Toward a republican theory of secession

IF 1.1 3区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Journal of Social Philosophy Pub Date : 2022-05-18 DOI:10.1111/josp.12468
Lluis Perez-Lozano
{"title":"Toward a republican theory of secession","authors":"Lluis Perez-Lozano","doi":"10.1111/josp.12468","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Like most theories of democracy, democratic republicanism has usually taken for granted who the <i>demos</i> is. However, precisely one of the most frequent sources of political conflicts in contemporary history is the determination of its boundaries, particularly –though not only– in secession conflicts. This article aims to answer a related question: <i>what kind of right to secede from a modern democratic state</i>,<sup>1</sup> <i>if any, can be acknowledged from a democratic republican viewpoint</i>? By answering this question, I hope to make a contribution both to republican literature (in which secession has barely been analyzed) and also to the normative literature on secession (in which republicanism has very rarely been used as a normative framework).</p><p>The core tenet of the republican theory of secession developed here is the recognition of a non-unilateral<sup>2</sup> right of secession for any democratic secessionist community within a democratic state, coupled symmetrically with a non-unilateral right to territorial unity for that democratic host state. The rationale behind this theory is to deny both sides the power to impose their will without having to consider the interests and opinions of the other side; that is, to deny arbitrary power, which in republican terms is synonymous with domination. As we will see, this in turn minimizes the chances of permanent majorities and powerful minorities achieving arbitrary power in center-periphery conflicts.</p><p>This article does not discuss secession as a general phenomenon, but focuses particularly on secession conflicts where both secessionists and the host state (and the unionists within it) are peaceful<sup>3</sup> and democratic. The rationale behind this analytical choice is to minimize what we might call <i>normative noise</i>, i.e., normative issues that distract our attention from the ones that we initially intended to discuss. Modern democracies, however imperfect they may be, are the closest polities to democratic republican ideals that exist in our contemporary world. Thus, when neither the host state nor the potentially seceding territory are attempting to move away from this political model in a non-democratic direction, secession appears normatively “naked” in democratic-republican terms. I am not trying to find out whether democratic secessionists are legitimated in seceding from undemocratic states, nor whether democratic states are legitimated in suppressing an undemocratic secessionist attempt.</p><p>The article presents this theory over eight sections: (1) a review of current theories of right of secession, pointing out why republicanism can be a useful framework to overcome their weaknesses; (2) an overview of the main tenets of republicanism, explaining why (and how) republicanism must analyze secession conflicts as a type of factional conflicts; (3) the presentation of the normative core of my republican theory of secession, based on non-unilateralism; (4) the outline of a non-unilateralist framework for secession conflicts; (5) an outline of three problematic scenarios for the theory, and of the role that unilateral mechanisms can play in order to tackle one of them; (6) an exploration of the strengths and weaknesses of two possible institutional translations of this theory (constitutionalization and internationalization); (7) a discussion of some foreseeable criticisms of the theory; and (8) a summary of my conclusions.</p><p>For the purposes of this article, a <i>secessionist movement</i> is a group of people that seek secession for a broader group of people, namely the <i>target group</i>. When secessionists are a clear majority within the target group, this group qualifies as a <i>secessionist community</i>. While every single member of a secessionist movement is secessionist, this is not true of secessionist communities. And when a secessionist community seeks to establish a modern democratic state through democratically acceptable means, it qualifies as a <i>democratic secessionist community</i>.</p><p>Unilateral secession is often regarded as “the principal focus of interest for theorists of secession” (Pavkovic &amp; Radan, <span>2007</span>, 200–201). Theories of right of secession (TRS) are usually classified into three different categories depending on who they deem entitled to (unilateral) secession: territorially concentrated groups, i.e., <i>plebiscitarianism</i> (Beran, <span>1984</span>; Copp, <span>1998</span>; Lefkowitz, <span>2008</span>; Philpott, <span>1998</span>; Wellman, <span>2005</span>); culturally encompassing groups, i.e., <i>ascriptivism</i> (Margalit &amp; Raz, <span>1990</span>; Miller, <span>1997</span>); or groups that are unjustly and intolerably harmed by the state, particularly (although not necessarily only) in terms of basic human rights, i.e., <i>remedialism</i> (Birch, <span>1984</span>; Brilmayer, <span>1991</span>; Buchanan, <span>1991</span>, <span>2007</span>; Christiano, <span>2006</span>; Patten, <span>2002</span>).</p><p>The first two categories of TRS conceive secession as a <i>primary right</i>, i.e., a right to which some groups of people are entitled a priori, with no need to justify their decision; the categories only differ regarding the definition of which people(s) are entitled to this primary right. Primary right TRS are usually criticized as being an open door to: (1) <i>secessio</i> ad infinitum, i.e., unending recursive secessions, leading to anarchy, and to (2) the <i>blackmail threat</i>, i.e., the risk of giving privileged minorities (e.g., wealthy ones) the power to threaten the whole polity. In addition, ascriptivism can be further criticized for: (3) its <i>weak operationalization</i>: it is difficult to give an empirically operational definition of the ascriptive features that a group of people must share in order to be considered a “culturally encompassing group”; and (4) the <i>threat of exclusion</i> it poses: those who live in the territory of the ascriptive group that is entitled to secession, but who do not share its ascriptive features, might come to be seen as second-class citizens, and eventually be excluded from the decision on secession, or even from citizenship altogether.<sup>4</sup></p><p>Due to these weaknesses, many scholars espouse some version of remedialism, which regards secession as a last resort in the face of certain persistent injustices. What these injustices are is a matter of discussion, but remedialists generally agree on some basic injustices, such as massive violations of basic human rights. However, remedial theories have been criticized as unfairly biased toward the status quo,<sup>5</sup> since they assume the legitimacy of current boundaries and put the burden of proof on secessionists. This is problematic since most boundaries are the result of historical episodes (e.g., wars) that are far from reflecting the democratic values that remedial theories rest upon. Remedialism suggests an answer to this objection: as long as states are reasonably just, boundaries are irrelevant. However, in a world of states, falling between terribly oppressed minorities and privileged, blackmailing ones, there are many intermediate cases of permanent minorities,<sup>6</sup> which are usually the weak sides in persistent controversies on certain issues related to state or nation-building (e.g., language regulations, or the territorial structure of political or economic institutions).<sup>7</sup> It seems unfair to assume that they must simply endure this condition because of a war lost in the distant past, for instance.</p><p>Thus, it seems that all current TRS are in some way criticized for being unfairly or dangerously biased toward either unionists or secessionists. I think that the reason behind this common weakness is that all current TRS choose an a priori winner in secession conflicts, that is entitled to the disputed territory unless X. Remedialists make this choice by means of a justice-based view of legitimacy: as long as a state is reasonably just, secession is unjustified, and therefore illegitimate. Plebiscitarian and ascriptive theories, on the other hand, make the choice by means of theories of legitimacy that are not based (or not based exclusively) on justice. In order to further examine their common weakness, I shall briefly explore this point.</p><p>It is important to distinguish between justice and legitimacy. Justice is about “the question of what should be done by political institutions or by the law; that is, what the content of political and legal decisions should be,” while legitimacy is about “the question of who should make the political and legal decisions that serve to approximate this ideal of justice, and how they should do it” (Martí, <span>2017</span>, 731). While this definition includes the “who” as a question of legitimacy, I think that when we look at concrete political conflicts, justice and legitimacy point toward two different “whos”: the people who we would like to see ruling (because we share their view of justice) may not be the people who we consider legitimated to rule. For instance, we may share a Rawlsian view of justice and, therefore, tend to support social-democratic governments; while at the same time, we can regard a government with a Nozickian libertarian agenda as legitimate, as long as it has won power through means we regard as legitimate (e.g., through free and fair multi-party elections).</p><p>I understand the question “who is legitimately entitled to secede?” as an aspect of the “who is legitimately entitled to rule?” question. As we have seen, remedialists establish a direct connection between the “whos” of justice and legitimacy: those who rule justly are entitled to rule, and for the same reason, those who are ruled unjustly are entitled to separate themselves from that unjust rule. However, the problem with establishing a direct connection between justice and legitimacy is that it makes political conflicts highly difficult to deal with. We all tend to have very different ideas regarding justice, and even on the practical implications of those ideas (especially when our interests are at stake). This is, precisely, one of the main reasons why we need governments and laws, so that we have someone to arbitrate such differences. But that someone is, in the end, someone like us, and if we establish that the person who is more just (or who has the best views on justice) is the person who should rule, then we will just be going round in circles and not tackling the problem. This is why political communities need procedures and institutions that enable them to choose governments and make laws, in a manner that can be recognized as legitimate even by those who think that those governments and laws are somehow unjust. In other words: political communities need procedures and institutions in order to manage political conflicts (including those involving conflicting ideas of justice) in a legitimate way.</p><p>Therefore, I think that plebiscitarian and ascriptive theorists are right not to establish a direct connection between legitimacy and justice regarding secessionist claims. The problem, however, is that they emphasize the “who” of legitimacy over the “how.” In my opinion, the “how” is the constitutive point of legitimacy, while the “who” of legitimacy is only derivative. When the legitimate “how” (e.g., free and fair elections in country X) settles the question on the legitimacy of “who” (e.g., who is the legitimate person to hold executive power in X), polities enjoy a great deal of internal and external legitimizations, making it easier to tackle political conflicts without resorting to a “might makes right” logic. When, conversely, there is not a legitimate “how” to decide the legitimate “who,” then might does indeed make right. This is the nemesis of freedom that was the case of wars of succession in monarchies. And nowadays, it is also the case of most secession conflicts.</p><p>For these reasons, rather than deciding who is right in secession conflicts, a TRS should first and foremost be a theory that sets out a legitimate institutional framework for secession conflicts. It needs to be a theory that could be placed within a turn that is now underway in the literature: rather than finding an a priori holder of a unilateral right to secession, several authors are delineating processes and mechanisms by which secession conflicts should be managed (e.g., Sanjaume-Calvet, <span>2019</span>); this even includes authors who establish a very close connection between justice and legitimacy (e.g., Bossacoma Busquets, <span>2020</span>). I will argue that democratic republicanism can provide valuable tools for developing such a theory.</p><p>This article is based on the contemporary reconstruction of the republican tradition developed by Pettit (<span>1997</span>), building on the historiographic work of Skinner (<span>1998</span>); this is arguably the mainstream in current republican literature. According to this reconstruction, republicanism: (1) stands for freedom as non-domination; (2) understands domination as the arbitrary power of the individual or group X over the individual or group Y, i.e., as a power that can be exercised by X over Y without having to consider Y's interests and opinions (Pettit, <span>1997</span>, 35); (3) argues that, in order to promote republican freedom, private sources of power must be controlled and dispersed by the state; (4) argues that, in order to prevent the state from itself becoming a dominator, it must be organized as a constitutional republic,<sup>8</sup> with its own powers being dispersed and kept in check by civic virtue and the rule of law; and (5) argues that civic virtue and freedom are mutually dependent. In addition, democratic republicans, as opposed to oligarchic ones, (6) endeavor for republican freedom to include as many people as possible (Pettit, <span>1997</span>, 95–96). Thus, <i>domination</i> and <i>exclusion</i>, as defined here, are the main concerns of democratic republicanism.</p><p>Considered in this way, republicanism encompasses canonical authors such as Aristotle, Cicero, Machiavelli, Spinoza, Madison or Wollstonecraft, to name but a few; it is, therefore, a long tradition of political thought, focused on justice as well as on legitimacy (Pettit, <span>2012</span>, 18–19), not only in the realm of domestic politics but also in that of international relations (Onuf, <span>1998</span>). Concerning this last value, a common topic in republican thought is the importance (and the danger) of factional conflicts when it comes to designing non-dominating (therefore, legitimate) political institutions. To republicans, political institutions should manage political conflicts in such a way that no contending faction can gain absolute (therefore, arbitrary) power over the others. The dispersion of public power is not only needed to guard against potential abuses by public officers, but also to guard against the risk of a factional takeover. Republican theorists have also applied this concern regarding balance of power to international relations (Deudney, <span>2008</span>). Republicanism, however, has not concerned itself with designing institutions that are able to manage secession conflicts, in which the contending factions neither seek to win power <i>within</i> a state, nor to win power <i>for</i> a state, but either to <i>become</i> a state formed out of another one (secessionism), or to prevent another group doing so (unionism).</p><p>Even authors with an affinity to republicanism, such as Miller (<span>2008</span>) or Weinstock &amp; Nadeau (<span>2004</span>), have not used republican concepts and principles in their works on secession (Miller, <span>1997</span>; Weinstock, <span>2000</span>, <span>2001</span>). And when scholars have occasionally worked on secession from a republican point of view, they often have done so in a somewhat exploratory way (McGarry &amp; Moore, <span>2011</span>), usually as a secondary issue within broader works on nationalism (Ovejero, <span>2006</span>, 81), international law (Sellers, <span>2006</span>, 158–66), or self-determination generally (Klabbers, <span>2006</span>). Other scholars, such as Caminal (<span>2007</span>) or Young (<span>2005</span>), have examined the relationship between republicanism and self-determination, but these works have focused on multinational federalism, rather than on secession. Only Catala (<span>2017</span>) has outlined some ethical–political duties of potentially secessionist groups, concerning non-domination, in one particular area (distributive justice). Thus, there is much work yet to be done in formulating a democratic republican TRS.</p><p>In my view, as I have already noted, a secession conflict can be understood as a sort of factional conflict. It is usually the ultimate expression of a conflict between a permanent central majority and a permanent peripheral minority, both of them defined along the lines of permanent disagreements on how the state should be conceived and organized in terms of <i>economy</i> (i.e., its territorial organization), <i>territory</i> (i.e., the territorial distribution of political power) and <i>identity</i>.<sup>9</sup> In this regard, a secession conflict may imply four different threats in democratic republican terms.</p><p>The first one is the threat of <i>exclusion</i>, i.e., the risk that some people who would be under the authority of the seceding polity may be excluded from deciding on the matter of secession, or even from citizenship of the polity altogether. This threat, in my opinion, is one of the darkest points of ascriptive theories: if the group with a right to secede is one defined by certain objective traits, then those who do not share these traits may be excluded from the process of deciding on secession; in fact, they may even be excluded from becoming citizens of the new state, since they are not part of “the people.”</p><p>The second threat is <i>domination by blackmailing minorities</i>: in the case of being capable of achieving unilateral secession at will, an X minority which happened to be particularly powerful (e.g., because of its wealth) would be in a position to blackmail<sup>10</sup> the Y citizenship of the rest of the polity,<sup>11</sup> with no need to consider Y's interests and opinions (thus, exercising arbitrary power over Y). This is a threat that affects ascriptive TRS, but especially plebiscitarian ones, for they are highly permissive about groups of people unilaterally seceding at will.</p><p>These two threats of exclusion and blackmail have led republican scholars like Ovejero (<span>2006</span>, 81) or Sellers (<span>2006</span>, 25) to embrace remedialism. I regard remedialism, however, as ill-prepared to handle a third threat, that of <i>arbitrary permanent majorities</i>: by stating that secessionists must bear the burden of proof, remedialism gives the high ground to permanent majorities, who may arbitrarily decide what degree of autonomy, recognition, or economic promotion they will grant to permanent minorities.</p><p>This third threat requires a little more explanation, since it may be confused with the “tough luck” attitude proffered to, say, the loser of a democratic election. For a polity to protect the republican freedom of its members, its institutions should be designed in a manner to require them to track the interests and opinions of the people. Since unanimity is a rarity (and a unanimity rule would thus be biased toward the status quo), democratic republicanism typically defends majority rule plus counter-majoritarian checks. The goal of these checks (in democratic republican terms) is not only to protect minorities, but to allow them to intervene in public debates and, therefore, to be able to persuade people and eventually become majorities themselves. Thus, in a healthy democracy, we can expect to be sometimes in a majority and sometimes in a minority. If, for instance, I am a progressive, I will sometimes be disappointed by a conservative win in a vote, and I will sometimes be pleased by a progressive victory (or vice versa, if I am a conservative). This easily changeable nature of majorities makes majority rule plus counter-majority checks the least imperfect way to force governments to track the interests and opinions of all citizens.</p><p>However, in center-periphery conflicts about economy, territory, and identity, the majorities hardly ever change; thus, it is easy to govern the polity without much regard for the interests and opinions of permanent minorities, even if their members are individually equipped with full democratic rights. For instance, a permanent linguistic majority can decide, by the sheer force of demographic numbers but through strictly democratic procedures, to remove the teaching of the indigenous language of a permanent minority from public education. This does not mean that they will do it, but that they <i>are able</i> to do it. And in republican terms, this is a dominating stance, i.e., a stance of arbitrary power.</p><p>There are two remedialist strategies that have been developed in order to overcome this threat posed by arbitrary permanent majorities: (1) the defense of reasonable degrees of intrastate autonomy (Buchanan, <span>2007</span>, 401–24); and (2) the inclusion, within the catalog of “just causes” for secession, of insufficient self-government, discriminatory redistribution, and/or failure of recognition (Bauböck, <span>2000</span>; Christiano, <span>2006</span>; Patten, <span>2002</span>; Seymour, <span>2007</span>). However, neither of these strategies actually overcomes the threat of arbitrary permanent majorities. What both strategies are actually saying is that the host state must accept reasonable settlements of center-periphery conflicts, without understanding that the definition of a “reasonable settlement” for a center-periphery conflict is precisely the very subject of that conflict. Moreover, this is a highly context-dependent matter that can only be discussed on a case-by-case basis. And in each case, the weak side in the conflict will usually be the peripheral permanent minority. So both strategies merely bounce around the threat they are trying to overcome.</p><p>It seems, therefore, that the (pro-secessionist or pro-unionist) bias of these TRS tends to open the door to exclusion and/or domination (either by permanent majorities or by permanent minorities). To make things worse, due to their bias toward one of the two sides, none of these TRS is likely to be accepted by the other side, thus leading to the fourth threat for democratic republican goals: <i>instability</i>, i.e., inappropriate handling of secession conflicts (including not handling them at all) is likely to promote instability, eventually triggering exclusion and/or domination. I have developed this republican critique of current TRS elsewhere (Perez-Lozano, <span>2021b</span>). In my view, in order to overcome all four threats, democratic republicanism needs a new TRS, based on a non-unilateralist logic. I will devote the next section to developing this point.</p><p>I think that a democratic republican TRS should lean toward non-unilateral mechanisms, without completely discarding unilateral ones. This non-unilateralist logic is aimed at allowing both secessionists and the host state to pursue their respective goals; while, at the same time, forcing them to take the interests and opinions of the other side into account, which is tantamount to forcing permanent majorities and permanent minorities, in center-periphery conflicts, to take each other's interests and opinions into account. We can see this point in the Quebec Secession Reference (Supreme Court of Canada, <span>1998</span>), and in how it was received by the Canadian government and the Quebec secessionists.</p><p>The Reference ruled out two unilateralist positions in the Quebec secession conflict: it denied Quebec the right to unilateral secession, either within the Canadian constitution or international law; but at the same time, it acknowledged that the Canadian government had the constitutional duty to negotiate with a secessionist Quebecer government in good faith, if a clear majority of Quebecers answered “yes” to a clear question about secession. The reference was welcomed by both the Canadian government and by the Quebec secessionists, and the delighted reaction of the latter to it was, in fact, quite telling.</p><p>We can see why by asking a counterfactual question: what would have happened if the Reference had not included Ottawa's obligation to negotiate in the case of a “Yes” victory? Initially, it would appear that the secession of Quebec would have been impossible, at least in legal terms. However, this is not exactly true: before the Court issued the Reference, Canadian federalists had repeatedly asserted that they did not want to retain Quebec within Canada against the will of Quebecers, but to remove the threat of unilateral secession (Sauvegau et al., <span>2006</span>, 108). But then, what difference did the Reference make? Why was it so gladly received by the same Quebec secessionists who had initially been so reluctant for the Court to have a role in the matter (Sauvegau et al., <span>2006</span>, 105–107)?</p><p>But by forbidding each side in the conflict to pursue its own goals without taking into account the interests and views of the other side, the Quebec Secession Reference minimized the chances of domination in both directions (Perez-Lozano, <span>2021a</span>). And, provided that this framework, interpreted in this way, appears to be fair and reasonable to both sides, it would be difficult for either of them to unilaterally break with it while presenting itself as a reasonable and fair player in the face of public opinion, both domestic or international; this would be a cost in terms of political legitimacy and is briefly pointed out in the Reference itself (272–273).</p><p>Republicanism aims to develop these kinds of schemes in order to obtain these kinds of results. It aims to channel deep political conflicts toward an institutional framework in which (1) all interested parties have a genuine say, and are thus protected from domination and (2) as a result, all of them legitimize the framework, therefore imposing high political costs onto anyone tempted to break away from it unilaterally. Thus, republican freedom and political stability go hand in hand. In secession conflicts within modern democracies, this job could be done, in my view, by a framework grounded in a non-unilateralist logic similar to that of the Quebec Secession Reference. In the next section, I outline what this framework could look like.</p><p>In my view, a democratic republican framework for secession conflicts should be based on three pillars: (1) a <i>non-unilateral</i> right<sup>12</sup> of secession for any democratic secessionist community, coupled with a <i>non-unilateral</i> right to territorial unity for its democratic host state; (2) a <i>unilateral</i> right of secession for extreme cases in which democratic secessionist communities are dealing with an oppressive,<sup>13</sup> unilateralist, or failed state; and (3) a <i>unilateral</i> right to territorial unity for extreme cases in which democratic host states are dealing with an oppressive, unilateralist, or failed secessionist community.</p><p>The first of these three pillars would take the form of a non-unilateral framework to manage secession conflicts, which would basically reflect the elements drawn up in the Quebec Secession Reference: (1) a <i>democratic</i> (therefore, <i>inclusive</i>) <i>referendum</i> among the members of the secessionist target group, with a clear question concerning secession, in order to find out whether they actually are a secessionist community; and (2) in the case of a clear “yes” victory, a <i>negotiation in good faith</i> between the host state and the secessionist community. While this framework offers the secessionist community the (non-unilateral) right to pursue secession, it also gives the host state the (non-unilateral) right to defend its territorial unity. Thus, the referendum will have both epistemic and normative values: it will find out whether the target group is a secessionist community; and (if it is) it will create both: (1) a mandate for its regional government and/or representatives to negotiate secession, in good faith, with the host state, and (2) an obligation for the host state to negotiate with them in good faith.</p><p>Of course, this raises the question of who should arbitrate such a negotiation, and the framework as a whole; we will come to that in section 6. For now, in order to reach a full understanding of how this non-unilateral right of secession would look, we must discuss the following: (a) <i>what is a clear question?</i>; (b) <i>how can a referendum be inclusive?</i>; (c) <i>what is a clear “yes” majority?</i>; and (d) <i>how would a “negotiation in good faith” between unionists and secessionists look?</i></p><p>Concerning the referendum, firstly, the question on secession must be <i>clear</i>. This, at least in theoretical terms, is not a challenge: for external observers, it will be uncontroversial to accept that the question in the 2014 Scottish referendum was clear, while the question in the 1980 Quebec referendum was not.<sup>14</sup> Secondly, the referendum should be <i>inclusive</i>, and the “yes” majority should be <i>clear</i> in order to make sure that we are talking about a secessionist community. The <i>inclusiveness</i> of the referendum has to do with “who” should vote in order for it to be considered a legitimate vote; the <i>clearness</i> of the majority has to do with “how many” should vote “yes” in order to determine that we are indeed dealing with a democratic secessionist community.</p><p>The “who” of the vote has two dimensions: <i>territorial</i> (which territory is potentially seceding in case of a “yes” victory) and <i>human</i> (who should vote in the referendum). Concerning the territorial dimension, I think it is reasonable to let secessionists define the territory that will potentially secede, and, therefore, where the referendum should be held. This rule should, however, have a precondition: it must be based on a broad consensus throughout that territory. This has some problematic implications that I will discuss in section 5; for now, let us just assume that in the territory drawn out by secessionists for a referendum there exists such a consensus. The human dimension, however, should not be decided by the secessionists, for obvious reasons concerning the threat of exclusion. In a vote on the creation of a new state, the inclusive nature of democratic republicanism requires, a priori, the right of all those who would be under the authority of that state to vote. To me, this includes, at least, all citizens residing in that territory, without necessarily excluding other possible groups depending on the specific case.