of epistemic vice, as well as specific pedagogical advice for educators on how to counteract them. Needless to say, this project is of special relevance today.</p>","PeriodicalId":47134,"journal":{"name":"EDUCATIONAL THEORY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0000,"publicationDate":"2024-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/edth.12621","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"EDUCATIONAL THEORY","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/edth.12621","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Perfect epistemic agents do not exist. People are messy. We make mistakes; we are error-prone. We have limited attention spans, sluggish cognitive processing powers, pedestrian interpersonal skills, inefficient and unreliable memories. At times we struggle to get out of our own way — the vagaries of life, relationships, and responsibilities, both individually and collectively, take a toll, especially in dopamine-seeking, split-attention environments. Such pressures keep us from being the very best version of themselves. More often than not, we are less than we ought to be. Specifically, all of us have flawed intellectual characters to some extent or another, which is to be expected. We are human after all. Flaws are encoded in our DNA. It comes as no surprise then, that there are times when we are defective inquirers — suboptimal or blameworthy epistemic agents. Prejudice, irrationality, superbia, closed-mindedness, epistemic entrenchment, willful ignorance, insouciance, my-side bias, to name but a few, all have the potential to colonize and deleteriously influence our capacities to efficiently and effectively acquire, share, produce, and audit knowledge, or to engage in responsible and effective inquiry. All this leaves us with a choice. Should educationalists pursue a virtue-based account of other-worldly epistemic excellence based on knowledge gained via strictly controlled laboratory conditions, or would it be more profitable to seek richer understandings of the flawed nature, scope, identity, and significance of our intellectual character traits, attitudes, and ways of thinking, and how they systematically, though not invariably, block the path to knowledge?1

Intellectual vices is a way of talking about those deleterious epistemic character traits, attitudes, and modes of thinking that reflect our imperfect epistemic desires and that get in the way of successful epistemic pursuits. Though various scholars understand the nature of epistemic vice in distinctive ways, there are currently two main perspectives: motivationalism and obstructivism.2 The former characterizes epistemic vice in terms of imperfect epistemic motivations, while the latter understands it in consequentialist terms: more specifically, that which obstructs the acquisition, retention, and transmission of knowledge.

Virtue epistemologists pursue normative accounts regarding how prototypical thinkers under ideal conditions should think. Vice epistemologists, on the other hand, take a more true-to-life view of matters. They look to our zetetic failings and present an explanatory account of the way in which corrupted motivations and flawed intellectual character traits get in the way of knowledge. Broadly put, their interests hinge on understanding how, why, and under what circumstances specific vices of the mind (both personal and collective intellectual failings) obstruct the acquisition, retention, auditing, and transmission of knowledge.

So, what are the epistemic vices? Etymologically, “vice” derives from the Latin word vitium, which is a fault or defect. If we take seriously our epistemic responsibilities, it stands to reason that we must develop a proper account of what goes wrong when we (individually and collectively) fail to acquire, transmit, and audit knowledge in credible ways. In cases where we have a measure of control with respect to remedying our vices, we also require guidance on how to mitigate or overcome them. On this approximation, epistemic vices might be conceptualized as intellectual character failings, vicious attitudes, or corrupted ways of thinking that systematically get in the way of knowledge. Since character traits, in part, explain what people do, scholars maintain that epistemic vices explain, at least to some extent, how people, more often than not, fail to appropriately think, reason, reflect, inquire, or evaluate relevant evidence, and stress-test the strength of competing claims.3

The relationship between epistemic vices and character traits is framed in dispositional terms. Vices, whether they are character traits, attitudes, or styles of thinking, first exist as dispositions. For instance, solubility is a disposition. On this view, dispositions are cashed out in terms of subjunctive conditionals. To say that sugar is soluble means that, if sugar were put in water, it would dissolve. Understood this way, dispositions are sensitive to certain stimulus events or conditions specific to them. Epistemic vices that are also character traits comprise tendencies to exhibit certain patterns of perception, feeling, thinking, reasoning, and behavior that obstruct the gaining, keeping, auditing, or sharing of knowledge. Like most robust character traits that are consistently manifested in a wide variety of trait-relevant eliciting conditions (including situations that are not always necessarily conducive to such behavior), they are habits of the heart-mind that are activated when the person comes into contact with the right activating conditions.4 In other words, they are stable dispositions to act, think, and feel in particular ways.5

