The right to death.

A. Flew
{"title":"The right to death.","authors":"A. Flew","doi":"10.5040/9781501345272.ch-003","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"I want to start with a phrase from the Declaration of Independence, but by the slightly indirect approach of quotation within a quotation. With his usual shrewd grasp of fundamentals, the lawyer Lincoln once wrote: “The authors of that notable instrument ... did not intend to declare all men equal in all respects. They did not mean to say that all men were equal in color, size, intellect, moral developments, or social capacity. They defined with tolerable distinctness in what respects they did consider all men created equal - equal in certain ‘unalienable rights, among which are life, liberty and the pursuit of happiness.’ ” It is perhaps tempting to digress to support and to labour the point that neither Lincoln nor the Founding Fathers believed: either that “at birth human infants, regardless of heredity, are as equal as Fords” or that some such repudiation of genetic fact is implied or presupposed by any insistence upon an equality of fundamental human rights. 1 But our present concern is with the actual prescriptive and proscriptive content of these particular norms. For us the crux is that they are all, in M. P. Golding’s terminology, option as opposed to welfare rights: the former forbid interference, within the spheres described, entitling everyone to act or not to act as they see fit; whereas the latter entitle everyone to be supplied with some good, by whom and at whose expense not normally being specified. 2 Hence, with that “peculiar felicity of expression” that led to his being given the drafting job, Thomas Jefferson spoke: not of rights to health, education, and welfare - and whatever else might be thought necessary to the achievement of happiness; but of rights to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness - it being up to you whether you do in fact pursue (and to the gods whether, if so, you capture) your prey. An option right is thus a right to be allowed, without interference, to do your own thing. A welfare right is a right to be supplied, by others, with something that is thought to be, and perhaps is, good for you, whether you actually want it or not. To show that the Founding Fathers were indeed thinking of option rather than welfare rights, it should here be sufficient to cite a passage from Blackstone, which has the further merit of indicating upon what general feature of our peculiarly human nature such fundamental rights must be grounded. From their first publication in 1765, his Commentaries on the Laws of England had a profound influence on all the common law jurisdictions in North America, an influence that continued well into the Federal period. Blackstone wrote: The absolute rights of man, considered as a free agent, endowed with discernment to know good from evil, and with the power of choosing those measures which appear to him to be most desirable, are usually summed up in one general appellation, and denominated the natural liberty of mankind ... The rights themselves ... will appear from what has been premised, to be no other, than that residuum of natural liberty, which is not required by the laws of society to be sacrificed to the public convenience; or else those civil privileges, which society has engaged to provide in lieu of the natural liberties so given up by individuals. 3","PeriodicalId":79889,"journal":{"name":"Frontiers in aging series","volume":"2 1","pages":"101-13"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2020-03-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"4","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Frontiers in aging series","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.5040/9781501345272.ch-003","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4