<sup>15</sup></p><p>Concerning the clarity of the “yes” majority (the “how many”), the question is: <i>what turnout, and how much support for the “yes” option, is enough in order to consider that there has been a clear secessionist victory?</i> In my view, this problem is highly context-dependent. However, I think that we can delineate two guiding criteria. In the first place, <i>the more historically continuous the identity of the target group as a political community</i>, <i>the lower the thresholds should be</i>. And secondly: <i>the more inclusive and cohesive (not necessarily uniform) the target group is, the lower the thresholds should be</i>. According to these two criteria, the threshold for a “yes” victory in Padania and in the Bosniak-Croat Federation of Bosnia and Herzegovina, respectively, should be higher than in Scotland. The rationale behind these criteria is that high vote thresholds in secessionist referenda are mainly justified as an instrument against: (1) <i>decisions based on volatile passions</i> (which in “recently invented peoples” like Padania can be supposed, ceteris paribus, to play a higher role in secessionism than in “historically consistent peoples” like Scotland); and (2) <i>the oppression of minorities</i> (which can be particularly threatening in cases of societies divided by deep-seated, long-standing ethnic rivalries).</p><p>These two criteria can be included within one single principle: <i>in a secession referendum, the more the secessionist target group can be considered a people (in terms of history, inclusion and cohesion), the lower the threshold for a clear “yes” victory should be</i>. I call this the <i>people clarity principle</i>. This might seem to contradict something that my approach to secession is based on: that there is not one clear, unequivocal and unbiased definition on what a “people” is. However, this is not the case. Unlike current TRS, the people clarity principle is not implicitly based on a clear-cut definition of what a “people” is; instead, it is formulated as a matter of degree, since it aims to capture an intuition that in fact arises as a matter of degree: despite the lack of a clear, unequivocal and unbiased definition of what “a people” (or “a nation”) is, it is nevertheless reasonable to be skeptical of the authenticity of a “people” whose identity was practically formed from scratch a few decades earlier, or of the capacity of a deeply divided society to form a decent state. The people clarity principle does not deny them a path to secession, but only asks them for further proof of the seriousness and decency of their secessionist aspirations.</p><p>One last problem is who should be able to call the referendum. In my view, it should ideally be called by an autonomous democratic legislature and/or executive that represents the target group; this is classically the case in target groups organized as autonomous units within federal or regional modern democratic states. However, this will not always be the case, because the target group may belong to a unitary state. Provided that the host state has repeatedly ignored claims for decentralization, the target group should provide itself with some kind of representative institution in order to call a secession referendum if it so wishes. In addition, secessionists should have clear democratic legitimacy in order to call the referendum; this means, of course, that they should first be a clear majority in the autonomous legislature and/or executive. But they should also have had an enduring number of elected officials over time, so that we can be sure that secessionism has firm roots, rather than being just a fleeting passion. In its practical application, this condition should be softer or stricter in compliance with the people clarity principle.</p><p>Let us now assume that a secession referendum has been held in a territory; that it has been held in compliance with the requirements I have just described, and that it has resulted in a clear “yes” victory. If this result did not lead to any consequences occurring, the target group would be vulnerable to arbitrary permanent majorities. If that result, on the other hand, were to lead to unilateral secession, this would make the host state vulnerable to blackmailing minorities. From this point onwards, in order to avoid both extremes, both sides would have an obligation to negotiate <i>in good faith</i>. I think we can state that <i>two actors negotiate in good faith when both pursue their own agendas while, at the same time, acknowledging each other's legitimate interests, and trying to attend them in a reasonable manner</i>. For instance: if the potentially seceding territory contains a natural resource that happens to be crucial for the host state's economy, neither part should claim absolute control over the resource a priori; instead, they should seek some kind of agreement in order to have an equitable share in administering and benefiting from the resource.</p><p>The expectation that a regional minority could hold a secession referendum is a check against arbitrary permanent majorities. On the other hand, the expectation that a negotiation in good faith should take place after a “yes” victory is a check against blackmailing minorities: it does not make much sense to threaten the host state with secession in order to fulfill unreasonable demands if the only way to reach secession is through a reasonable negotiation with that host state. However, up until now an important question about this institutional framework has remained unanswered: should the negotiation process address secession and its details? Or should it also include the possibility of a third way between secession and the status quo (e.g., a decentralization agreement)?</p><p>The key point here is how the host state regards this negotiation, since it could take two stances: (1) to only negotiate the terms of secession; and (2) to offer and negotiate a unity agreement that is able to satisfy the secessionist community's aspirations within the host state, so that it ceases to be secessionist in the first place. In the first case, the problem disappears; whereas in the second case, we face a dilemma. In my view, at this point, we should recall the symmetry between the secessionist community's non-unilateral right of secession, on the one hand, and on the other, the host state's non-unilateral right to territorial unity. Applied to the negotiation, this means it should enable both parts to pursue their agendas, and the final agreement should reflect their legitimate interests. If the host state takes the second stance, this will mean that it wants to make a last push for territorial unity through negotiation.</p><p>One obvious risk posed by this approach is the possibility of reaching a stalemate, in which the host state and the secessionist community, with neither being particularly unreasonable, are nevertheless both very reluctant to give up their respective initial goals. One way to handle this risk would be to adopt an iterative approach to this negotiation process, intermingling it with other democratic procedures in order to unblock negotiations. For instance, if the host state offers further autonomy in exchange for maintaining the state's unity, and neither the secessionist representatives are willing to accept it, nor the host state willing to withdraw it (and accept secession), then a new referendum could be held in the secessionist community; in this new referendum, voters would be able to express whether they still prefer secession or if they would rather accept what the host state is proposing. The result, especially if it is very clear, should be taken into account in order to reach a final agreement. The more steadfast and constant the secessionist community happens to appear in its preference for secession, the less reasonable it would be for the host state to negotiate anything but secession.</p><p>Related to this, a “no” victory also poses a question: should the secessionist government that has called the referendum have the power to call another one? In my view, allowing secessionists to call as many referendums as they want whenever they want will place the host state under the threat of blackmailing minorities; while forbidding a new referendum on the matter will put the secessionist target group under the threat of arbitrary permanent majorities. Thus, it seems in tune with this theory to allow secessionist governments to call for a new referendum after a “no” vote, but only after a cooling down period. The length of this period needs to be settled case by case, so again, the existence of an arbiter becomes important; and it should be settled before the first referendum takes place, so that voters can take it into account before making their decision.</p><p>For the sake of prudence, we should acknowledge that when this general scheme is actually applied to each concrete case, even if it happens to solve all the aforementioned problems, it might encounter three further problematic scenarios, when: (1) one part of the territory proposed by secessionists as potentially seceding is not part of the political unit in which the secessionist movement holds the democratic power to call for a referendum (e.g., Navarre in the case of an hypothetical secession referendum in the Basque Country); (2) one identifiable part of the territory proposed by secessionists as potentially seceding is, in fact, inhabited by a majority of people who oppose secession (e.g., the indigenous-populated parts of Northern Quebec); and (3) one of the two factions of the conflict explicitly rejects this entire non-unilateralist scheme. Concerning the <i>first scenario</i>, I think it would be reasonable not to include the territory in the secession referendum unless the inhabitants of that territory decide to be included by democratic means.<sup>16</sup></p><p>The <i>second scenario</i> can be handled, I think, by simply applying the very same scheme of non-unilateral secession. The application of this scheme to this “internal secession” would be justified on the same democratic republican grounds that justified its application to the “external” secession scenario.<sup>17</sup> However, I think that we must divide this “internal secession” scenario into two further sub-scenarios: (2.1) a majority of the sub-territory's population wants to secede from the broader territory; (2.2) a majority of the sub-territory's population wants to secede from the broader territory <i>if the broader territory happens to secede from the host state</i>. I think that, ceteris paribus, the clarity threshold for a “yes” majority should be higher in the second sub-scenario than in the first one. The rationale behind this consideration is the people clarity principle: an “internally secessionist” will that is independent of the potential secession of the broader territory shows a stronger identity on the part of the sub-territory's population as a people than if they only wanted to “internally secede” in the case of the broader territory seceding from the host state.</p><p>Finally, the <i>third scenario</i> implies that one of the two actors is attempting to unilaterally impose its agenda. In the case of the democratic host state, I think that this is only justified when: (1) secession implies a serious risk of outright oppression of minorities inhabiting the potentially seceding territory (e.g., ethnic cleansing); (2) the target group would be, beyond any reasonable doubt, a failed secessionist community, i.e., incapable of establishing a functional sovereign state; or (3) the secessionists are clearly attempting to secede unilaterally in the first place. Symmetrically, unilateral secession by a democratic secessionist community would only be justified when: (1) there is outright oppression being exercised by the host state (in the same aforementioned terms); (2) the host state is a failed one; or (3) the host state is clearly intending to unilaterally maintain its territorial unity and suppress a secession attempt in the first place. Thus, the conditions for having a right to act unilaterally would be symmetrical for both factions: they would only have this right if the opposing faction happened to be <i>oppressive</i>, <i>failed</i> or already <i>unilateralist</i>.</p><p>Here, it should be recalled that this non-unilateralist scheme leaves many unanswered questions when it comes to applying it to each concrete case. To point out but a few: (1) should only resident citizens vote on the referendum, or should we include other groups (e.g., immigrants or the secessionist community's diaspora)?; (2) what should be the threshold for a clear “yes” majority?; (3) in the case of a clear “yes” victory, how can it be decided whether the host state and the secessionist community are actually negotiating in good faith?; (4) how can it be determined whether the host state or the secessionist community are actually experiencing any of the scenarios that justify them acting unilaterally?</p><p>The answers to these questions would inevitably be context-dependent. Thus, we need to determine <i>who</i> should answer them: i.e., who should be the arbiter of the whole process, and under what legal and political framework that body should act. There are two possible forms of arbitration: (1) constitutional; and (2) international. Concerning the first one, it is usually assumed that “non-unilateral” and “constitutional” secession are synonymous (Buchanan, <span>2007</span>, 338–39). Indeed, the possibility of a constitutional right of secession has attracted the attention of different scholars, either to endorse it (Corlett, <span>1998</span>; Jovanovic, <span>2007</span>; Norman, <span>2003</span>; Weinstock, <span>2000</span>, <span>2001</span>), or to reject it (Aronovitch, <span>2006</span>; Sunstein, <span>1991</span>, <span>2001</span>), but up until now no analysis of the matter has been carried out from the point of view of democratic republicanism.</p><p>The introduction of this constitutional right would imply that the arbiter of this non-unilateralist framework could be either a constitutionally sanctioned specialized agency, or the institution charged, in each state, with the task of constitutional review, i.e., the host state legislature, its supreme court or its constitutional court, depending on the case. In my view, this raises a problem: a constitutional right of secession, while promising in terms of minimizing domination and exclusion, will always be limited by the fact that the arbiter of such procedure will be, in the end, one of the powers belonging to the host state; that is, a power belonging to one of the conflicting factions. That does not mean that this power will necessarily be unable to be reasonably impartial (as the Quebec Secession Reference shows), but nevertheless, in terms of legitimacy, this problem stands.</p><p>However, the synonymizing of “constitutional” and “non-unilateral” secession, while common in the literature, is doubtful. I think there is a second possible institutional translation of this republican TRS: its non-unilateralist principles should be taken up within the international system, through a series of deliberations and agreements (from joint declarations to treaties) between democratic states, as well as between them and internationally relevant democratic actors (from sub-state secessionist governments to international organizations or NGOs). This would outline an institutional framework for a non-unilateralist management of secession political conflicts. Again, the arbiter in this framework could either be a specialized agency, or the institutions charged with monitoring the lawfulness of the international system (particularly, the International Court of Justice).<sup>18</sup></p><p>To embed this non-unilateralist framework within the international system would transform it into a <i>multilateralist</i> framework. This would be in tune with the fact that, in their contributions to International Thought, current republican scholars working within Pettit's paradigm usually stand for a combination of: (1) promoting democratic regimes and (2) avoiding the undesireable extremes of anarchy and hierarchy through international organizations and law, rather than through the formation of a world state rendered unfeasible and/or undesirable (Besson, <span>2009</span>; Cheneval, <span>2009</span>; Deudney, <span>2008</span>; Pettit, <span>2010</span>, <span>2016</span>; Slaughter, <span>2005</span>). Cheneval uses the term <i>multilateralism</i> to label this middle ground between international anarchy and a world state. According to him, an institution is multilateral (as opposed to bilateral or unilateral) “if it follows generalized behaviour principles and implies elements of creation of common law and collective action by more than two states” (Cheneval, <span>2009</span>, 246). The specificity of republican multilateralism lies in the fact that “the Member States of the process adhere to republican principles and strive at a more perfect realization of republican principles via the multilateral institutions they adhere to” (Cheneval, <span>2009</span>, 246).</p><p>There are two important assumptions that underlie these republican proposals for a multilateral international order: (1) the existence of independent states; and (2) that humankind is not willing to merge them into a world state. However, there has been little reflection on the legitimacy of the borders of these states. And among the few international republican theorists who have dealt with secession, an unjustified bias for the existing borders tends to be the norm.<sup>19</sup></p><p>Since international law is made by states, it could be argued that, in the end, we cannot expect an international arbiter to actually be more impartial than a constitutional domestic arbiter. It is true that it is not a perfect solution. But while international law is law created by all states, the parties involved in one given secession conflict are not all states against one given secessionist community, but one given state against one given secessionist community. So it seems reasonable to expect that an international arbitration body would be more trusted, by secessionists, to be an impartial arbiter without, nevertheless, being regarded as partial by the host state. In a way, the gain would be similar to that achieved by the creation of international courts of human rights: it is true that they are created by the same states that are expected to be monitored by them. And yet, they are usually a last line of defense against human rights abuses perpetrated by one concrete state or another.</p><p>So it seems that an optimal institutional translation of this republican TRS would be an international, multilateralist framework to manage secession conflicts. But if the constitutional translation would be problematic because of the risk of a partial arbiter, the international translation would be problematic because it is highly ambitious: states, even democratic ones, tend to be highly protective of their sovereignty over their internal affairs, so the day when they accept third partners interfering in their relations with secessionist communities remains far in the horizon. In practical terms, therefore, the most realistic approach for implementing the principles of this republican TRS would be: (1) to persuade as many democratic actors as possible (both state and non-state ones) of the soundness of this non-unilateralist approach to secession conflicts, so that they begin to incorporate it when facing actual secessionist controversies; and (2) to work for the implementation of this approach both in constitutional as well as in international law, when and where possible.</p><p>I think that six main criticisms can be leveled at this democratic republican TRS: four <i>republican</i> and two <i>practical</i> ones. The first republican criticism would be a <i>deliberative</i> one. Republicanism tends to regard deliberative democracy as an efficient shield against factional domination (Pettit, <span>1997</span>, 187–90). It would not be justified for a deliberative democracy, the argument goes, to recognize a non-remedial right of secession: if regional majority claims are persistently a minority view in the host state, this is because they have a factional nature. In my view, factional conflict does not disappear, nor is it well handled, just by saying that “we should deliberate”; rather, it is the other way around: only an institutional design that keeps factional arbitrary power in check will force all factions to publicly discuss and convince each other by using public reasons.</p><p>The second republican criticism, namely that of <i>civic virtue</i>, consists of recalling that republicanism gives primary importance to citizens' disposition to participate in public affairs by taking care of the common good. This can only arise from a shared allegiance with the whole political community; secession can only undermine this allegiance, and therefore a republican TRS should condemn secession except in very specific remedial cases. As in the previous criticism, I think this one confuses wishes and reality: secession conflicts arise precisely when this kind of shared allegiance is already considerably weakened. To force people to share a state does not mean, in any sense, that they are going to share allegiance to it. And before we start arguing that this allegiance should be based upon “shared democratic values,” we should realize that “the fact that two societies share the same values is not particularly informative regarding their willingness to live together (e.g.,: the secessions of Norway and Sweden at the beginning of the twentieth century and Slovakia and the Czech Republic in the 1990s)” (Requejo, <span>2010</span>, 152–53).</p><p>In this sense, the adoption of a non-unilateralist framework for a secession conflict can only produce two outcomes: (1) an agreement to a secession; or (2) an agreement for unity through decentralization and recognition. In the first case, the host state, as well as the seceding one, will each become far more cohesive political communities than the host state prior to secession; in the second case, the host state will have accommodated the secessionist community so that it ceases to be secessionist in the first place. Thus, it is reasonable to expect that this democratic republican TRS, if practically applied, will be helpful, rather than harmful, in terms of promoting political communities which are able to cultivate civic virtue among their citizenry.</p><p>A third republican criticism would be that of <i>exclusion</i>. The argument would be that this TRS falls precisely into the threat of exclusion, because in fact all secessions are intrinsically exclusionary. To give some people a right to secede from a modern democracy, even a non-unilateral right, would mean: (1) to let some people decide over a matter that affects the whole political community; and (2) to brand the rest of the political community as foreigners, i.e., as non-citizens.</p><p>In my view, both versions of this criticism would be misleading. Concerning the first, we can only consider that secession affects “the whole political community” if we take for granted that “the political community” (the “nation,” one could say) is the host state, which would basically be methodological nationalism.<sup>20</sup> Otherwise, secession would “affect” the host state in the same way as many decisions taken by the government of the host state (e.g., concerning tariffs or immigration policies) affect its neighbors. If this is an argument against secession, it should equally be an argument against the independence of the host state. Moreover, this TRS ensures a say for the host state and its population in a non-unilateral framework for secession conflicts. “A say,” not “the only say.”</p><p>Concerning the second version of this criticism, secession does not “exclude” the people at the other side of the new border in the same way in which, for instance, African–Americans were excluded from full citizenship in the Southern U.S. before the 1960s. If Quebec secedes after a referendum in which all Quebec residents have been able to participate, and if all Quebec residents are entitled to the new Quebecer citizenship, then the people of the rest of Canada would not be any more “excluded” from Quebec than they currently are from the U.S.; in any case, they would be excluded from the new Quebecer citizenship, but not from “democratic citizenship,” generally speaking, which was the case of African-Americans: the Canadians will continue to be full members of a well-functioning democratic community. The territorial borders of their democracy will be smaller; their inclusion within that democracy will not.</p><p>A fourth republican criticism, one of <i>permanency</i>, goes as follows: the republican tradition wishes to guarantee that republics will endure in time (Pocock, <span>2003</span>). Thus, secession will be anathema to any republican project. However, I think this is misleading. The “permanency” that ancient and early modern republicans such as Aristotle, Polybius or Machiavelli were seeking was basically permanency in the face of corruption and the related extremes of anarchy and civil war on the one hand, and of tyranny on the other. In the end, what matters for democratic republicanism is to prevent domination and exclusion,<sup>21</sup> as well as to avoid instability (which may trigger them).</p><p>Concerning the practical criticisms, the first one would argue that this theory, even if it were widely accepted in public debate, would be <i>useless</i> in practical terms. Modern democratic states are sovereign states, and as such they conduct themselves according to their own interests, not according to ethical standards. However, take Human Rights, for instance. The theoretical notion of the human being as having a set of “natural” rights was, before the foundation of the U.N., a useful standard in order to morally assess the legitimacy of the way states treated their inhabitants; its embodiment in an international framework has obviously not been enough in order to ensure that states respect these rights, but nevertheless: (1) it has provided a legal standard to appraise states' behavior; and (2) connected to this, it has made Human Rights an element of soft power for states. I hope the principles described in this republican TRS, if they become widely accepted, have a similarly limited-but-useful impact on the behavior of states and secessionists.</p><p>The second practical criticism, the <i>autonomic</i> one, would argue for adopting other, “softer” solutions for center-periphery conflicts, rather than secession—particularly, intrastate autonomy arrangements.<sup>22</sup> However, I think that: (1) my theory does not exclude the possibility of reaching such agreements; (2) secession has, for any minority, a comparative advantage over intrastate autonomy: it transforms the minority into a majority with its own sovereign state, something that provides an ultimate protection for its self-government (Pavkovic &amp; Radan, <span>2007</span>, 246); and (3) there is some evidence that the very existence of a legal path toward secession favors the promotion and protection of self-government agreements (Sorens, <span>2012</span>, 139–52). Thus, the possibility of initiating a secession process, and not just in the face of outright oppression, is also a resource for a permanent minority to discourage a permanent majority from unilaterally subverting an intrastate autonomy arrangement.</p><p>The democratic republican TRS developed here can be summarized as follows: (1) secession conflicts must be regarded as factional ones (in fact, as the the ultimate stage of center-periphery conflicts); (2) a democratic republican framework for secession conflicts within modern democracies should be based on a non-unilateralist logic, that could be translated into a non-unilateral right of secession for any democratic secessionist community, plus a non-unilateral right to territorial unity for its democratic host state, plus a right for both sides to act unilaterally when the opposing faction happens to be <i>oppressive</i>, <i>failed</i> or already <i>unilateralist</i>; and (3) the monitoring and arbitration of the framework could be undertaken through constitutional and/or international institutional designs.</p><p>It is clear, though, that there are many unfulfilled tasks that fall out of the scope of this article, but which need to be undertaken by further research in order to further develop this TRS. In particular, there are two main groups of open issues that remain to be addressed: (1) concerning the institutionalization of the principles of the theory (e.g., what provisions should a constitutional clause on secession contain? How could we shape an international arbiter for secession conflicts? What should be the elements of an iterative approach to solve a stalemate in a negotiation on secession?); and (2) concerning the impact of this theory on adjacent theoretical problems (e.g., should its principles be applied to non-democratic contexts? Should they be applied to other territorial conflicts, such as irredentist ones?).</p><p>I have deliberately considered secession conflicts as not having a theoretical resolution based on answering the “who should the <i>demos</i> be?” question, contrary to almost all current TRS. Unfortunately, I think that there is no clear answer to this question, in purely theoretical terms; so in the real world it inevitably has to be answered through politics. Asking if only states are to be considered sovereign <i>demos</i> or if “stateless nations” (however defined) also hold legitimate sovereignty, is like asking whether left-wing parties or right-wing parties should govern. Regarding this sort of power disputes, the main task of a democratic republican theory is not to decide “<i>who is right?</i>,” but rather to design institutions that are able to channel those disputes using civilized and non-dominating means.</p><p>I have no conflicts of interest to disclose.</p>","PeriodicalId":46756,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Social Philosophy","volume":"53 3","pages":"421-440"},"PeriodicalIF":1.1000,"publicationDate":"2022-05-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/josp.12468","citationCount":"1","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Social Philosophy","FirstCategoryId":"98","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/josp.12468","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"ETHICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1