Here are some examples of how this plays out in the real world. Closed-mindedness is a relatively familiar example of a characterological epistemic vice. First, to be clear: being closed-minded and thinking closed-mindedly represent the difference between a trait (what a person is predisposed toward) and an action (what a person does). Only part of what it is to be closed-minded is to think closed-mindedly. By thinking systematically in ways that are unreasonably entrenched, inflexible, insular, blinkered, irrationally defensive, and unreceptive or unresponsive to evidence that contravenes or threatens preexisting views, irrespective of the objective merits of such, closed-mindedness constitutes “an unwillingness or inability to engage, or engage seriously, with relevant intellectual options.”6

Yet this is only part of the story: there is more to being closed-minded than simply thinking closed-mindedly. This is why thinking vices are more basic than character ones. Without a proper grasp of thinking vices, the corresponding character vice remains conceptually elusive. One mistake is to view closed-mindedness as necessitating having already made up one's mind (i.e., forming a prejudgment)7 about a given topic. Closed-mindedness also pertains to the manner through which one arrives at beliefs or conducts inquiries, or the manner through which one seeks out and interprets the probative force of evidence. In real-world terms, closed-mindedness might manifest itself in exercising preferential treatment for certain select sources. It also might influence the types of questions one asks, how they are asked, the sequence in which they are asked, the time at which they are asked, the environment in which they are asked, and of whom they are asked.8 Since not all instances of closed-mindedness amount to reductionist instances of dismissing intellectual options, educators require more nuanced and conceptually robust understandings of the concept, including how it plays out in real-world conditions. To explain why, look at another example. Since closed-mindedness need not involve dismissing an option outright, more subtle or stealthy instantiations of the concept exist. Some closed-minded individuals overinflate the valency of other options. Some downplay options they would rather avoid, not to dismiss them per se, but just enough to cast sufficient doubt so that others start to worry about their evidential merits. Likewise, closed-mindedness need not just be about failing to engage with other valid options. Such failures, where blameworthy, come in degrees and are context-dependent. Depending on the particulars of the case at hand, one might interpretively silence others (by unjustly assigning them a credibility deficit or purposively misinterpreting their utterances to suit their own agenda), fail to seek out and marshal discordant perspectives responsibly, flatly ignore nonconformists or malcontents, or be wholly oblivious to some or all of the above at any one time.

Epistemic vices often do not make much sense without understanding the attitudinal elements animating them. These attitudes express summary evaluations or appraisals of objects. To like or dislike something is to form a perspective on it, based on a particular evaluative description that shapes a perspective about that subject or object — a perspective that invariably comes in terms of degrees. For instance, I like soccer but dislike professional cycling. The extent to which I like soccer and dislike cycling can, in turn, be captured by means of attitudinal scales. Superbia (haughtiness), intellectual arrogance,9 and insouciance10 are noteworthy examples. Other paradigmatic cases include “cognitive superiority complex,”11 “epistemic entrenchment” (imperviousness to contradictory evidence or reasons),12 “my-world myopia,” and “epistemic malevolence” — a hostility or contempt for the good, including epistemic goods.13 “My-world myopia” is a phrase I coin to capture situations in which members of elite or dominant demographic groups consciously avoid knowledge about the experiences and lifeworlds of oppressed or marginalized groups14 in order to preserve psychologically comforting half-truths, to protect untested assumptions, to preserve unchecked privilege, and to evade accountability. For Quassim Cassam, insouciance captures the “casual lack of concern about whether one's beliefs have any basis in reality or are adequately supported by the best available evidence.”15 Arguably this vice captures the zeitgeist of ameliorative epistemology in educational discourse. Students who engage in bullshit (the primary product of insouciance), at least in Harry Frankfurt's analysis, do not care about facts, evidence, rationality, truth, or falsity. More precisely, since the bullshitter “does not reject the authority of truth; he [simply] pays no attention to it at all,”16 one can see the importance of educationalists focusing on scholarly conceptualizations of its forebearer, insouciance, framed here as a casual indifference (an epistemic apathy of sorts) to the truth, together with a stoic indifference to the central epistemic obligations to ground one's views in relevant facts, reasons, or evidence.