Abstract

I want to start with a phrase from the Declaration of Independence, but by the slightly indirect approach of quotation within a quotation. With his usual shrewd grasp of fundamentals, the lawyer Lincoln once wrote: “The authors of that notable instrument ... did not intend to declare all men equal in all respects. They did not mean to say that all men were equal in color, size, intellect, moral developments, or social capacity. They defined with tolerable distinctness in what respects they did consider all men created equal - equal in certain ‘unalienable rights, among which are life, liberty and the pursuit of happiness.’ ” It is perhaps tempting to digress to support and to labour the point that neither Lincoln nor the Founding Fathers believed: either that “at birth human infants, regardless of heredity, are as equal as Fords” or that some such repudiation of genetic fact is implied or presupposed by any insistence upon an equality of fundamental human rights. 1 But our present concern is with the actual prescriptive and proscriptive content of these particular norms. For us the crux is that they are all, in M. P. Golding’s terminology, option as opposed to welfare rights: the former forbid interference, within the spheres described, entitling everyone to act or not to act as they see fit; whereas the latter entitle everyone to be supplied with some good, by whom and at whose expense not normally being specified. 2 Hence, with that “peculiar felicity of expression” that led to his being given the drafting job, Thomas Jefferson spoke: not of rights to health, education, and welfare - and whatever else might be thought necessary to the achievement of happiness; but of rights to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness - it being up to you whether you do in fact pursue (and to the gods whether, if so, you capture) your prey. An option right is thus a right to be allowed, without interference, to do your own thing. A welfare right is a right to be supplied, by others, with something that is thought to be, and perhaps is, good for you, whether you actually want it or not. To show that the Founding Fathers were indeed thinking of option rather than welfare rights, it should here be sufficient to cite a passage from Blackstone, which has the further merit of indicating upon what general feature of our peculiarly human nature such fundamental rights must be grounded. From their first publication in 1765, his Commentaries on the Laws of England had a profound influence on all the common law jurisdictions in North America, an influence that continued well into the Federal period. Blackstone wrote: The absolute rights of man, considered as a free agent, endowed with discernment to know good from evil, and with the power of choosing those measures which appear to him to be most desirable, are usually summed up in one general appellation, and denominated the natural liberty of mankind ... The rights themselves ... will appear from what has been premised, to be no other, than that residuum of natural liberty, which is not required by the laws of society to be sacrificed to the public convenience; or else those civil privileges, which society has engaged to provide in lieu of the natural liberties so given up by individuals. 3
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
死亡的权利。
我想从《独立宣言》中的一句话开始,但是用了一种间接的方式,在引用中引用。律师林肯以他一贯的对基本原理的敏锐把握,曾经写道:“那件著名乐器的作者……我并不打算宣布所有人在所有方面都是平等的。他们并不是说所有人在肤色、身材、智力、道德发展或社会能力方面都是平等的。他们相当明确地界定了在哪些方面他们确实认为人人生而平等——在某些“不可剥夺的权利”上平等,其中包括生命、自由和追求幸福。这也许很容易偏离主题去支持和阐述林肯和开国元勋们都不相信的观点:要么是“人类婴儿出生时,无论遗传如何,都和福特一样平等”,要么是任何对基本人权平等的坚持都暗示或预设了一些对遗传事实的否定。但我们目前关注的是这些特定规范的实际规定性和禁止性内容。对我们来说,关键在于,用m·p·戈尔丁(m.p. Golding)的术语来说,它们都是与福利权利相对的选择权:前者在所描述的领域内禁止干涉,赋予每个人按照自己认为合适的方式行事或不行事的权利;而后者则使每个人都有权获得某种商品,而这种商品通常是由谁提供的,由谁支付的,通常是不明确的。因此,托马斯·杰斐逊以他那使他获得起草工作的“独特的表达方式”发言:不是健康、教育和福利的权利——以及任何其他可能被认为是实现幸福所必需的权利;但是关于生存权、自由权和追求幸福的权利——这取决于你是否真的去追求(如果是的话,你是否抓住了上帝)你的猎物。因此,选择权是一种被允许不受干涉地做自己事情的权利。福利权是一种由他人提供的,被认为对你有好处的东西的权利,不管你是否真的想要它。为了证明开国元勋们确实考虑的是选择权而不是福利权,这里引用布莱克斯通的一段话就足够了,这段话还有进一步的优点,它表明了这种基本权利必须建立在我们独特的人性的什么一般特征之上。自1765年首次出版以来,他的《英格兰法评注》对北美所有普通法管辖区产生了深远的影响,这种影响一直持续到联邦时期。布莱克斯通写道:人的绝对权利,被认为是一个自由的行动者,被赋予辨别善恶的能力,并有能力选择他认为最可取的措施,通常被概括为一个总称,并命名为人类的自然自由……权利本身……从所提出的前提看来,这只不过是自然自由的残余,社会法律不要求为了公众的便利而牺牲这种残余;或者是那些公民特权,这些特权是社会承诺提供的,以代替个人放弃的自然自由。3.
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
期刊最新文献
The right to death. Technical aids for the disabled as applied to gerontology. Technology and aging. The new frontier. Translations of technologies to meet needs of the elderly. An overview of issues in robotic and artificial intelligence applications for health and human service domains.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1