Abstract

Like most theories of democracy, democratic republicanism has usually taken for granted who the demos is. However, precisely one of the most frequent sources of political conflicts in contemporary history is the determination of its boundaries, particularly –though not only– in secession conflicts. This article aims to answer a related question: what kind of right to secede from a modern democratic state,1 if any, can be acknowledged from a democratic republican viewpoint? By answering this question, I hope to make a contribution both to republican literature (in which secession has barely been analyzed) and also to the normative literature on secession (in which republicanism has very rarely been used as a normative framework).

The core tenet of the republican theory of secession developed here is the recognition of a non-unilateral2 right of secession for any democratic secessionist community within a democratic state, coupled symmetrically with a non-unilateral right to territorial unity for that democratic host state. The rationale behind this theory is to deny both sides the power to impose their will without having to consider the interests and opinions of the other side; that is, to deny arbitrary power, which in republican terms is synonymous with domination. As we will see, this in turn minimizes the chances of permanent majorities and powerful minorities achieving arbitrary power in center-periphery conflicts.

This article does not discuss secession as a general phenomenon, but focuses particularly on secession conflicts where both secessionists and the host state (and the unionists within it) are peaceful3 and democratic. The rationale behind this analytical choice is to minimize what we might call normative noise, i.e., normative issues that distract our attention from the ones that we initially intended to discuss. Modern democracies, however imperfect they may be, are the closest polities to democratic republican ideals that exist in our contemporary world. Thus, when neither the host state nor the potentially seceding territory are attempting to move away from this political model in a non-democratic direction, secession appears normatively “naked” in democratic-republican terms. I am not trying to find out whether democratic secessionists are legitimated in seceding from undemocratic states, nor whether democratic states are legitimated in suppressing an undemocratic secessionist attempt.

The article presents this theory over eight sections: (1) a review of current theories of right of secession, pointing out why republicanism can be a useful framework to overcome their weaknesses; (2) an overview of the main tenets of republicanism, explaining why (and how) republicanism must analyze secession conflicts as a type of factional conflicts; (3) the presentation of the normative core of my republican theory of secession, based on non-unilateralism; (4) the outline of a non-unilateralist framework for secession conflicts; (5) an outline of three problematic scenarios for the theory, and of the role that unilateral mechanisms can play in order to tackle one of them; (6) an exploration of the strengths and weaknesses of two possible institutional translations of this theory (constitutionalization and internationalization); (7) a discussion of some foreseeable criticisms of the theory; and (8) a summary of my conclusions.

For the purposes of this article, a secessionist movement is a group of people that seek secession for a broader group of people, namely the target group. When secessionists are a clear majority within the target group, this group qualifies as a secessionist community. While every single member of a secessionist movement is secessionist, this is not true of secessionist communities. And when a secessionist community seeks to establish a modern democratic state through democratically acceptable means, it qualifies as a democratic secessionist community.

Unilateral secession is often regarded as “the principal focus of interest for theorists of secession” (Pavkovic & Radan, 2007, 200–201). Theories of right of secession (TRS) are usually classified into three different categories depending on who they deem entitled to (unilateral) secession: territorially concentrated groups, i.e., plebiscitarianism (Beran, 1984; Copp, 1998; Lefkowitz, 2008; Philpott, 1998; Wellman, 2005); culturally encompassing groups, i.e., ascriptivism (Margalit & Raz, 1990; Miller, 1997); or groups that are unjustly and intolerably harmed by the state, particularly (although not necessarily only) in terms of basic human rights, i.e., remedialism (Birch, 1984; Brilmayer, 1991; Buchanan, 1991, 2007; Christiano, 2006; Patten, 2002).

