James and Waismann on Temperament in Philosophy

IF 0.2 4区 哲学 N/A PHILOSOPHY Pluralist Pub Date : 2023-06-22 DOI:10.5406/19446489.18.2.03
J. Capps
{"title":"James and Waismann on Temperament in Philosophy","authors":"J. Capps","doi":"10.5406/19446489.18.2.03","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"For William James, philosophy is inextricably linked to what he calls temperament. In the first of his Pragmatism lectures, he claims that “the history of philosophy is to a great extent that of a certain clash of human temperaments” (Pragmatism 11), while conceding that this will strike many philosophers as “undignified.” In a similar vein, he elsewhere writes that philosophy seeks “by hard reasoning for results emotionally valuable” (Some Problems of Philosophy 11). It’s not hard to see a connection between these two claims: whether a philosophical conclusion is “emotionally valuable” will presumably depend, at least in part, on the reader’s temperament. A philosophical work will leave some readers cold while resonating with others; some philosophy will engage one’s interest and energy, while other philosophy will seem not so much mistaken as alien, remote from what one might ever find useful, interesting, or enlightening. James’s meta-philosophical claim—his philosophy of philosophy—has received surprisingly little attention. Much of the literature has focused instead on what he meant by “temperament” in the context of nineteenthand early twentieth-century theories of psychology and brain science. Much less attention has been paid to whether he is right and what the consequences would be if he is right.1 I aim to address this gap by first raising some fundamental issues with James’s position. To see better what he should have said, I will then turn to some later but surprisingly similar remarks by the Anglo-Austrian philosopher and mathematician Friedrich Waismann, before turning to a more recent account of philosophical methodology defended by Timothy Williamson.","PeriodicalId":42609,"journal":{"name":"Pluralist","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2000,"publicationDate":"2023-06-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Pluralist","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.5406/19446489.18.2.03","RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"N/A","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

For William James, philosophy is inextricably linked to what he calls temperament. In the first of his Pragmatism lectures, he claims that “the history of philosophy is to a great extent that of a certain clash of human temperaments” (Pragmatism 11), while conceding that this will strike many philosophers as “undignified.” In a similar vein, he elsewhere writes that philosophy seeks “by hard reasoning for results emotionally valuable” (Some Problems of Philosophy 11). It’s not hard to see a connection between these two claims: whether a philosophical conclusion is “emotionally valuable” will presumably depend, at least in part, on the reader’s temperament. A philosophical work will leave some readers cold while resonating with others; some philosophy will engage one’s interest and energy, while other philosophy will seem not so much mistaken as alien, remote from what one might ever find useful, interesting, or enlightening. James’s meta-philosophical claim—his philosophy of philosophy—has received surprisingly little attention. Much of the literature has focused instead on what he meant by “temperament” in the context of nineteenthand early twentieth-century theories of psychology and brain science. Much less attention has been paid to whether he is right and what the consequences would be if he is right.1 I aim to address this gap by first raising some fundamental issues with James’s position. To see better what he should have said, I will then turn to some later but surprisingly similar remarks by the Anglo-Austrian philosopher and mathematician Friedrich Waismann, before turning to a more recent account of philosophical methodology defended by Timothy Williamson.
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
詹姆斯与韦斯曼论哲学中的气质
对威廉·詹姆斯来说,哲学与他所谓的气质密不可分。在他的第一次实用主义讲座中,他声称“哲学史在很大程度上是人类气质的某种冲突”(实用主义11),同时承认这会让许多哲学家感到“不体面”,他在其他地方写道,哲学寻求“通过艰难的推理获得情感上有价值的结果”(《哲学的一些问题》11)。不难看出这两种说法之间的联系:哲学结论是否“有情感价值”,至少在一定程度上取决于读者的气质。一部哲学作品会让一些读者感到冷漠,同时也会引起其他人的共鸣;有些哲学会吸引一个人的兴趣和精力,而另一些哲学则不会被误解为异类,与人们可能会发现的有用、有趣或有启发性的东西相去甚远。詹姆斯的元哲学主张——他的哲学——出人意料地很少受到关注。相反,在19世纪和20世纪初的心理学和脑科学理论中,许多文献都集中在他所说的“气质”的含义上。人们很少关注他是否正确,以及如果他正确会产生什么后果。1我的目标是通过首先提出詹姆斯立场的一些基本问题来解决这个差距。为了更好地了解他应该说些什么,我将转向后来英奥哲学家和数学家弗里德里希·韦斯曼的一些令人惊讶的相似言论,然后转向蒂莫西·威廉姆森对哲学方法论的更新描述。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
Pluralist
Pluralist PHILOSOPHY-
CiteScore
0.50
自引率
0.00%
发文量
39
期刊最新文献
Casting a Vote for Subordination Using a Slur Affective Foundation of Society in Nietzsche's Philosophy Philosophy and the Modern African American Freedom Struggle: A Freedom Gaze The Dramatization of Absolute Idealism: Gabriel Marcel and F. H. Bradley Collective Regret and Guilt and Heroic Agency: A Pro-Existential Approach
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1