The preceding discussion provides a useful context for the papers in this Educational Theory symposium. Understanding epistemic vices is the key to rehabilitation. And since vices can exist in either individual or social settings, each with their own context-dependent particularities, and each with deleterious consequences for inquirers and knowledge, educators require a robust understanding of how, why, and under what conditions such vices operate — and how the individual and social registers relate to and influence each other. The papers in this symposium all speak to the pedagogical dimensions of dealing with epistemic vices.

David Coady in his paper “Stop Talking about Echo Chambers and Filter Bubbles” takes issue with the pervasive focus on echo chambers and filter bubbles as the cause of epistemic vices. He argues that such ubiquitous concepts and their repurposing by epistemologists17 suffer from “use-mention confusion” whereby the “emergence and proliferation of new terms has been mistaken for the emergence and proliferation of new phenomena to which these terms putatively refer.”18 In a sense, he asks, “what's new in the new?”— a question theorists, in his view, fail to answer satisfactorily. The upshot of this conceptual fuzziness is that echo chambers and filter bubbles remain inconsistently defined in the literature and, as a consequence, lack explanatory usefulness. Extrapolating further, Coady presents a compelling argument as to why the pursuit of certain binary characterizations of political views is a fools' errand: the very idea that exposure to the “other side” neatly captures predefined and clearly demarcated opposing ideologies (liberal versus conservative, for instance) is so ingrained in Western culture that we have forgotten to examine these false dichotomies critically. This argument has ramifications for neologisms like “epistemic bubbles” and “echo chambers,” since the former putatively refers to “social epistemic structure[s] which [have] inadequate coverage through a process of exclusion by omission,” while the latter supposedly represents a “significant disparity in trust between members and non-members.”19 Taking epistemic bubbles to constitute situations in which other voices are not heard, while in echo chambers, “other voices are actively undermined,”20 both rely on oversimple dichotomies. Getting clear about what precisely constitutes epistemically discordant exchanges requires a deeper and more nuanced consideration of what characterizes a sufficiently rich and varied broad political spectrum, together with an understanding of the particular structures that supposedly foster it. For Coady, the focus on echo chambers and filter bubbles — even those colonized by epistemologists — amounts to a debate as to whether or not most people expose themselves to heterogenous political discourses. That is the issue to focus on; toward this purpose he finds the language of echo chambers and filter bubbles to be not only “unnecessary” but “extremely harmful.”21

The second paper in this collection examines whether interventionist epistemic paternalistic practices make us better evidentialist agents. In “Can Epistemic Paternalistic Practice Make Us Better Epistemic Agents?,” Giada Fratantonio looks to the purported benefits of using these as pedagogical tools with students to mitigate or eradicate what she refers to as “evidential vices.”22 Noting that much of the literature focuses on whether epistemic paternalism is a genuinely epistemic form of paternalism,23 as well as who is entitled to apply such interferences,24 there exists a lacuna regarding to what extent, if any, such practices are actually effective in making a student a better epistemic agent. Breaking new ground, she argues, contra Daniella Meehan,25 that epistemic nudges are both morally preferable and more effective in an instrumental sense. Principally, this argument turns on whether psychological dispositions are fixed or not. On this view, epistemic nudges are a bit like bubble wrap around a vase. Bubble wrap does not change the fragility of the vase; it only masks it. When epistemic nudges are not present and the bubble wrap removed, the vase remains as fragile as before.26 This leads Meehan to maintain that epistemic nudges are not only ineffective but counterproductive, insofar as they can lead to epistemic laziness. In response, Fratantonio's counterargument posits that repeated nudges can result in long-lasting effects for the epistemic agent, and contrary to Meehan's worry about laziness, nudges do not bypass or hinder one's capacities to reason and think critically. In conclusion, Fratantonio suggests that epistemic nudges might house some unexplored promise in educational contexts.