The first two categories of TRS conceive secession as a primary right, i.e., a right to which some groups of people are entitled a priori, with no need to justify their decision; the categories only differ regarding the definition of which people(s) are entitled to this primary right. Primary right TRS are usually criticized as being an open door to: (1) secessio ad infinitum, i.e., unending recursive secessions, leading to anarchy, and to (2) the blackmail threat, i.e., the risk of giving privileged minorities (e.g., wealthy ones) the power to threaten the whole polity. In addition, ascriptivism can be further criticized for: (3) its weak operationalization: it is difficult to give an empirically operational definition of the ascriptive features that a group of people must share in order to be considered a “culturally encompassing group”; and (4) the threat of exclusion it poses: those who live in the territory of the ascriptive group that is entitled to secession, but who do not share its ascriptive features, might come to be seen as second-class citizens, and eventually be excluded from the decision on secession, or even from citizenship altogether.4

Due to these weaknesses, many scholars espouse some version of remedialism, which regards secession as a last resort in the face of certain persistent injustices. What these injustices are is a matter of discussion, but remedialists generally agree on some basic injustices, such as massive violations of basic human rights. However, remedial theories have been criticized as unfairly biased toward the status quo,5 since they assume the legitimacy of current boundaries and put the burden of proof on secessionists. This is problematic since most boundaries are the result of historical episodes (e.g., wars) that are far from reflecting the democratic values that remedial theories rest upon. Remedialism suggests an answer to this objection: as long as states are reasonably just, boundaries are irrelevant. However, in a world of states, falling between terribly oppressed minorities and privileged, blackmailing ones, there are many intermediate cases of permanent minorities,6 which are usually the weak sides in persistent controversies on certain issues related to state or nation-building (e.g., language regulations, or the territorial structure of political or economic institutions).7 It seems unfair to assume that they must simply endure this condition because of a war lost in the distant past, for instance.

Thus, it seems that all current TRS are in some way criticized for being unfairly or dangerously biased toward either unionists or secessionists. I think that the reason behind this common weakness is that all current TRS choose an a priori winner in secession conflicts, that is entitled to the disputed territory unless X. Remedialists make this choice by means of a justice-based view of legitimacy: as long as a state is reasonably just, secession is unjustified, and therefore illegitimate. Plebiscitarian and ascriptive theories, on the other hand, make the choice by means of theories of legitimacy that are not based (or not based exclusively) on justice. In order to further examine their common weakness, I shall briefly explore this point.

It is important to distinguish between justice and legitimacy. Justice is about “the question of what should be done by political institutions or by the law; that is, what the content of political and legal decisions should be,” while legitimacy is about “the question of who should make the political and legal decisions that serve to approximate this ideal of justice, and how they should do it” (Martí, 2017, 731). While this definition includes the “who” as a question of legitimacy, I think that when we look at concrete political conflicts, justice and legitimacy point toward two different “whos”: the people who we would like to see ruling (because we share their view of justice) may not be the people who we consider legitimated to rule. For instance, we may share a Rawlsian view of justice and, therefore, tend to support social-democratic governments; while at the same time, we can regard a government with a Nozickian libertarian agenda as legitimate, as long as it has won power through means we regard as legitimate (e.g., through free and fair multi-party elections).

I understand the question “who is legitimately entitled to secede?” as an aspect of the “who is legitimately entitled to rule?” question. As we have seen, remedialists establish a direct connection between the “whos” of justice and legitimacy: those who rule justly are entitled to rule, and for the same reason, those who are ruled unjustly are entitled to separate themselves from that unjust rule. However, the problem with establishing a direct connection between justice and legitimacy is that it makes political conflicts highly difficult to deal with. We all tend to have very different ideas regarding justice, and even on the practical implications of those ideas (especially when our interests are at stake). This is, precisely, one of the main reasons why we need governments and laws, so that we have someone to arbitrate such differences. But that someone is, in the end, someone like us, and if we establish that the person who is more just (or who has the best views on justice) is the person who should rule, then we will just be going round in circles and not tackling the problem. This is why political communities need procedures and institutions that enable them to choose governments and make laws, in a manner that can be recognized as legitimate even by those who think that those governments and laws are somehow unjust. In other words: political communities need procedures and institutions in order to manage political conflicts (including those involving conflicting ideas of justice) in a legitimate way.

Therefore, I think that plebiscitarian and ascriptive theorists are right not to establish a direct connection between legitimacy and justice regarding secessionist claims. The problem, however, is that they emphasize the “who” of legitimacy over the “how.” In my opinion, the “how” is the constitutive point of legitimacy, while the “who” of legitimacy is only derivative. When the legitimate “how” (e.g., free and fair elections in country X) settles the question on the legitimacy of “who” (e.g., who is the legitimate person to hold executive power in X), polities enjoy a great deal of internal and external legitimizations, making it easier to tackle political conflicts without resorting to a “might makes right” logic. When, conversely, there is not a legitimate “how” to decide the legitimate “who,” then might does indeed make right. This is the nemesis of freedom that was the case of wars of succession in monarchies. And nowadays, it is also the case of most secession conflicts.

For these reasons, rather than deciding who is right in secession conflicts, a TRS should first and foremost be a theory that sets out a legitimate institutional framework for secession conflicts. It needs to be a theory that could be placed within a turn that is now underway in the literature: rather than finding an a priori holder of a unilateral right to secession, several authors are delineating processes and mechanisms by which secession conflicts should be managed (e.g., Sanjaume-Calvet, 2019); this even includes authors who establish a very close connection between justice and legitimacy (e.g., Bossacoma Busquets, 2020). I will argue that democratic republicanism can provide valuable tools for developing such a theory.

This article is based on the contemporary reconstruction of the republican tradition developed by Pettit (1997), building on the historiographic work of Skinner (1998); this is arguably the mainstream in current republican literature. According to this reconstruction, republicanism: (1) stands for freedom as non-domination; (2) understands domination as the arbitrary power of the individual or group X over the individual or group Y, i.e., as a power that can be exercised by X over Y without having to consider Y's interests and opinions (Pettit, 1997, 35); (3) argues that, in order to promote republican freedom, private sources of power must be controlled and dispersed by the state; (4) argues that, in order to prevent the state from itself becoming a dominator, it must be organized as a constitutional republic,8 with its own powers being dispersed and kept in check by civic virtue and the rule of law; and (5) argues that civic virtue and freedom are mutually dependent. In addition, democratic republicans, as opposed to oligarchic ones, (6) endeavor for republican freedom to include as many people as possible (Pettit, 1997, 95–96). Thus, domination and exclusion, as defined here, are the main concerns of democratic republicanism.

Considered in this way, republicanism encompasses canonical authors such as Aristotle, Cicero, Machiavelli, Spinoza, Madison or Wollstonecraft, to name but a few; it is, therefore, a long tradition of political thought, focused on justice as well as on legitimacy (Pettit, 2012, 18–19), not only in the realm of domestic politics but also in that of international relations (Onuf, 1998). Concerning this last value, a common topic in republican thought is the importance (and the danger) of factional conflicts when it comes to designing non-dominating (therefore, legitimate) political institutions. To republicans, political institutions should manage political conflicts in such a way that no contending faction can gain absolute (therefore, arbitrary) power over the others. The dispersion of public power is not only needed to guard against potential abuses by public officers, but also to guard against the risk of a factional takeover. Republican theorists have also applied this concern regarding balance of power to international relations (Deudney, 2008). Republicanism, however, has not concerned itself with designing institutions that are able to manage secession conflicts, in which the contending factions neither seek to win power within a state, nor to win power for a state, but either to become a state formed out of another one (secessionism), or to prevent another group doing so (unionism).

Even authors with an affinity to republicanism, such as Miller (2008) or Weinstock & Nadeau (2004), have not used republican concepts and principles in their works on secession (Miller, 1997; Weinstock, 2000, 2001). And when scholars have occasionally worked on secession from a republican point of view, they often have done so in a somewhat exploratory way (McGarry & Moore, 2011), usually as a secondary issue within broader works on nationalism (Ovejero, 2006, 81), international law (Sellers, 2006, 158–66), or self-determination generally (Klabbers, 2006). Other scholars, such as Caminal (2007) or Young (2005), have examined the relationship between republicanism and self-determination, but these works have focused on multinational federalism, rather than on secession. Only Catala (2017) has outlined some ethical–political duties of potentially secessionist groups, concerning non-domination, in one particular area (distributive justice). Thus, there is much work yet to be done in formulating a democratic republican TRS.

In my view, as I have already noted, a secession conflict can be understood as a sort of factional conflict. It is usually the ultimate expression of a conflict between a permanent central majority and a permanent peripheral minority, both of them defined along the lines of permanent disagreements on how the state should be conceived and organized in terms of economy (i.e., its territorial organization), territory (i.e., the territorial distribution of political power) and identity.9 In this regard, a secession conflict may imply four different threats in democratic republican terms.

The first one is the threat of exclusion, i.e., the risk that some people who would be under the authority of the seceding polity may be excluded from deciding on the matter of secession, or even from citizenship of the polity altogether. This threat, in my opinion, is one of the darkest points of ascriptive theories: if the group with a right to secede is one defined by certain objective traits, then those who do not share these traits may be excluded from the process of deciding on secession; in fact, they may even be excluded from becoming citizens of the new state, since they are not part of “the people.”

The second threat is domination by blackmailing minorities: in the case of being capable of achieving unilateral secession at will, an X minority which happened to be particularly powerful (e.g., because of its wealth) would be in a position to blackmail10 the Y citizenship of the rest of the polity,11 with no need to consider Y's interests and opinions (thus, exercising arbitrary power over Y). This is a threat that affects ascriptive TRS, but especially plebiscitarian ones, for they are highly permissive about groups of people unilaterally seceding at will.

These two threats of exclusion and blackmail have led republican scholars like Ovejero (2006, 81) or Sellers (2006, 25) to embrace remedialism. I regard remedialism, however, as ill-prepared to handle a third threat, that of arbitrary permanent majorities: by stating that secessionists must bear the burden of proof, remedialism gives the high ground to permanent majorities, who may arbitrarily decide what degree of autonomy, recognition, or economic promotion they will grant to permanent minorities.

This third threat requires a little more explanation, since it may be confused with the “tough luck” attitude proffered to, say, the loser of a democratic election. For a polity to protect the republican freedom of its members, its institutions should be designed in a manner to require them to track the interests and opinions of the people. Since unanimity is a rarity (and a unanimity rule would thus be biased toward the status quo), democratic republicanism typically defends majority rule plus counter-majoritarian checks. The goal of these checks (in democratic republican terms) is not only to protect minorities, but to allow them to intervene in public debates and, therefore, to be able to persuade people and eventually become majorities themselves. Thus, in a healthy democracy, we can expect to be sometimes in a majority and sometimes in a minority. If, for instance, I am a progressive, I will sometimes be disappointed by a conservative win in a vote, and I will sometimes be pleased by a progressive victory (or vice versa, if I am a conservative). This easily changeable nature of majorities makes majority rule plus counter-majority checks the least imperfect way to force governments to track the interests and opinions of all citizens.

However, in center-periphery conflicts about economy, territory, and identity, the majorities hardly ever change; thus, it is easy to govern the polity without much regard for the interests and opinions of permanent minorities, even if their members are individually equipped with full democratic rights. For instance, a permanent linguistic majority can decide, by the sheer force of demographic numbers but through strictly democratic procedures, to remove the teaching of the indigenous language of a permanent minority from public education. This does not mean that they will do it, but that they are able to do it. And in republican terms, this is a dominating stance, i.e., a stance of arbitrary power.

There are two remedialist strategies that have been developed in order to overcome this threat posed by arbitrary permanent majorities: (1) the defense of reasonable degrees of intrastate autonomy (Buchanan, 2007, 401–24); and (2) the inclusion, within the catalog of “just causes” for secession, of insufficient self-government, discriminatory redistribution, and/or failure of recognition (Bauböck, 2000; Christiano, 2006; Patten, 2002; Seymour, 2007). However, neither of these strategies actually overcomes the threat of arbitrary permanent majorities. What both strategies are actually saying is that the host state must accept reasonable settlements of center-periphery conflicts, without understanding that the definition of a “reasonable settlement” for a center-periphery conflict is precisely the very subject of that conflict. Moreover, this is a highly context-dependent matter that can only be discussed on a case-by-case basis. And in each case, the weak side in the conflict will usually be the peripheral permanent minority. So both strategies merely bounce around the threat they are trying to overcome.

It seems, therefore, that the (pro-secessionist or pro-unionist) bias of these TRS tends to open the door to exclusion and/or domination (either by permanent majorities or by permanent minorities). To make things worse, due to their bias toward one of the two sides, none of these TRS is likely to be accepted by the other side, thus leading to the fourth threat for democratic republican goals: instability, i.e., inappropriate handling of secession conflicts (including not handling them at all) is likely to promote instability, eventually triggering exclusion and/or domination. I have developed this republican critique of current TRS elsewhere (Perez-Lozano, 2021b). In my view, in order to overcome all four threats, democratic republicanism needs a new TRS, based on a non-unilateralist logic. I will devote the next section to developing this point.

I think that a democratic republican TRS should lean toward non-unilateral mechanisms, without completely discarding unilateral ones. This non-unilateralist logic is aimed at allowing both secessionists and the host state to pursue their respective goals; while, at the same time, forcing them to take the interests and opinions of the other side into account, which is tantamount to forcing permanent majorities and permanent minorities, in center-periphery conflicts, to take each other's interests and opinions into account. We can see this point in the Quebec Secession Reference (Supreme Court of Canada, 1998), and in how it was received by the Canadian government and the Quebec secessionists.

The Reference ruled out two unilateralist positions in the Quebec secession conflict: it denied Quebec the right to unilateral secession, either within the Canadian constitution or international law; but at the same time, it acknowledged that the Canadian government had the constitutional duty to negotiate with a secessionist Quebecer government in good faith, if a clear majority of Quebecers answered “yes” to a clear question about secession. The reference was welcomed by both the Canadian government and by the Quebec secessionists, and the delighted reaction of the latter to it was, in fact, quite telling.

We can see why by asking a counterfactual question: what would have happened if the Reference had not included Ottawa's obligation to negotiate in the case of a “Yes” victory? Initially, it would appear that the secession of Quebec would have been impossible, at least in legal terms. However, this is not exactly true: before the Court issued the Reference, Canadian federalists had repeatedly asserted that they did not want to retain Quebec within Canada against the will of Quebecers, but to remove the threat of unilateral secession (Sauvegau et al., 2006, 108). But then, what difference did the Reference make? Why was it so gladly received by the same Quebec secessionists who had initially been so reluctant for the Court to have a role in the matter (Sauvegau et al., 2006, 105–107)?

But by forbidding each side in the conflict to pursue its own goals without taking into account the interests and views of the other side, the Quebec Secession Reference minimized the chances of domination in both directions (Perez-Lozano, 2021a). And, provided that this framework, interpreted in this way, appears to be fair and reasonable to both sides, it would be difficult for either of them to unilaterally break with it while presenting itself as a reasonable and fair player in the face of public opinion, both domestic or international; this would be a cost in terms of political legitimacy and is briefly pointed out in the Reference itself (272–273).

Republicanism aims to develop these kinds of schemes in order to obtain these kinds of results. It aims to channel deep political conflicts toward an institutional framework in which (1) all interested parties have a genuine say, and are thus protected from domination and (2) as a result, all of them legitimize the framework, therefore imposing high political costs onto anyone tempted to break away from it unilaterally. Thus, republican freedom and political stability go hand in hand. In secession conflicts within modern democracies, this job could be done, in my view, by a framework grounded in a non-unilateralist logic similar to that of the Quebec Secession Reference. In the next section, I outline what this framework could look like.

In my view, a democratic republican framework for secession conflicts should be based on three pillars: (1) a non-unilateral right12 of secession for any democratic secessionist community, coupled with a non-unilateral right to territorial unity for its democratic host state; (2) a unilateral right of secession for extreme cases in which democratic secessionist communities are dealing with an oppressive,13 unilateralist, or failed state; and (3) a unilateral right to territorial unity for extreme cases in which democratic host states are dealing with an oppressive, unilateralist, or failed secessionist community.

