Assessing Expert Claims: Critical Thinking and the Appeal to Authority

Q4 Social Sciences Philosophical Inquiry in Education Pub Date : 2020-11-11 DOI:10.7202/1073304AR
M. Battersby
{"title":"Assessing Expert Claims: Critical Thinking and the Appeal to Authority","authors":"M. Battersby","doi":"10.7202/1073304AR","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Much of our understanding and knowledge of the world is based on the authoritative pronouncements of experts. Both our scientific and historical understanding is grounded in this way. Think of germ theory, astronomy, plate techtonics, ancient history, dinosaurs, the origin of humans; it does not take much reflection to see that most of our understanding of the world is, in fact, grounded on information supplied and warranted by experts. Given how much of our knowledge has this basis, one would think that epistemologists would have given detailed consideration to the issue of appeal to scientific and other intellectual authority. But appeals to authority and the role that authority plays in knowledge have received little attention in modem philosophy. Indeed, philosophers generally have been opposed to such appeals since the birth of Western philosophy. Greek philosophy distinguished itself from Greek theology by rejecting appeals to authority (the wisdom of the ancients or the oracle's supply of the word of god) as the primary basis of knowledge and replacing those appeals with appeals to observation and reason as the basis of knowledge. Philosophy in many ways began with rejection of authoritative pronouncements and, when philosophy revived in the seventeenth century, the aversion to authority reappeared. By rejecting the authority of both Aristotle and the church, Descartes, Bacon, and Locke helped pave the way for modem science. These authors all rejected the appeal to any authority and, in doing so, marked the beginning of modern philosophy with its emphasis on individual confirmation of claims. As a result of this history, most contemporary introductions to epistemology do not even mention the issue of appeals to experts and authority, and there is little in contemporary epistemological literature that concerns itself with this topic.1 But one might expect critical thinking, with its concern for the practical needs of knowledge assessment, would devote considerably more attention to appeals to authority. In fact, most critical thinking texts do not even refer to appeals to authority and only a few texts give the subject significant treatment; none of these treatments is adequate, in part, perhaps because there is no epistemological theory on which to base such a treatment. Of those that do treat such appeals, many give appeals a definite secondary and necessary evil status. For example, Walton states:","PeriodicalId":36151,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Inquiry in Education","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2020-11-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"1","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Philosophical Inquiry in Education","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.7202/1073304AR","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q4","JCRName":"Social Sciences","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1

Abstract

Much of our understanding and knowledge of the world is based on the authoritative pronouncements of experts. Both our scientific and historical understanding is grounded in this way. Think of germ theory, astronomy, plate techtonics, ancient history, dinosaurs, the origin of humans; it does not take much reflection to see that most of our understanding of the world is, in fact, grounded on information supplied and warranted by experts. Given how much of our knowledge has this basis, one would think that epistemologists would have given detailed consideration to the issue of appeal to scientific and other intellectual authority. But appeals to authority and the role that authority plays in knowledge have received little attention in modem philosophy. Indeed, philosophers generally have been opposed to such appeals since the birth of Western philosophy. Greek philosophy distinguished itself from Greek theology by rejecting appeals to authority (the wisdom of the ancients or the oracle's supply of the word of god) as the primary basis of knowledge and replacing those appeals with appeals to observation and reason as the basis of knowledge. Philosophy in many ways began with rejection of authoritative pronouncements and, when philosophy revived in the seventeenth century, the aversion to authority reappeared. By rejecting the authority of both Aristotle and the church, Descartes, Bacon, and Locke helped pave the way for modem science. These authors all rejected the appeal to any authority and, in doing so, marked the beginning of modern philosophy with its emphasis on individual confirmation of claims. As a result of this history, most contemporary introductions to epistemology do not even mention the issue of appeals to experts and authority, and there is little in contemporary epistemological literature that concerns itself with this topic.1 But one might expect critical thinking, with its concern for the practical needs of knowledge assessment, would devote considerably more attention to appeals to authority. In fact, most critical thinking texts do not even refer to appeals to authority and only a few texts give the subject significant treatment; none of these treatments is adequate, in part, perhaps because there is no epistemological theory on which to base such a treatment. Of those that do treat such appeals, many give appeals a definite secondary and necessary evil status. For example, Walton states:
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
专家索赔评估:批判性思维与权威诉求
我们对世界的许多理解和知识都是建立在专家权威声明的基础上的。我们对科学和历史的理解都是以这种方式为基础的。想想细菌理论、天文学、板块技术学、古代史、恐龙、人类起源;不需要太多思考就能发现,我们对世界的大部分理解实际上都是基于专家提供和保证的信息。考虑到我们有多少知识都有这个基础,人们会认为认识论者会详细考虑对科学和其他知识权威的吸引力问题。但是,对权威的呼吁以及权威在知识中的作用在现代哲学中却很少受到关注。事实上,自西方哲学诞生以来,哲学家们普遍反对这种呼吁。希腊哲学与希腊神学的区别在于,它拒绝将对权威的诉求(古人的智慧或神谕对上帝话语的供应)作为知识的主要基础,并用对观察和理性的诉求作为知识的基础来取代这些诉求。哲学在许多方面都始于对权威声明的拒绝,当哲学在17世纪复兴时,对权威的厌恶再次出现。笛卡尔、培根和洛克拒绝亚里士多德和教会的权威,为现代科学铺平了道路。这些作者都拒绝了对任何权威的呼吁,这样做标志着现代哲学的开始,强调对主张的个人确认。由于这段历史,大多数当代认识论导论甚至没有提到吸引专家和权威的问题,当代认识论文献中也很少涉及这一主题。1但人们可能会期待批判性思维,它关注知识评估的实际需求,将更多地关注向当局申诉。事实上,大多数批判性思维文本甚至没有提到对权威的呼吁,只有少数文本对主题给予了显著的处理;这些治疗方法都不充分,部分原因可能是没有认识论理论可以作为这种治疗方法的基础。在那些处理此类上诉的人中,许多人给予上诉明确的次要和必要的邪恶地位。例如,Walton指出:
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
Philosophical Inquiry in Education
Philosophical Inquiry in Education Social Sciences-Education
CiteScore
0.50
自引率
0.00%
发文量
13
审稿时长
20 weeks
期刊最新文献
Education after COVID Promoting Critical Thinking in Anti-Critical Thinking Times: Lessons from COVID Discourse When the Façade of the Normal Falls Away Demoralization and Remoralization: The Power of Creating Space for Teachers’ Moral Centres Pandemic Resurrection: Making Gendered Citizenship Visible in a “Postfeminist” Era
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1