The final article, “Epistemic Vice Rehabilitation: Saints and Sinners Zetetic Exemplarism,” by Gerry Dunne and Alkis Kotsonis, surveys a range of pedagogical possibilities for rehabilitating epistemic vices.27 Rather than individualistic expositions, where vice reduction lies at the feet of each individual, we look instead to an exemplarist animated community of inquiry principles based on defeasible-reasons-regulated processes. We argue that this approach epitomizes a more socially attuned, interdependently calibrated, true-to-life vice-reduction model. Our proposed model comprises four distinct yet complementary components: (1) positive exemplars of epistemic virtue (saints); (2) negative exemplars of epistemic vice (sinners); (3) direct teaching/instruction; and (4) cognitive apprenticeship. Positive exemplars give students role models to admire and emulate. Negative exemplars show how we are all human and that what is important about mistakes is that we learn from them and endeavor not to make them again. Direct teaching tackles epistemic vices head-on by means of using age and stage-appropriate stimuli (Tik Tok videos, Instagram videos, etc.) to unpack the deleterious effects of epistemic vice. Finally, cognitive apprenticeship uses the principles of modeling and expert-guided practice, where students learn via hands-on, real-world tasks to harness and enhance their inquiry processes, such as conceptual mapping, stress-testing reasons, anticipating objections, formulating alternative explanations, and scrutinizing the force of evidential claims.

Together these papers offer a theoretical elaboration of the problem of epistemic vice, as well as specific pedagogical advice for educators on how to counteract them. Needless to say, this project is of special relevance today.