The first of these three pillars would take the form of a non-unilateral framework to manage secession conflicts, which would basically reflect the elements drawn up in the Quebec Secession Reference: (1) a democratic (therefore, inclusive) referendum among the members of the secessionist target group, with a clear question concerning secession, in order to find out whether they actually are a secessionist community; and (2) in the case of a clear “yes” victory, a negotiation in good faith between the host state and the secessionist community. While this framework offers the secessionist community the (non-unilateral) right to pursue secession, it also gives the host state the (non-unilateral) right to defend its territorial unity. Thus, the referendum will have both epistemic and normative values: it will find out whether the target group is a secessionist community; and (if it is) it will create both: (1) a mandate for its regional government and/or representatives to negotiate secession, in good faith, with the host state, and (2) an obligation for the host state to negotiate with them in good faith.

Of course, this raises the question of who should arbitrate such a negotiation, and the framework as a whole; we will come to that in section 6. For now, in order to reach a full understanding of how this non-unilateral right of secession would look, we must discuss the following: (a) what is a clear question?; (b) how can a referendum be inclusive?; (c) what is a clear “yes” majority?; and (d) how would a “negotiation in good faith” between unionists and secessionists look?

Concerning the referendum, firstly, the question on secession must be clear. This, at least in theoretical terms, is not a challenge: for external observers, it will be uncontroversial to accept that the question in the 2014 Scottish referendum was clear, while the question in the 1980 Quebec referendum was not.14 Secondly, the referendum should be inclusive, and the “yes” majority should be clear in order to make sure that we are talking about a secessionist community. The inclusiveness of the referendum has to do with “who” should vote in order for it to be considered a legitimate vote; the clearness of the majority has to do with “how many” should vote “yes” in order to determine that we are indeed dealing with a democratic secessionist community.

The “who” of the vote has two dimensions: territorial (which territory is potentially seceding in case of a “yes” victory) and human (who should vote in the referendum). Concerning the territorial dimension, I think it is reasonable to let secessionists define the territory that will potentially secede, and, therefore, where the referendum should be held. This rule should, however, have a precondition: it must be based on a broad consensus throughout that territory. This has some problematic implications that I will discuss in section 5; for now, let us just assume that in the territory drawn out by secessionists for a referendum there exists such a consensus. The human dimension, however, should not be decided by the secessionists, for obvious reasons concerning the threat of exclusion. In a vote on the creation of a new state, the inclusive nature of democratic republicanism requires, a priori, the right of all those who would be under the authority of that state to vote. To me, this includes, at least, all citizens residing in that territory, without necessarily excluding other possible groups depending on the specific case.15

Concerning the clarity of the “yes” majority (the “how many”), the question is: what turnout, and how much support for the “yes” option, is enough in order to consider that there has been a clear secessionist victory? In my view, this problem is highly context-dependent. However, I think that we can delineate two guiding criteria. In the first place, the more historically continuous the identity of the target group as a political community, the lower the thresholds should be. And secondly: the more inclusive and cohesive (not necessarily uniform) the target group is, the lower the thresholds should be. According to these two criteria, the threshold for a “yes” victory in Padania and in the Bosniak-Croat Federation of Bosnia and Herzegovina, respectively, should be higher than in Scotland. The rationale behind these criteria is that high vote thresholds in secessionist referenda are mainly justified as an instrument against: (1) decisions based on volatile passions (which in “recently invented peoples” like Padania can be supposed, ceteris paribus, to play a higher role in secessionism than in “historically consistent peoples” like Scotland); and (2) the oppression of minorities (which can be particularly threatening in cases of societies divided by deep-seated, long-standing ethnic rivalries).

These two criteria can be included within one single principle: in a secession referendum, the more the secessionist target group can be considered a people (in terms of history, inclusion and cohesion), the lower the threshold for a clear “yes” victory should be. I call this the people clarity principle. This might seem to contradict something that my approach to secession is based on: that there is not one clear, unequivocal and unbiased definition on what a “people” is. However, this is not the case. Unlike current TRS, the people clarity principle is not implicitly based on a clear-cut definition of what a “people” is; instead, it is formulated as a matter of degree, since it aims to capture an intuition that in fact arises as a matter of degree: despite the lack of a clear, unequivocal and unbiased definition of what “a people” (or “a nation”) is, it is nevertheless reasonable to be skeptical of the authenticity of a “people” whose identity was practically formed from scratch a few decades earlier, or of the capacity of a deeply divided society to form a decent state. The people clarity principle does not deny them a path to secession, but only asks them for further proof of the seriousness and decency of their secessionist aspirations.

One last problem is who should be able to call the referendum. In my view, it should ideally be called by an autonomous democratic legislature and/or executive that represents the target group; this is classically the case in target groups organized as autonomous units within federal or regional modern democratic states. However, this will not always be the case, because the target group may belong to a unitary state. Provided that the host state has repeatedly ignored claims for decentralization, the target group should provide itself with some kind of representative institution in order to call a secession referendum if it so wishes. In addition, secessionists should have clear democratic legitimacy in order to call the referendum; this means, of course, that they should first be a clear majority in the autonomous legislature and/or executive. But they should also have had an enduring number of elected officials over time, so that we can be sure that secessionism has firm roots, rather than being just a fleeting passion. In its practical application, this condition should be softer or stricter in compliance with the people clarity principle.

Let us now assume that a secession referendum has been held in a territory; that it has been held in compliance with the requirements I have just described, and that it has resulted in a clear “yes” victory. If this result did not lead to any consequences occurring, the target group would be vulnerable to arbitrary permanent majorities. If that result, on the other hand, were to lead to unilateral secession, this would make the host state vulnerable to blackmailing minorities. From this point onwards, in order to avoid both extremes, both sides would have an obligation to negotiate in good faith. I think we can state that two actors negotiate in good faith when both pursue their own agendas while, at the same time, acknowledging each other's legitimate interests, and trying to attend them in a reasonable manner. For instance: if the potentially seceding territory contains a natural resource that happens to be crucial for the host state's economy, neither part should claim absolute control over the resource a priori; instead, they should seek some kind of agreement in order to have an equitable share in administering and benefiting from the resource.

The expectation that a regional minority could hold a secession referendum is a check against arbitrary permanent majorities. On the other hand, the expectation that a negotiation in good faith should take place after a “yes” victory is a check against blackmailing minorities: it does not make much sense to threaten the host state with secession in order to fulfill unreasonable demands if the only way to reach secession is through a reasonable negotiation with that host state. However, up until now an important question about this institutional framework has remained unanswered: should the negotiation process address secession and its details? Or should it also include the possibility of a third way between secession and the status quo (e.g., a decentralization agreement)?

The key point here is how the host state regards this negotiation, since it could take two stances: (1) to only negotiate the terms of secession; and (2) to offer and negotiate a unity agreement that is able to satisfy the secessionist community's aspirations within the host state, so that it ceases to be secessionist in the first place. In the first case, the problem disappears; whereas in the second case, we face a dilemma. In my view, at this point, we should recall the symmetry between the secessionist community's non-unilateral right of secession, on the one hand, and on the other, the host state's non-unilateral right to territorial unity. Applied to the negotiation, this means it should enable both parts to pursue their agendas, and the final agreement should reflect their legitimate interests. If the host state takes the second stance, this will mean that it wants to make a last push for territorial unity through negotiation.

One obvious risk posed by this approach is the possibility of reaching a stalemate, in which the host state and the secessionist community, with neither being particularly unreasonable, are nevertheless both very reluctant to give up their respective initial goals. One way to handle this risk would be to adopt an iterative approach to this negotiation process, intermingling it with other democratic procedures in order to unblock negotiations. For instance, if the host state offers further autonomy in exchange for maintaining the state's unity, and neither the secessionist representatives are willing to accept it, nor the host state willing to withdraw it (and accept secession), then a new referendum could be held in the secessionist community; in this new referendum, voters would be able to express whether they still prefer secession or if they would rather accept what the host state is proposing. The result, especially if it is very clear, should be taken into account in order to reach a final agreement. The more steadfast and constant the secessionist community happens to appear in its preference for secession, the less reasonable it would be for the host state to negotiate anything but secession.

Related to this, a “no” victory also poses a question: should the secessionist government that has called the referendum have the power to call another one? In my view, allowing secessionists to call as many referendums as they want whenever they want will place the host state under the threat of blackmailing minorities; while forbidding a new referendum on the matter will put the secessionist target group under the threat of arbitrary permanent majorities. Thus, it seems in tune with this theory to allow secessionist governments to call for a new referendum after a “no” vote, but only after a cooling down period. The length of this period needs to be settled case by case, so again, the existence of an arbiter becomes important; and it should be settled before the first referendum takes place, so that voters can take it into account before making their decision.

For the sake of prudence, we should acknowledge that when this general scheme is actually applied to each concrete case, even if it happens to solve all the aforementioned problems, it might encounter three further problematic scenarios, when: (1) one part of the territory proposed by secessionists as potentially seceding is not part of the political unit in which the secessionist movement holds the democratic power to call for a referendum (e.g., Navarre in the case of an hypothetical secession referendum in the Basque Country); (2) one identifiable part of the territory proposed by secessionists as potentially seceding is, in fact, inhabited by a majority of people who oppose secession (e.g., the indigenous-populated parts of Northern Quebec); and (3) one of the two factions of the conflict explicitly rejects this entire non-unilateralist scheme. Concerning the first scenario, I think it would be reasonable not to include the territory in the secession referendum unless the inhabitants of that territory decide to be included by democratic means.16

The second scenario can be handled, I think, by simply applying the very same scheme of non-unilateral secession. The application of this scheme to this “internal secession” would be justified on the same democratic republican grounds that justified its application to the “external” secession scenario.17 However, I think that we must divide this “internal secession” scenario into two further sub-scenarios: (2.1) a majority of the sub-territory's population wants to secede from the broader territory; (2.2) a majority of the sub-territory's population wants to secede from the broader territory if the broader territory happens to secede from the host state. I think that, ceteris paribus, the clarity threshold for a “yes” majority should be higher in the second sub-scenario than in the first one. The rationale behind this consideration is the people clarity principle: an “internally secessionist” will that is independent of the potential secession of the broader territory shows a stronger identity on the part of the sub-territory's population as a people than if they only wanted to “internally secede” in the case of the broader territory seceding from the host state.

Finally, the third scenario implies that one of the two actors is attempting to unilaterally impose its agenda. In the case of the democratic host state, I think that this is only justified when: (1) secession implies a serious risk of outright oppression of minorities inhabiting the potentially seceding territory (e.g., ethnic cleansing); (2) the target group would be, beyond any reasonable doubt, a failed secessionist community, i.e., incapable of establishing a functional sovereign state; or (3) the secessionists are clearly attempting to secede unilaterally in the first place. Symmetrically, unilateral secession by a democratic secessionist community would only be justified when: (1) there is outright oppression being exercised by the host state (in the same aforementioned terms); (2) the host state is a failed one; or (3) the host state is clearly intending to unilaterally maintain its territorial unity and suppress a secession attempt in the first place. Thus, the conditions for having a right to act unilaterally would be symmetrical for both factions: they would only have this right if the opposing faction happened to be oppressive, failed or already unilateralist.

Here, it should be recalled that this non-unilateralist scheme leaves many unanswered questions when it comes to applying it to each concrete case. To point out but a few: (1) should only resident citizens vote on the referendum, or should we include other groups (e.g., immigrants or the secessionist community's diaspora)?; (2) what should be the threshold for a clear “yes” majority?; (3) in the case of a clear “yes” victory, how can it be decided whether the host state and the secessionist community are actually negotiating in good faith?; (4) how can it be determined whether the host state or the secessionist community are actually experiencing any of the scenarios that justify them acting unilaterally?

The answers to these questions would inevitably be context-dependent. Thus, we need to determine who should answer them: i.e., who should be the arbiter of the whole process, and under what legal and political framework that body should act. There are two possible forms of arbitration: (1) constitutional; and (2) international. Concerning the first one, it is usually assumed that “non-unilateral” and “constitutional” secession are synonymous (Buchanan, 2007, 338–39). Indeed, the possibility of a constitutional right of secession has attracted the attention of different scholars, either to endorse it (Corlett, 1998; Jovanovic, 2007; Norman, 2003; Weinstock, 2000, 2001), or to reject it (Aronovitch, 2006; Sunstein, 1991, 2001), but up until now no analysis of the matter has been carried out from the point of view of democratic republicanism.

The introduction of this constitutional right would imply that the arbiter of this non-unilateralist framework could be either a constitutionally sanctioned specialized agency, or the institution charged, in each state, with the task of constitutional review, i.e., the host state legislature, its supreme court or its constitutional court, depending on the case. In my view, this raises a problem: a constitutional right of secession, while promising in terms of minimizing domination and exclusion, will always be limited by the fact that the arbiter of such procedure will be, in the end, one of the powers belonging to the host state; that is, a power belonging to one of the conflicting factions. That does not mean that this power will necessarily be unable to be reasonably impartial (as the Quebec Secession Reference shows), but nevertheless, in terms of legitimacy, this problem stands.

However, the synonymizing of “constitutional” and “non-unilateral” secession, while common in the literature, is doubtful. I think there is a second possible institutional translation of this republican TRS: its non-unilateralist principles should be taken up within the international system, through a series of deliberations and agreements (from joint declarations to treaties) between democratic states, as well as between them and internationally relevant democratic actors (from sub-state secessionist governments to international organizations or NGOs). This would outline an institutional framework for a non-unilateralist management of secession political conflicts. Again, the arbiter in this framework could either be a specialized agency, or the institutions charged with monitoring the lawfulness of the international system (particularly, the International Court of Justice).18

To embed this non-unilateralist framework within the international system would transform it into a multilateralist framework. This would be in tune with the fact that, in their contributions to International Thought, current republican scholars working within Pettit's paradigm usually stand for a combination of: (1) promoting democratic regimes and (2) avoiding the undesireable extremes of anarchy and hierarchy through international organizations and law, rather than through the formation of a world state rendered unfeasible and/or undesirable (Besson, 2009; Cheneval, 2009; Deudney, 2008; Pettit, 2010, 2016; Slaughter, 2005). Cheneval uses the term multilateralism to label this middle ground between international anarchy and a world state. According to him, an institution is multilateral (as opposed to bilateral or unilateral) “if it follows generalized behaviour principles and implies elements of creation of common law and collective action by more than two states” (Cheneval, 2009, 246). The specificity of republican multilateralism lies in the fact that “the Member States of the process adhere to republican principles and strive at a more perfect realization of republican principles via the multilateral institutions they adhere to” (Cheneval, 2009, 246).

There are two important assumptions that underlie these republican proposals for a multilateral international order: (1) the existence of independent states; and (2) that humankind is not willing to merge them into a world state. However, there has been little reflection on the legitimacy of the borders of these states. And among the few international republican theorists who have dealt with secession, an unjustified bias for the existing borders tends to be the norm.19

Since international law is made by states, it could be argued that, in the end, we cannot expect an international arbiter to actually be more impartial than a constitutional domestic arbiter. It is true that it is not a perfect solution. But while international law is law created by all states, the parties involved in one given secession conflict are not all states against one given secessionist community, but one given state against one given secessionist community. So it seems reasonable to expect that an international arbitration body would be more trusted, by secessionists, to be an impartial arbiter without, nevertheless, being regarded as partial by the host state. In a way, the gain would be similar to that achieved by the creation of international courts of human rights: it is true that they are created by the same states that are expected to be monitored by them. And yet, they are usually a last line of defense against human rights abuses perpetrated by one concrete state or another.

So it seems that an optimal institutional translation of this republican TRS would be an international, multilateralist framework to manage secession conflicts. But if the constitutional translation would be problematic because of the risk of a partial arbiter, the international translation would be problematic because it is highly ambitious: states, even democratic ones, tend to be highly protective of their sovereignty over their internal affairs, so the day when they accept third partners interfering in their relations with secessionist communities remains far in the horizon. In practical terms, therefore, the most realistic approach for implementing the principles of this republican TRS would be: (1) to persuade as many democratic actors as possible (both state and non-state ones) of the soundness of this non-unilateralist approach to secession conflicts, so that they begin to incorporate it when facing actual secessionist controversies; and (2) to work for the implementation of this approach both in constitutional as well as in international law, when and where possible.

I think that six main criticisms can be leveled at this democratic republican TRS: four republican and two practical ones. The first republican criticism would be a deliberative one. Republicanism tends to regard deliberative democracy as an efficient shield against factional domination (Pettit, 1997, 187–90). It would not be justified for a deliberative democracy, the argument goes, to recognize a non-remedial right of secession: if regional majority claims are persistently a minority view in the host state, this is because they have a factional nature. In my view, factional conflict does not disappear, nor is it well handled, just by saying that “we should deliberate”; rather, it is the other way around: only an institutional design that keeps factional arbitrary power in check will force all factions to publicly discuss and convince each other by using public reasons.

The second republican criticism, namely that of civic virtue, consists of recalling that republicanism gives primary importance to citizens' disposition to participate in public affairs by taking care of the common good. This can only arise from a shared allegiance with the whole political community; secession can only undermine this allegiance, and therefore a republican TRS should condemn secession except in very specific remedial cases. As in the previous criticism, I think this one confuses wishes and reality: secession conflicts arise precisely when this kind of shared allegiance is already considerably weakened. To force people to share a state does not mean, in any sense, that they are going to share allegiance to it. And before we start arguing that this allegiance should be based upon “shared democratic values,” we should realize that “the fact that two societies share the same values is not particularly informative regarding their willingness to live together (e.g.,: the secessions of Norway and Sweden at the beginning of the twentieth century and Slovakia and the Czech Republic in the 1990s)” (Requejo, 2010, 152–53).

In this sense, the adoption of a non-unilateralist framework for a secession conflict can only produce two outcomes: (1) an agreement to a secession; or (2) an agreement for unity through decentralization and recognition. In the first case, the host state, as well as the seceding one, will each become far more cohesive political communities than the host state prior to secession; in the second case, the host state will have accommodated the secessionist community so that it ceases to be secessionist in the first place. Thus, it is reasonable to expect that this democratic republican TRS, if practically applied, will be helpful, rather than harmful, in terms of promoting political communities which are able to cultivate civic virtue among their citizenry.

A third republican criticism would be that of exclusion. The argument would be that this TRS falls precisely into the threat of exclusion, because in fact all secessions are intrinsically exclusionary. To give some people a right to secede from a modern democracy, even a non-unilateral right, would mean: (1) to let some people decide over a matter that affects the whole political community; and (2) to brand the rest of the political community as foreigners, i.e., as non-citizens.

In my view, both versions of this criticism would be misleading. Concerning the first, we can only consider that secession affects “the whole political community” if we take for granted that “the political community” (the “nation,” one could say) is the host state, which would basically be methodological nationalism.20 Otherwise, secession would “affect” the host state in the same way as many decisions taken by the government of the host state (e.g., concerning tariffs or immigration policies) affect its neighbors. If this is an argument against secession, it should equally be an argument against the independence of the host state. Moreover, this TRS ensures a say for the host state and its population in a non-unilateral framework for secession conflicts. “A say,” not “the only say.”

Concerning the second version of this criticism, secession does not “exclude” the people at the other side of the new border in the same way in which, for instance, African–Americans were excluded from full citizenship in the Southern U.S. before the 1960s. If Quebec secedes after a referendum in which all Quebec residents have been able to participate, and if all Quebec residents are entitled to the new Quebecer citizenship, then the people of the rest of Canada would not be any more “excluded” from Quebec than they currently are from the U.S.; in any case, they would be excluded from the new Quebecer citizenship, but not from “democratic citizenship,” generally speaking, which was the case of African-Americans: the Canadians will continue to be full members of a well-functioning democratic community. The territorial borders of their democracy will be smaller; their inclusion within that democracy will not.

A fourth republican criticism, one of permanency, goes as follows: the republican tradition wishes to guarantee that republics will endure in time (Pocock, 2003). Thus, secession will be anathema to any republican project. However, I think this is misleading. The “permanency” that ancient and early modern republicans such as Aristotle, Polybius or Machiavelli were seeking was basically permanency in the face of corruption and the related extremes of anarchy and civil war on the one hand, and of tyranny on the other. In the end, what matters for democratic republicanism is to prevent domination and exclusion,21 as well as to avoid instability (which may trigger them).

Concerning the practical criticisms, the first one would argue that this theory, even if it were widely accepted in public debate, would be useless in practical terms. Modern democratic states are sovereign states, and as such they conduct themselves according to their own interests, not according to ethical standards. However, take Human Rights, for instance. The theoretical notion of the human being as having a set of “natural” rights was, before the foundation of the U.N., a useful standard in order to morally assess the legitimacy of the way states treated their inhabitants; its embodiment in an international framework has obviously not been enough in order to ensure that states respect these rights, but nevertheless: (1) it has provided a legal standard to appraise states' behavior; and (2) connected to this, it has made Human Rights an element of soft power for states. I hope the principles described in this republican TRS, if they become widely accepted, have a similarly limited-but-useful impact on the behavior of states and secessionists.

The second practical criticism, the autonomic one, would argue for adopting other, “softer” solutions for center-periphery conflicts, rather than secession—particularly, intrastate autonomy arrangements.22 However, I think that: (1) my theory does not exclude the possibility of reaching such agreements; (2) secession has, for any minority, a comparative advantage over intrastate autonomy: it transforms the minority into a majority with its own sovereign state, something that provides an ultimate protection for its self-government (Pavkovic & Radan, 2007, 246); and (3) there is some evidence that the very existence of a legal path toward secession favors the promotion and protection of self-government agreements (Sorens, 2012, 139–52). Thus, the possibility of initiating a secession process, and not just in the face of outright oppression, is also a resource for a permanent minority to discourage a permanent majority from unilaterally subverting an intrastate autonomy arrangement.

The democratic republican TRS developed here can be summarized as follows: (1) secession conflicts must be regarded as factional ones (in fact, as the the ultimate stage of center-periphery conflicts); (2) a democratic republican framework for secession conflicts within modern democracies should be based on a non-unilateralist logic, that could be translated into a non-unilateral right of secession for any democratic secessionist community, plus a non-unilateral right to territorial unity for its democratic host state, plus a right for both sides to act unilaterally when the opposing faction happens to be oppressive, failed or already unilateralist; and (3) the monitoring and arbitration of the framework could be undertaken through constitutional and/or international institutional designs.

It is clear, though, that there are many unfulfilled tasks that fall out of the scope of this article, but which need to be undertaken by further research in order to further develop this TRS. In particular, there are two main groups of open issues that remain to be addressed: (1) concerning the institutionalization of the principles of the theory (e.g., what provisions should a constitutional clause on secession contain? How could we shape an international arbiter for secession conflicts? What should be the elements of an iterative approach to solve a stalemate in a negotiation on secession?); and (2) concerning the impact of this theory on adjacent theoretical problems (e.g., should its principles be applied to non-democratic contexts? Should they be applied to other territorial conflicts, such as irredentist ones?).

I have deliberately considered secession conflicts as not having a theoretical resolution based on answering the “who should the demos be?” question, contrary to almost all current TRS. Unfortunately, I think that there is no clear answer to this question, in purely theoretical terms; so in the real world it inevitably has to be answered through politics. Asking if only states are to be considered sovereign demos or if “stateless nations” (however defined) also hold legitimate sovereignty, is like asking whether left-wing parties or right-wing parties should govern. Regarding this sort of power disputes, the main task of a democratic republican theory is not to decide “who is right?,” but rather to design institutions that are able to channel those disputes using civilized and non-dominating means.

I have no conflicts of interest to disclose.