查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
专题讨论会导言:认识论的恶习:超越圣人与罪人
完美的认识论代理人是不存在的。人是混乱的。我们会犯错;我们容易出错。我们的注意力有限,认知处理能力迟钝,人际交往能力稚嫩,记忆效率低下且不可靠。有时,我们难以摆脱自己的方式--变幻莫测的生活、人际关系和责任,无论是个人还是集体,都会让我们付出代价,尤其是在追求多巴胺、注意力分散的环境中。这些压力让我们无法成为最好的自己。更多的时候,我们不如我们应该成为的样子。具体来说,我们每个人在某种程度上都有智力缺陷,这是意料之中的。我们毕竟是人。缺陷是我们 DNA 中的编码。因此,我们有时会成为有缺陷的探究者--次优的或值得指责的认识论主体,这并不奇怪。偏见、非理性、迷信、封闭、认识论固化、故意无知、轻率、我行我素等等,都有可能成为我们的殖民地,并对我们高效获取、分享、生产和审核知识的能力,或进行负责任和有效探究的能力产生有害影响。所有这些都给我们留下了选择的余地。教育家们是应该根据在严格控制的实验室条件下获得的知识,来追求一种基于美德的另一个世界的卓越认识论,还是应该更深入地了解我们智力性格特征、态度和思维方式的缺陷性质、范围、特性和意义,以及它们是如何系统地(尽管并非一成不变地)阻碍我们获取知识的道路的?知识恶习是指那些有害的认识论性格特征、态度和思维模式,它们反映了我们不完美的认识论欲望,阻碍了我们成功的认识论追求。尽管不同学者对认识论恶习的性质有不同的理解,但目前主要有两种观点:动机主义和阻碍主义。2 前者从不完善的认识论动机的角度来描述认识论恶习,而后者则从后果主义的角度来理解认识论恶习:更具体地说,就是阻碍知识的获取、保留和传播。另一方面,恶性认识论者则从更真实的角度看待问题。他们着眼于我们思想上的缺陷,对腐朽的动机和有缺陷的知识分子性格特征是如何阻碍我们获得知识的进行了解释性说明。概括地说,他们的兴趣在于了解特定的思想恶习(包括个人和集体的智力缺陷)是如何、为何以及在何种情况下阻碍知识的获取、保留、审核和传播的。从词源学上讲,"恶习 "源于拉丁文 vitium,意为过失或缺陷。如果我们认真对待我们在认识论方面的责任,我们就必须对我们(个人和集体)未能以可信的方式获取、传递和审核知识时出现的问题做出正确的解释。如果我们在一定程度上可以控制自己的恶习,我们也需要指导如何减轻或克服这些恶习。根据这种近似的观点,认识论恶习可以被概念化为知识分子的性格缺陷、恶毒态度或腐朽的思维方式,它们系统地阻碍了知识的发展。由于性格特征在一定程度上解释了人们的所作所为,学者们坚持认为,认识论恶习至少在一定程度上解释了人们如何经常不能恰当地思考、推理、反思、探究或评估相关证据,以及强调检验相互竞争的主张的力度。无论是性格特征、态度还是思维方式,恶习首先是作为倾向性存在的。例如,溶解性就是一种处置。根据这种观点,性情是用从句条件式来表述的。说糖是可溶的,意味着如果把糖放在水里,它就会溶解。这样理解,处置对某些刺激事件或特定条件是敏感的。同时也是性格特征的认识恶习包括表现出某些感知、感觉、思维、推理和行为模式的倾向,这些模式会阻碍知识的获取、保存、审核或分享。 26 这导致米汉认为,认识论上的鼓励不仅无效,而且会适得其反,因为它们会导致认识论上的懒惰。对此,弗拉坦托尼奥的反驳认为,反复的 "点拨 "会给认识论主体带来持久的影响,而且与米汉对 "懒惰 "的担忧相反,"点拨 "不会绕过或阻碍一个人的推理能力和批判性思维。最后,弗拉坦托尼奥认为,认识论上的鼓励可能会在教育领域带来一些尚未开发的前景:格里-邓恩(Gerry Dunne)和阿尔基斯-科特索尼斯(Alkis Kotsonis)撰写的最后一篇文章《认识论恶习的改造:圣人与罪人的榜样主义》("Saints and Sinners Zetetic Exemplarism")探讨了改造认识论恶习的一系列教学可能性。我们认为,这种方法体现了一种更贴近社会、相互依存、经过校准的真实的减少恶习模式。我们提出的模式包括四个不同但互补的组成部分:(1) 认识美德的正面典范(圣人);(2) 认识恶习的反面典范(罪人);(3) 直接教学/指导;(4) 认知学徒制。正面典范给学生提供了钦佩和效仿的榜样。反面典型说明我们都是人,重要的是我们要从错误中吸取教训,努力不再犯错。直接教学通过使用与年龄和阶段相适应的刺激物(Tik Tok 视频、Instagram 视频等)来揭示认识论恶习的有害影响,从而迎头痛击认识论恶习。最后,认知学徒制利用建模和专家指导实践的原则,让学生通过亲身实践、真实世界的任务来学习,以利用和加强他们的探究过程,如概念图、压力测试理由、预测反对意见、制定替代解释以及仔细检查证据主张的力度。这些论文共同对认识论恶习问题进行了理论阐述,并就如何抵制认识论恶习为教育工作者提供了具体的教学建议。毋庸置疑,这一项目在今天具有特殊的现实意义。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
EDUCATIONAL THEORY
EDUCATIONAL THEORY EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH-
CiteScore
2.20
自引率
0.00%
发文量
19
期刊介绍: The general purposes of Educational Theory are to foster the continuing development of educational theory and to encourage wide and effective discussion of theoretical problems within the educational profession. In order to achieve these purposes, the journal is devoted to publishing scholarly articles and studies in the foundations of education, and in related disciplines outside the field of education, which contribute to the advancement of educational theory. It is the policy of the sponsoring organizations to maintain the journal as an open channel of communication and as an open forum for discussion.
期刊最新文献
Issue Information “Society is the present of teaching”: Teaching as a Phenomenon in Levinas's Unedited Lecture Notes The Consequences of Peirce's Theory of Agential Ideas for Qualitative Research Case-Based Reasoning in Educational Ethics: Phronēsis and Epistemic Blinders Education for Robust Self-Respect in an Unjust World†
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1