查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
走向脱离的共和理论
像大多数民主理论一样,民主共和主义通常认为谁是民众是理所当然的。然而,当代史上最常见的政治冲突来源之一恰恰是边界的确定,尤其是——尽管不仅是——在分裂冲突中。本文旨在回答一个相关的问题:从民主共和的观点来看,从一个现代民主国家脱离的权利(如果有的话)是什么样的?通过回答这个问题,我希望对共和主义文学(其中很少分析分裂)和关于分裂的规范文学(其中很少将共和主义用作规范框架)做出贡献。在此形成的共和分裂理论的核心原则是,承认民主国家内任何民主分裂主义团体都有非单方面的分裂权,与此对称的是,该民主东道国也有非单方面的领土统一权。这一理论背后的基本原理是否认双方在不考虑对方利益和意见的情况下将自己的意志强加于人的权力;也就是说,否认专断权力,在共和主义的术语中,专断权力等同于统治。正如我们将看到的,这反过来又将永久多数和强大的少数在中心-边缘冲突中获得专断权力的机会降至最低。本文不把分裂作为一种普遍现象来讨论,而是特别关注分裂分子和所在国(以及所在国的联合派)都是和平民主的分裂冲突。这种分析性选择背后的基本原理是尽量减少我们所谓的规范性噪音,即那些分散我们对最初打算讨论的规范性问题的注意力的规范性问题。现代民主政体,无论多么不完美,都是我们当代世界中最接近民主共和理想的政体。因此,当东道国和潜在的分裂领土都没有试图从这种政治模式转向非民主方向时,分裂在民主-共和的术语中显得规范地“赤裸裸”。我不是试图找出民主分裂主义者从非民主国家脱离是否合法,也不是民主国家镇压非民主分裂主义者的企图是否合法。本文分八个部分介绍了这一理论:(1)对现有的分离权理论进行了回顾,指出为什么共和主义可以成为一个有用的框架来克服它们的弱点;(2)概述共和主义的主要原则,解释共和主义为什么(以及如何)必须将分裂冲突作为一种派系冲突来分析;(3)以非单边主义为基础,提出了我的共和分裂论的规范性核心;(4)针对分裂国家冲突的非单边主义框架纲要;(5)概述该理论的三个有问题的场景,以及为了解决其中一个问题,单边机制可以发挥的作用;(6)探讨这一理论的两种可能的制度翻译(宪政化和国际化)的优缺点;(7)讨论一些可预见的对该理论的批评;(8)总结我的结论。为了本文的目的,分离主义运动是指一群人为更广泛的人群,即目标群体寻求分离。当分离主义者在目标群体中占明显多数时,这个群体就有资格成为分离主义者社区。虽然分离主义运动的每个成员都是分离主义者,但分离主义社区并非如此。当一个分离主义团体试图通过民主可接受的手段建立一个现代民主国家时,它就有资格成为一个民主的分离主义团体。单方面的分离通常被认为是“分离论者主要关注的焦点”(Pavkovic &;Radan, 2007, 200-201)。分离权理论通常根据他们认为谁有权(单方面)分离而分为三种不同的类别:领土集中的群体,即公民投票(Beran, 1984;库普,1998;莱夫科维茨,2008;菲尔波特,1998;Wellman, 2005);文化包容群体,即归因主义(Margalit &拉兹,1990;米勒,1997);或受到国家不公正和不可容忍的伤害的群体,特别是(尽管不一定是)在基本人权方面,即补救主义(Birch, 1984;Brilmayer, 1991;布坎南,1991,2007;global, 2006;彭定康,2002)。前两类TRS将分离视为一项基本权利,即某些群体先天享有的权利,无需为其决定辩护;这些类别的不同之处在于对哪些人有权享有这一基本权利的定义。 在我看来,这提出了一个问题:宪法规定的分离权虽然有望最大限度地减少统治和排斥,但它总是受到这样一个事实的限制:这种程序的仲裁者最终将是属于东道国的权力之一;也就是说,属于冲突派系之一的权力。这并不意味着这种权力必然不能合理公正(如魁北克分离参考所示),但无论如何,就合法性而言,这个问题仍然存在。然而,“宪法”和“非单方面”分裂的同义词虽然在文献中很常见,但值得怀疑。我认为,这种共和主义的TRS还有第二种可能的制度翻译:它的非单边主义原则应该在国际体系中得到采纳,通过民主国家之间的一系列审议和协议(从联合声明到条约),以及它们与国际上相关的民主行动者(从次国家分裂主义政府到国际组织或非政府组织)之间的协商和协议。这将勾勒出一个非单边主义管理分裂政治冲突的体制框架。同样,这个框架中的仲裁者既可以是一个专门机构,也可以是负责监督国际制度合法性的机构(特别是国际法院)。将这一非单边主义框架纳入国际体系将使其转变为多边主义框架。这与这样一个事实是一致的,即在他们对国际思想的贡献中,目前在佩蒂特范式下工作的共和党学者通常主张:(1)促进民主制度;(2)通过国际组织和法律避免不受欢迎的无政府状态和等级制度的极端,而不是通过形成一个不可行和/或不受欢迎的世界国家(Besson, 2009;Cheneval, 2009;Deudney, 2008;Pettit, 2010, 2016;屠杀,2005)。切内瓦尔用“多边主义”这个词来标记这种介于国际无政府状态和世界国家之间的中间地带。根据他的说法,一个制度是多边的(与双边或单边相反),“如果它遵循一般的行为原则,并包含创建普通法和两个以上国家集体行动的要素”(Cheneval, 2009, 246)。共和多边主义的特殊性在于“进程的成员国坚持共和原则,并通过其所坚持的多边机构,力求更完善地实现共和原则”(Cheneval, 2009, 246)。这些关于多边国际秩序的共和主义提议有两个重要的假设:(1)独立国家的存在;(2)人类不愿意将它们合并成一个世界国家。然而,人们对这些国家边界的合法性几乎没有反思。在少数研究过分裂问题的国际共和理论家中,对现有边界的不合理偏见往往是常态。19由于国际法是由国家制定的,因此可以说,最终,我们不能期望国际仲裁者实际上比宪法规定的国内仲裁者更公正。的确,这不是一个完美的解决方案。但是,虽然国际法是由所有国家制定的法律,但卷入某一分裂冲突的各方并不是所有国家反对某一分裂主义团体,而是一个国家反对某一分裂主义团体。因此,我们似乎有理由期待一个国际仲裁机构会更受分裂主义者的信任,成为一个公正的仲裁者,而不会被东道国视为偏颇。在某种程度上,这样做的好处与设立国际人权法庭所取得的好处类似:的确,这些法庭是由同样的国家设立的,而这些国家预计将受到它们的监督。然而,它们通常是抵御某个具体国家或另一个国家侵犯人权行为的最后一道防线。因此,这个共和TRS的最佳制度翻译似乎是一个管理分裂冲突的国际多边主义框架。但是,如果宪法翻译会因为一个不公正的仲裁者的风险而有问题,那么国际翻译也会有问题,因为它是高度雄心勃勃的:国家,即使是民主国家,往往高度保护自己的主权,而不是内政,所以他们接受第三方伙伴干涉他们与分离主义社区关系的那一天仍然遥远。 因此,在实践中,实施这一共和主义TRS原则的最现实的方法是:(1)说服尽可能多的民主行为体(包括国家和非国家行为体),让他们相信这种处理分裂冲突的非单边主义方法的合理性,以便他们在面对实际的分裂主义争议时开始将其纳入;(2)在可能的时间和地点,为在宪法和国际法中实施这一方法而努力。我认为可以对民主共和党的TRS提出六个主要批评:四个是共和党的,两个是实际的。共和党的第一个批评将是深思熟虑的。共和主义倾向于将协商民主视为对抗派系统治的有效屏障(Pettit, 1997,187 - 90)。这种观点认为,对于协商民主来说,承认一种非补救性的分离权是没有道理的:如果地区多数人的主张在东道国始终是少数人的观点,那是因为它们具有派系性质。在我看来,派系冲突并没有消失,也没有处理得很好,只是说了一句“我们应该商量一下”;相反,它是另一种方式:只有一种制度设计,使派系专断权力受到制约,才能迫使所有派系公开讨论,并利用公共理由说服对方。共和主义的第二种批评,即公民美德的批评,包括回顾共和主义对公民通过照顾共同利益参与公共事务的倾向的首要重要性。这只能来自与整个政治共同体的共同忠诚;分裂只会破坏这种忠诚,因此共和党TRS应该谴责分裂,除非在非常具体的补救情况下。和之前的批评一样,我认为这一批评混淆了愿望和现实:分裂冲突恰恰是在这种共同的忠诚已经大大削弱的时候出现的。强迫人们共享一个国家,在任何意义上都不意味着他们将共同效忠这个国家。在我们开始争论这种忠诚应该基于“共同的民主价值观”之前,我们应该意识到,“两个社会拥有相同的价值观,这一事实并不能特别说明它们是否愿意共同生活(例如:20世纪初挪威和瑞典的分离,以及20世纪90年代斯洛伐克和捷克共和国的分离)”(Requejo, 2010, 152-53)。从这个意义上说,采用非单边主义的框架来解决分裂冲突只会产生两种结果:(1)达成分裂协议;或者(2)通过分权和承认达成统一协议。在第一种情况下,东道国以及分离国将各自成为比分离前的东道国更具凝聚力的政治共同体;在第二种情况下,东道国将接纳分裂主义社区,使其首先不再是分裂主义社区。因此,有理由期望这种民主共和的TRS,如果实际应用,在促进能够在其公民中培养公民美德的政治社区方面将是有益的,而不是有害的。共和党的第三个批评是排斥。争论的焦点是,这个TRS恰恰属于排他的威胁,因为事实上,所有的分裂本质上都是排他的。赋予一些人脱离现代民主的权利,即使是一种非单方面的权利,将意味着:(1)让一些人决定影响整个政治共同体的事情;(2)将政治团体的其他成员标记为外国人,即非公民。在我看来,这种批评的两个版本都具有误导性。关于前者,我们只能认为分裂影响“整个政治共同体”,如果我们理所当然地认为“政治共同体”(可以说“民族”)是东道国,这基本上是方法论民族主义否则,分裂将“影响”东道国,就像东道国政府做出的许多决定(例如,有关关税或移民政策)影响其邻国一样。如果这是一个反对分裂的论据,那么它同样应该是一个反对东道国独立的论据。此外,这一TRS确保了东道国及其人民在分裂冲突的非单边框架中的发言权。“一个说”,而不是“唯一的说”。关于这种批评的第二种说法,脱离联邦并没有像1960年代以前在美国南部把非裔美国人排除在完全公民权之外那样,把新边界另一边的人“排除在外”。 如果魁北克在所有魁北克居民都能参加的公民投票后脱离,如果所有魁北克居民都有权获得新的魁北克公民身份,那么加拿大其他地区的人就不会像现在被排除在美国之外那样被“排除”在魁北克之外;无论如何,他们将被排除在新的魁北克公民身份之外,但不会被排除在“民主公民身份”之外,一般来说,非洲裔美国人的情况就是如此:加拿大人将继续成为一个运作良好的民主社区的正式成员。民主国家的疆界将会缩小;将他们纳入民主制度则不会。共和主义的第四种批评,即持久性的批评,如下所述:共和主义传统希望保证共和国能够及时地延续下去(Pocock, 2003)。因此,分裂将是任何共和计划的诅咒。然而,我认为这是误导。亚里士多德、波利比乌斯或马基雅维利等古代和早期现代共和党人所追求的“永恒性”,基本上是面对腐败和无政府状态、内战以及暴政等极端情况时的永恒性。最后,对民主共和主义来说,重要的是防止统治和排斥,以及避免不稳定(这可能引发它们)。关于实践上的批评,第一种人认为,即使这一理论在公开辩论中被广泛接受,它在实践上也是无用的。现代民主国家是主权国家,因此,它们按照自己的利益行事,而不是按照道德标准行事。然而,以人权为例。在联合国成立之前,人类拥有一系列“自然”权利的理论概念是一个有用的标准,用于从道德上评估国家对待其居民的方式的合法性;它在国际框架中的体现显然不足以确保各国尊重这些权利,但无论如何:(1)它提供了一个评估国家行为的法律标准;(2)与此相关的是,它使人权成为国家软实力的一个要素。我希望这个共和党TRS中所描述的原则,如果它们被广泛接受,对各州和分离主义者的行为也会产生同样有限但有用的影响。第二种实际的批评,自治主义的批评,会主张采用其他的,“软”的解决方案来解决中心-边缘冲突,而不是分裂-特别是内部自治安排然而,我认为:(1)我的理论并不排除达成这种协议的可能性;(2)对于任何少数民族来说,分裂都比内部自治有相对优势:它将少数民族转变为拥有自己主权国家的多数民族,这为其自治政府提供了最终的保护(Pavkovic &;Radan, 2007, 246);(3)有一些证据表明,走向分裂的法律途径的存在有利于促进和保护自治协议(Sorens, 2012, 139-52)。因此,启动分离进程的可能性,而不仅仅是面对彻底的压迫,也是永久少数民族阻止永久多数人单方面颠覆内部自治安排的一种资源。这里发展的民主共和TRS可以概括为:(1)分裂冲突必须被视为派系冲突(实际上是中心-边缘冲突的最终阶段);(2)现代民主国家内部分裂冲突的民主共和框架应以非单边主义逻辑为基础,这可以转化为任何民主分裂主义社区的非单边分裂权,加上其民主东道国的非单边领土统一权,加上当对立派系恰好是压迫性的,失败的或已经是单边主义者时,双方单方面采取行动的权利;(3)框架的监督和仲裁可以通过宪法和/或国际机构设计来进行。然而,很明显,还有许多未完成的任务超出了本文的范围,但为了进一步开发该TRS,这些任务需要通过进一步的研究来完成。特别是,有两组悬而未决的问题有待解决:(1)关于理论原则的制度化(例如,关于分裂的宪法条款应该包含哪些条款?我们如何塑造一个国际仲裁者来处理分裂国家的冲突?解决分裂谈判僵局的迭代方法应该包含哪些元素?);(2)关于该理论对相邻理论问题的影响。 它的原则是否也适用于非民主环境?它们是否也适用于其他领土冲突,比如统一主义冲突?)我故意认为,分裂国家的冲突没有一个基于回答“谁应该是公民?”的问题,与目前几乎所有的TRS相反。不幸的是,我认为这个问题没有明确的答案,从纯理论的角度来看;因此,在现实世界中,不可避免地要通过政治来回答这个问题。问只有国家才能被视为主权人民,还是“无国籍国家”(无论如何定义)也拥有合法主权,就像问应该由左翼政党还是右翼政党执政一样。对于这种权力之争,民主共和理论的主要任务不是决定“谁是对的?”而是要设计一种制度,能够用文明的、非支配性的手段来引导这些争端。我没有要透露的利益冲突。 主要权利TRS通常被批评为打开了一扇门:(1)无限分裂,即无休止的递归分裂,导致无政府状态,以及(2)勒索威胁,即给予特权少数人(例如富人)威胁整个政体的权力的风险。此外,归因主义还可以进一步受到批评,因为:(3)它的操作性弱:很难对一群人为了被认为是一个“文化包容的群体”而必须共享的归因特征给出经验上的可操作性定义;(4)它所带来的排斥威胁:那些生活在有权分离的归属群体的领土上,但不具有其归属特征的人,可能会被视为二等公民,最终被排除在分离的决定之外,甚至完全被排除在公民身份之外。由于这些弱点,许多学者支持某种形式的补救主义,认为分裂是面对某些持续不公正的最后手段。这些不公正是什么是一个讨论的问题,但补救主义者普遍同意一些基本的不公正,例如对基本人权的大规模侵犯。然而,补救理论被批评为不公平地偏向于现状5,因为它们假定当前边界的合法性,并将举证责任推给分离主义者。这是有问题的,因为大多数边界都是历史事件(例如战争)的结果,远远不能反映补救理论所依据的民主价值观。补救主义提出了对这一反对意见的回答:只要国家合理公正,边界就无关紧要。然而,在一个国家的世界里,介于受严重压迫的少数民族和享有特权的勒索者之间,有许多永久性少数民族的中间案例,6他们通常是在与国家或民族建设有关的某些问题上持续争论的弱势一方(例如,语言法规或政治或经济机构的领土结构)例如,假设他们必须仅仅因为在遥远的过去输掉了一场战争而忍受这种状况,似乎是不公平的。因此,似乎所有现有的TRS都在某种程度上被批评为不公平或危险地偏向于联合主义者或分离主义者。我认为,这一共同弱点背后的原因是,所有当前的TRS在分裂冲突中都选择了一个先验的赢家,这个赢家有权获得有争议的领土,除非x。补救主义者通过基于正义的合法性观点做出了这种选择:只要一个国家是合理公正的,分裂就是不合理的,因此是非法的。另一方面,公民投票和归属理论通过不以(或不完全以)正义为基础的合法性理论做出选择。为了进一步考察它们的共同弱点,我将简要地探讨这一点。区分正义和合法性是很重要的。正义是关于“政治制度或法律应该做什么的问题;也就是说,政治和法律决定的内容应该是什么,”而合法性是关于“谁应该做出有助于接近这种正义理想的政治和法律决定的问题,以及他们应该如何做到这一点”(Martí, 2017, 731)。虽然这个定义包括了“谁”作为合法性问题,但我认为,当我们审视具体的政治冲突时,正义和合法性指向两个不同的“谁”:我们希望看到统治的人(因为我们认同他们对正义的看法)可能不是我们认为合法统治的人。例如,我们可能认同罗尔斯的正义观,因此倾向于支持社会民主主义政府;而与此同时,我们可以认为一个拥有诺齐克式自由意志主义议程的政府是合法的,只要它通过我们认为合法的手段赢得权力(例如,通过自由公正的多党选举)。我理解这个问题“谁合法地有权脱离?”作为“谁有合法权力统治?””的问题。正如我们所看到的,补救主义者在正义和合法性的“谁”之间建立了直接的联系:那些公正统治的人有权统治,出于同样的原因,那些被不公正统治的人有权将自己从不公正的统治中分离出来。然而,在正义和合法性之间建立直接联系的问题是,它使政治冲突非常难以处理。我们都倾向于有非常不同的关于正义的想法,甚至对这些想法的实际含义(特别是当我们的利益受到威胁时)。这正是我们需要政府和法律的主要原因之一,这样我们就有人来仲裁这些差异。 但最终,这个人是像我们一样的人,如果我们确定更公正的人(或对正义有最好看法的人)是应该统治的人,那么我们只是在兜圈子,而不是解决问题。这就是为什么政治团体需要程序和制度,使他们能够选择政府和制定法律,即使是那些认为这些政府和法律在某种程度上是不公正的人,也能承认这种方式是合法的。换句话说:政治团体需要程序和制度,以便以合法的方式管理政治冲突(包括涉及正义观念冲突的冲突)。因此,我认为公民投票论和归属论理论家没有在关于分离主义主张的合法性和正义之间建立直接联系是正确的。然而,问题在于他们强调合法性的“谁”,而不是“如何”。我认为,“如何”是合法性的本构点,而合法性的“谁”只是衍生点。当合法的“如何”(例如,X国自由公正的选举)解决了“谁”(例如,谁是X国行政权力的合法人)的合法性问题时,政治享有大量的内部和外部合法性,使其更容易解决政治冲突,而无需诉诸“强权即公理”的逻辑。相反,当没有一个合理的“如何”来决定合理的“谁”时,那么强权确实是正确的。这是自由的克星,在君主制的继承战争中就是如此。如今,大多数分裂冲突也是如此。由于这些原因,与其决定谁在分裂冲突中是正确的,TRS首先应该是一种为分裂冲突制定合法制度框架的理论。它需要是一种可以放在文献中正在进行的转变中的理论:一些作者正在描绘应该管理分裂冲突的过程和机制,而不是寻找单方面分裂权的先验持有者(例如,Sanjaume-Calvet, 2019);这甚至包括在正义和合法性之间建立非常密切联系的作者(例如,Bossacoma Busquets, 2020)。我将论证民主共和主义可以为发展这样一种理论提供有价值的工具。本文以史金纳(1998)的史学工作为基础,以佩蒂特(1997)对共和传统的当代重建为基础;这可以说是当代共和文学的主流。根据这种重构,共和主义:(1)代表着非统治的自由;(2)将支配理解为个人或群体X对个人或群体Y的任意权力,即X可以对Y行使权力而不必考虑Y的利益和意见(Pettit, 1997,35);(3)认为,为了促进共和自由,私人权力来源必须由国家控制和分散;(4)认为,为了防止国家本身成为统治者,它必须被组织成一个宪政共和国,8其自身的权力被分散,并受到公民美德和法治的制约;(5)认为公民美德和自由是相互依存的。此外,与寡头政治的共和党人相反,民主共和党人(6)努力争取共和自由,使尽可能多的人参与其中(佩蒂特,1997,95 - 96)。因此,统治和排斥,正如这里所定义的,是民主共和主义的主要关注点。以这种方式考虑,共和主义包含了经典作家,如亚里士多德、西塞罗、马基雅维利、斯宾诺莎、麦迪逊或沃斯通克拉夫特,仅举几例;因此,它是一个悠久的政治思想传统,不仅在国内政治领域,而且在国际关系领域(Onuf, 1998),它不仅关注正义,也关注合法性(Pettit, 2012, 18-19)。关于这最后一个价值,共和思想中的一个共同话题是派系冲突在设计非支配性(因此是合法的)政治制度时的重要性(和危险性)。对于共和党人来说,政治制度应该以这样一种方式来管理政治冲突,即没有任何竞争派系能够获得对其他派系的绝对(因此是专断的)权力。公共权力的分散不仅是为了防止公职人员潜在的滥用权力,也是为了防止派系接管的风险。共和党理论家也将这种对权力平衡的关注应用于国际关系(Deudney, 2008)。 然而,共和主义并不关心设计能够管理分裂冲突的机构,在这种冲突中,竞争的派系既不寻求在一个国家内赢得权力,也不寻求为一个国家赢得权力,而是成为一个由另一个国家组成的国家(分裂主义),或者阻止另一个团体这样做(联合主义)。即使是倾向于共和主义的作家,如米勒(2008)或温斯托克(Weinstock &纳多(2004),并没有在他们关于分裂的著作中使用共和的概念和原则(米勒,1997;Weinstock, 2000,2001)。当学者们偶尔从共和党的角度研究分裂时,他们通常是以一种探索性的方式来做的(McGarry &摩尔,2011),通常作为一个次要问题,在更广泛的作品中,民族主义(Ovejero, 2006,81),国际法(Sellers, 2006,158 - 66),或一般自决(Klabbers, 2006)。其他学者,如Caminal(2007)或Young(2005),已经研究了共和主义和自决之间的关系,但这些作品关注的是多国联邦制,而不是分离主义。只有Catala(2017)概述了潜在分离主义团体在一个特定领域(分配正义)的非统治性道德-政治义务。因此,在制定民主共和的TRS方面还有很多工作要做。在我看来,正如我已经指出的,分裂冲突可以被理解为一种派系冲突。它通常是永久的中心多数人和永久的边缘少数人之间冲突的最终表现,两者都是根据如何在经济(即其领土组织),领土(即政治权力的领土分配)和身份方面构想和组织国家的永久分歧来定义的在这方面,分裂冲突可能意味着民主共和的四种不同威胁。第一个是排斥的威胁,也就是说,一些在脱离联邦政体权威下的人可能会被排除在对脱离联邦问题的决定之外,甚至完全被排除在公民身份之外。在我看来,这种威胁是归属理论中最黑暗的一点:如果有权分离的群体是由某些客观特征定义的群体,那么那些不具有这些特征的人可能会被排除在决定分离的过程之外;事实上,他们甚至可能被排除在新国家的公民之外,因为他们不是“人民”的一部分。第二个威胁是通过勒索少数民族来统治;在能够随意实现单方面分离的情况下,碰巧特别强大的X少数民族(例如,由于其财富)将能够勒索政体其余部分的Y公民身份,而无需考虑Y的利益和意见(因此,对Y行使专断权力)。这是一种影响归属TRS的威胁,尤其是公民投票制的TRS。因为他们是高度宽容的群体单方面脱离意志。排斥和勒索这两种威胁使得共和党学者如Ovejero(2006,81)或Sellers(2006,25)接受了补救主义。然而,我认为补救主义没有准备好应对第三种威胁,即武断的永久多数的威胁:通过声明分离主义者必须承担举证责任,补救主义给了永久多数高地,他们可以武断地决定给予永久少数民族多大程度的自治、承认或经济提升。第三个威胁需要更多的解释,因为它可能会与向民主选举的失败者提供的“运气不好”的态度相混淆。对于一个政体来说,要保护其成员的共和自由,其机构的设计应该要求它们追踪人民的利益和意见。由于一致同意是罕见的(一致同意规则因此会偏向于现状),民主共和主义通常捍卫多数统治加上反多数主义的制衡。这些制衡的目标(用民主共和党的话说)不仅是为了保护少数群体,而且是为了让他们能够干预公共辩论,从而能够说服人们,最终自己成为多数人。因此,在一个健康的民主制度中,我们有时会成为多数,有时会成为少数。例如,如果我是一个进步派,我有时会对保守派在投票中获胜感到失望,有时又会对进步派的胜利感到高兴(反之亦然,如果我是一个保守派)。多数人的这种容易改变的性质,使得多数决定加反多数制衡成为迫使政府追踪所有公民利益和意见的最不完美的方式。 然而,在中心与边缘的经济、领土和身份冲突中,多数人几乎没有改变;因此,不太考虑永久少数群体的利益和意见来管理政体是很容易的,即使他们的成员个人拥有充分的民主权利。例如,在语言上占多数的永久居民,可以完全依靠人口数量的力量,但通过严格的民主程序,决定从公共教育中取消对永久少数民族的土著语言的教学。这并不意味着他们会去做,而是说他们有能力去做。用共和主义的术语来说,这是一种支配性的立场,也就是说,一种专断权力的立场。为了克服这种由任意的永久多数构成的威胁,已经发展出两种补救主义策略:(1)捍卫合理程度的州内自治(Buchanan, 2007, 401-24);(2)在分裂的“正当理由”目录中,包括自治不足,歧视性再分配和/或未得到承认(Bauböck, 2000;global, 2006;彭定康,2002;西摩,2007)。然而,这两种策略实际上都没有克服任意的永久多数的威胁。这两种战略实际上都在说,东道国必须接受中心与周边冲突的合理解决方案,而不理解中心与周边冲突的“合理解决”的定义恰恰是冲突的主题。此外,这是一个高度依赖上下文的问题,只能在个案基础上进行讨论。在每一种情况下,冲突中的弱势一方通常都是边缘的永久少数。因此,这两种策略都只是围绕着它们试图克服的威胁而展开。因此,这些TRS(支持分离主义或支持统一主义)的偏见似乎倾向于为排斥和/或统治(无论是由永久多数还是永久少数)打开大门。更糟糕的是,由于他们偏向于双方中的一方,这些TRS都不太可能被另一方所接受,从而导致民主共和目标的第四个威胁:不稳定,即对分裂冲突的不当处理(包括根本不处理)可能会促进不稳定,最终引发排斥和/或统治。我在其他地方发展了共和党对当前TRS的批评(Perez-Lozano, 2021b)。在我看来,为了克服这四个威胁,民主共和主义需要一个基于非单边主义逻辑的新TRS。我将在下一节讨论这一点。我认为民主共和的TRS应该倾向于非单边机制,而不是完全抛弃单边机制。这种非单边主义的逻辑旨在让分裂主义者和东道国都能追求各自的目标;而与此同时,迫使他们考虑对方的利益和意见,这就等于在中心与边缘的冲突中,迫使永久的多数和永久的少数考虑彼此的利益和意见。我们可以在魁北克分离参考(加拿大最高法院,1998年)中看到这一点,以及加拿大政府和魁北克分离主义者如何接受这一点。《参考文件》排除了魁北克分离冲突中的两种单边主义立场:它否认魁北克在加拿大宪法或国际法范围内有单方面分离的权利;但与此同时,它也承认,如果有明显多数魁北克人对有关分裂的明确问题回答“是”,加拿大政府有宪法义务真诚地与分离主义的魁北克政府进行谈判。这项提议受到加拿大政府和魁北克分离主义者的欢迎,后者对此的高兴反应实际上很能说明问题。我们可以通过问一个反事实的问题来理解为什么:如果参考文件中没有包括渥太华在“赞成”胜利的情况下进行谈判的义务,会发生什么?最初,魁北克的分离似乎是不可能的,至少在法律上是不可能的。然而,这并不完全正确:在法院发布参考文件之前,加拿大联邦主义者一再声称,他们不想违背魁北克人的意愿将魁北克保留在加拿大境内,而是为了消除单方面分离的威胁(Sauvegau et al., 2006, 108)。但是,参考文献又有什么不同呢?为什么最初不愿法院在这个问题上发挥作用的魁北克分离主义者会如此高兴地接受它(Sauvegau等)? , 2006, 105-107)?但是,通过禁止冲突中的每一方在不考虑对方的利益和观点的情况下追求自己的目标,魁北克分离参考最小化了两个方向的统治机会(Perez-Lozano, 2021a)。而且,如果这样解释的这个框架对双方来说似乎是公平合理的,那么任何一方都很难在面对国内或国际舆论时单方面打破它,同时表现出自己是一个合理和公平的参与者;就政治合法性而言,这将是一种代价,并在参考资料本身(272-273)中简要指出。共和主义的目标是发展这类计划,以获得这类结果。它的目的是将深刻的政治冲突引向一个制度框架,在这个制度框架中,(1)所有利益相关方都有真正的发言权,从而免受统治;(2)因此,所有利益相关方都使框架合法化,因此,任何试图单方面脱离该框架的人都要付出高昂的政治代价。因此,共和自由和政治稳定是齐头并进的。我认为,在现代民主国家内部的分裂冲突中,这项工作可以通过一个基于类似于《魁北克分裂参考》的非单边主义逻辑的框架来完成。在下一节中,我将概述这个框架的外观。在我看来,解决分裂冲突的民主共和框架应该基于三个支柱:(1)任何民主分裂主义社区的非单边分裂权,加上其民主东道国的非单边领土统一权;(2)在极端情况下,民主分离主义社区面对的是一个压迫性的、单边主义的或失败的国家,在这种情况下,有单方面分离的权利;(3)在极端情况下,民主东道国在处理压迫性的、单边主义的或失败的分离主义社区时,单方面享有领土统一的权利。这三个支柱中的第一个将采取非单方面框架的形式来管理分离冲突,这将基本上反映魁北克分离参考文件中起草的要素:(1)在分离主义目标群体的成员中进行民主(因此是包容性的)公民投票,明确提出有关分离主义的问题,以查明他们是否实际上是一个分离主义社区;(2)在公投结果明显为“赞成”的情况下,在主办国和分离主义团体之间进行真诚的谈判。虽然这一框架为分裂主义社区提供了(非单边的)追求分裂的权利,但它也赋予了东道国捍卫其领土统一的(非单边的)权利。因此,公投将具有认知和规范的双重价值:它将查明目标群体是否是一个分离主义社区;而且(如果是这样的话)它将创造:(1)授权其地区政府和/或代表真诚地与东道国进行分离谈判,以及(2)东道国有义务真诚地与他们进行谈判。当然,这就提出了一个问题:由谁来仲裁这样的谈判,以及整个框架;我们会在第六节讲到。目前,为了充分了解这种非单方面的分离权将会是什么样子,我们必须讨论以下问题:(a)什么是明确的问题?(b)公民投票如何能够具有包容性?(三)什么是明确的“赞成”多数?(d)统一派和分离派之间的“真诚谈判”会是什么样子?关于公投,首先,分裂的问题必须明确。至少从理论上讲,这并不是一种挑战:对于外部观察者来说,接受2014年苏格兰公投中的问题是明确的,而1980年魁北克公投中的问题则不明确,是没有争议的其次,公投应该是包容性的,“赞成”的多数应该是明确的,以确保我们谈论的是一个分离主义的社区。公投的包容性在于“谁”应该投票,才能被视为一次合法的投票;多数的明确性与“有多少人”应该投赞成票有关,以确定我们确实是在处理一个民主分裂主义社区。投票的“谁”有两个维度:领土(如果“赞成”获胜,哪些领土可能会脱离)和人(谁应该在公投中投票)。关于领土问题,我认为让分裂主义者确定可能分裂的领土是合理的,因此,公民投票应该在哪里举行。但是,这条规则应该有一个先决条件:它必须以该领土各地的广泛协商一致意见为基础。 这有一些问题的含义,我将在第5节讨论;目前,让我们假设,在分裂主义者为公投而划定的领土上,存在这样一种共识。然而,人的方面不应由分离主义者决定,理由很明显,就是有被排斥的威胁。在关于建立一个新国家的投票中,民主共和主义的包容性要求,先验地,所有在这个国家权力下的人都有投票权。对我来说,这至少包括居住在该领土上的所有公民,而不一定排除其他可能的群体,视具体情况而定。15关于“赞成”多数的明确程度(“多少”),问题是:投票率和支持“赞成”选项的人数,足以认为分裂派已经取得明显胜利?在我看来,这个问题是高度依赖于上下文的。然而,我认为我们可以划定两个指导标准。首先,目标群体作为一个政治共同体的身份在历史上越持续,门槛就应该越低。其次,目标群体的包容性和凝聚力越强(不一定是统一的),门槛就应该越低。根据这两项标准,在帕达尼亚和在波斯尼亚-黑塞哥维那波斯尼亚-克族联邦分别获得“赞成”胜利的门槛应该比在苏格兰高。这些标准背后的基本原理是,分离主义公投的高投票门槛主要被证明是一种反对:(1)基于不稳定情绪的决定(在其他条件不变的情况下,可以认为,在像帕达尼亚这样的“新发明的民族”中,这种情绪在分离主义中发挥的作用比在像苏格兰这样的“历史一致的民族”中发挥的作用更大);(2)对少数民族的压迫(在社会因根深蒂固的、长期的种族对立而分裂的情况下,这尤其具有威胁性)。这两个标准可以包含在一个单一的原则中:在独立公投中,分离主义目标群体越能被视为一个民族(在历史、包容性和凝聚力方面),“赞成”胜利的门槛就越低。我把这叫做“人的清晰原则”。这似乎与我对分裂的态度所基于的一些东西相矛盾:对于什么是“人民”,没有一个清晰、明确和公正的定义。然而,事实并非如此。与目前的TRS不同,人的清晰度原则并非隐含地基于对“人”的明确定义;相反,它是制定作为一个程度的问题,因为它的目标是捕捉一个直觉,事实上出现的学位:尽管缺乏一个清晰的、明确的和公正的定义的“人”(或“一个国家”),它仍然是合理的怀疑真实性的“人”的身份几乎从头开始形成之前几十年,或者分裂社会的能力形成一个良好的状态。“人民清晰原则”并不否认他们有脱离国家的道路,而只是要求他们进一步证明他们的分离主义愿望是认真和体面的。最后一个问题是,由谁来召集公投。在我看来,理想情况下,它应该由代表目标群体的自治民主立法机构和/或行政机构召集;在联邦或地区现代民主国家内作为自治单位组织起来的目标群体中,这是典型的情况。然而,情况并非总是如此,因为目标群体可能属于一个单一的国家。如果东道国一再无视分权的要求,目标群体应该为自己提供某种代表机构,以便在他们愿意的情况下举行独立公投。此外,分裂主义者应该有明确的民主合法性,才能举行公投;当然,这意味着他们首先应该在自治的立法机构和/或行政机构中占明显多数。但随着时间的推移,他们也应该有一批稳定的民选官员,这样我们才能确保分离主义有坚实的根基,而不仅仅是一种转瞬即逝的激情。在实际应用中,这一条件应根据人的明晰性原则放宽或严格。现在让我们假设在一个地区举行了一场独立公投;它是按照我刚才描述的要求举行的,它的结果是明显的“是”胜利。如果这一结果没有导致任何后果,目标群体将容易受到任意的永久多数的影响。另一方面,如果这一结果导致单方面的分裂,这将使东道国容易受到勒索少数民族的威胁。 从现在起,为了避免两个极端,双方都有义务真诚地进行谈判。我认为我们可以说,当双方都追求自己的议程,同时承认对方的合法利益,并试图以合理的方式参与其中时,双方谈判是真诚的。例如,如果潜在的分离领土包含对东道国经济至关重要的自然资源,那么任何一方都不应该声称对该资源拥有绝对的先天控制权;相反,它们应该寻求某种协议,以便在管理资源方面有公平的份额并从中受益。地区少数民族可以举行独立公投的预期,是对专制的永久多数的一种制衡。另一方面,期望在“赞成”胜利后进行真诚的谈判是对少数派敲诈的一种遏制:如果达成分裂的唯一途径是通过与东道国进行合理的谈判,那么以分裂来威胁东道国以满足不合理的要求是没有多大意义的。然而,到目前为止,关于这一体制框架的一个重要问题仍未得到解答:谈判进程是否应解决分裂及其细节问题?或者它是否也应该包括在分裂和现状之间的第三条道路的可能性(例如,分权协议)?这里的关键是东道国如何看待这次谈判,因为它可以采取两种立场:(1)只谈判分离的条款;(2)提出并谈判一项统一协议,能够满足分裂主义团体在东道国内的愿望,使其首先不再是分裂主义者。在第一种情况下,问题消失了;而在第二种情况下,我们面临两难。在我看来,在这一点上,我们应该回顾分裂主义社区的非单方面分离权与东道国的非单方面领土统一权之间的对称性。适用于谈判,这意味着它应该使双方都能追求自己的议程,最终的协议应该反映他们的合法利益。如果东道国采取第二种立场,这意味着它想通过谈判为领土统一做最后的努力。这种做法带来的一个明显风险是可能陷入僵局,在这种僵局中,东道国和分离主义团体都不是特别不合理,但都非常不愿意放弃各自的最初目标。处理这一风险的一种办法是对这一谈判进程采取一种反复的办法,将其与其他民主程序混合起来,以解除谈判的障碍。例如,如果东道国提出进一步的自治以换取维持国家的统一,而分裂派代表既不愿意接受,东道国也不愿意撤回它(并接受分裂),那么在分裂派社区可以举行新的全民公决;在这次新的公投中,选民将能够表达他们是否仍然倾向于分裂,或者他们是否宁愿接受东道国的提议。为了达成最终协议,应该考虑到结果,特别是如果结果非常明确的话。分裂主义团体越是坚定和坚定地倾向于分裂,那么东道国就越不合理地进行任何谈判,而不是分裂。与此相关的是,“反对”的胜利也提出了一个问题:要求举行公投的分离主义政府是否有权要求再次举行公投?在我看来,允许分裂主义者在他们想要的任何时候举行尽可能多的公投,将使东道国面临勒索少数民族的威胁;而禁止就这一问题举行新的公投,将使分裂主义目标群体受到武断的永久多数的威胁。因此,似乎与这一理论一致的是,允许分裂主义政府在“反对”投票后要求举行新的公投,但必须经过一段冷静期。这段时间的长短需要逐个解决,所以仲裁者的存在变得很重要;这个问题应该在第一次公投之前解决,这样选民在做出决定之前就能考虑到这一点。为了谨慎起见,我们应该承认,当这个总体方案实际应用于每个具体案例时,即使它碰巧解决了上述所有问题,它也可能遇到三种进一步的问题,当:(1)分裂主义者提出的潜在分裂领土的一部分不属于分裂主义者运动拥有民主权力的政治单元的一部分,要求举行全民公决(例如; 在巴斯克地区进行分离公投的情况下,纳瓦拉);(2)分离主义者提出的可能分离的领土的一个可识别的部分,实际上居住着大多数反对分离的人(例如,魁北克北部的土著居民地区);(3)冲突的两派之一明确反对整个非单边主义方案。关于第一种情况,我认为,除非该领土的居民决定通过民主手段将该领土包括在内,否则不将该领土纳入分离公民投票是合理的。我认为,第二种情况可以通过简单地采用非单方面分离的方案来解决。将这一方案应用于这种“内部分裂”的理由与将其应用于“外部”分裂的理由相同,是合理的然而,我认为我们必须将这种“内部分裂”的情况进一步分为两个子情况:(2.1)大多数分区人口希望从更广泛的领土分离出去;(2.2)如果更大的领土碰巧从东道国分离出去,那么子领土的大多数人口希望从更大的领土分离出去。我认为,在其他条件不变的情况下,第二个子情景中“赞成”多数的明确门槛应该高于第一个子情景。这种考虑背后的基本原理是人民清晰原则:独立于更广泛领土的潜在分裂的“内部分裂主义”意志,比在更广泛领土从东道国分离的情况下只想“内部分裂”的情况下,显示出子领土人口作为一个民族的更强的身份认同。最后,第三种情况意味着两个行动者中的一个正试图单方面强加其议程。在民主东道国的情况下,我认为这只有在以下情况下才是合理的:(1)分离意味着对居住在潜在分离领土上的少数民族进行彻底压迫的严重风险(例如,种族清洗);(2)毫无疑问,目标群体将是一个失败的分离主义社区,即没有能力建立一个正常运作的主权国家;或者(3)分离主义者显然首先就试图单方面分离。与此相对应的是,一个民主的分离主义社区的单方面分裂只有在以下情况下才有理由:(1)东道国正在进行彻底的压迫(以上述相同的条件);(2)主机状态为故障状态;或者(3)东道国显然打算单方面维护其领土统一,并首先镇压分裂企图。因此,对两派来说,拥有单方面行动权利的条件是对称的:只有当对方恰好是压迫性的、失败的或已经是单边主义者时,他们才会拥有这种权利。在此,应当回顾,在将这一非单边主义的办法应用于每一个具体案件时,留下了许多悬而未决的问题。这里只提出几个问题:(1)应该只有本地公民参与公投,还是应该包括其他群体(如移民或分离主义社区的侨民)?(2)“赞成”多数票的门槛应该是多少?(3)如果公投结果明显是“赞成”,那么如何判断主办国和分离主义团体是否真的在真诚地进行谈判?(4)如何确定东道国或分裂主义社区是否确实经历了任何可以证明他们单方面行动的情况?这些问题的答案将不可避免地与上下文相关。因此,我们需要确定谁应回答这些问题:即谁应成为整个进程的仲裁者,以及该机构应在何种法律和政治框架下采取行动。有两种可能的仲裁形式:(1)宪法仲裁;(2)国际化。关于第一种分离,通常认为“非单边”分离和“宪法”分离是同义词(Buchanan, 2007, 338-39)。事实上,宪法中分离权的可能性已经引起了不同学者的注意,他们要么支持它(Corlett, 1998;约万诺维奇,2007;诺曼,2003;Weinstock, 2000,2001),或者拒绝它(Aronovitch, 2006;Sunstein, 1991,2001),但到目前为止,还没有人从民主共和主义的角度对此事进行分析。引入这一宪法权利将意味着,这一非单边主义框架的仲裁者既可以是宪法批准的专门机构,也可以是每个州负责宪法审查任务的机构,即东道国立法机构、其最高法院或其宪法法院,视情况而定。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
2.20
自引率
12.50%
发文量
44
期刊最新文献
Issue Information Issue Information - NASSP Page Contributors Introduction for special issue on “Excellence, diversity, and the philosophy exception” Property as power: A theory of representation
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1