首页 > 最新文献

Pluralist最新文献

英文 中文
Affective Foundation of Society in Nietzsche's Philosophy 尼采哲学中的社会情感基础
4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-01 DOI: 10.5406/19446489.18.3.01
Jihun Jeong
Nietzsche believes that the different human types should be allowed to thrive and not be reduced into uniformity, as he says “nothing should be banished more than . . . the approximation and reconciliation” of the different types (KSA 12:10[59]).1 He sees the approximation as a reflection of democratic values and monolithic morality that he opposes. Instead, he believes that humans should be naturalized and allowed to live in accordance with their own nature. To achieve this, Nietzsche proposed “the great politics,” which “makes physiology into the ruler over all other questions” to “breed humanity as a whole” so that “one affirms what one is, one denies what one is not” (KSA 13:25[1]). In this way, Nietzsche thinks the different types should live in accordance with their respective nature.In The Antichrist, Nietzsche argues that “every healthy society” consists of different physiological types.2 He repeatedly says that “Nature, not Manu,” separates these physiological types of the hierarchical order,3 which is “merely the sanction of a natural order, natural lawfulness of the first rank.” While each type has “its own hygiene, its own realm of work, its own feelings of perfection and mastery” (A 57), this rank order is “the sanctioning of a natural distance between several physiological types,” which are “determined and best developed for different activity,” like “division of labor” (KSA 13:14[221]). Therefore, Nietzsche describes the physiological types divided in a healthy society as “differently gravitating” and “mutually conditioning” types (A 57). In order for a society to be healthy as a whole, individuals should be neither uniform nor scattered, but should be in an organized structure together. This structure is “opposed to an atomistic anarchy.” A “human community is a unity [Einheit],” and “all unity is unity only as organization and co-operation.” In this way “a ruling structure,” which does not exist as one, “means one [Eins]” (KSA 12:2[87]).However, what is it that produces this unity? Nietzsche's envisioned “naturalization of human beings” (KSA 9:11[211]) involves a society where different types live actively in accordance with their nature or respective physiological constitution. However, the existence of different types does not ensure the formation of society as a whole. Individuals of different types with different power will not automatically gather to form a society if they remain merely as individuals. In other words, if there is no social character in nature itself, a society could be seen to be formed “by accident,” as Hobbes understands (42). What then is the basis that allows individuals to be incorporated into the social order? This article explores the social aspect of Nietzsche's understanding of nature, particularly with attention to his idea of affects, which will lead us to the idea of the affective foundation of society in his philosophy.4Nietzsche often describes nature as something chaotic that is elusive, uncer
如果我们考虑到尼采关于我们两种本性相互作用的观点,并且我们理解驱动力是可改变的,很难创造一个单一的位置,从这个位置来判断和优先考虑构成人性的不同驱动力。因此,尼采在1882年之后不再使用“第一本性”这个术语,8相反,他使用“权力意志”这个概念作为理解自然的工具。从这个讨论中,我们了解到尼采重视自然的社会和文化方面,也就是说,人性在社会关系中得到协调和转化。正如我们将看到的,这方面也包括在权力意志的概念中。通过考察这一概念的社会性质,我们可以看到社会形成的基础是什么。当然,权力意志可以用不同的方式来考虑和检验。尼采认为“生命本身就是权力意志”(BGE 13),并探索了“一个本质是权力意志的世界”(BGE 186)。他使用几个术语来考虑权力意志:驱动力、情感、欲望和本能(参见GS 349;6;KSA 39 [6];KSA 12:1 [61];KSA 12:1[59])。这些不同的描述显示了这个概念的多层面,它们来自于生命本身的复杂和多面性,具有“‘权力意志’的多样性:每一个都有多种表达和形式”(KSA 12:1[58])生活以各种方式展现自己,通过思想、欲望、情感等等。换句话说,生活就是这些表达自己的领域。尼采试图从权力意志的角度来理解这些表达,权力意志是“存在的最内在本质”(KSA 13:14[80])。他把这个本质和它的表现都称为“本体”;本质上,权力意志是情感、动力和欲望,表现为情感、动力和欲望。尼采认为,在这些生命表达的基本层面上,驱动力和情感是最重要的。本文更多地关注情感,因为将权力意志与情感联系起来,可以明显地显示其社会特征,并更清楚地揭示与社会形成相关的含义。那么,对权力意志的有效理解是什么呢?尼采谈到“心理上的权力意志”,认为“权力意志是情感的原始形式,所有其他的情感只是它的发展”(《圣歌》13:14[121];参见BGE 23)。他认为“所有的情感都是从一个权力意志中衍生出来的”,并认为它们具有相同的本质(KSA 12:10[57])。在这方面,权力意志是一种情感,它包含在一切情感中,并被表现为一切情感。人们经常讨论驱力对于理解我们的本性是必不可少的。我们现在需要看看情感在什么意义上是自然的组成部分。虽然尼采强调“在每一种思想之下都有一种情感”,并且“情感、思想等的一系列和连续是实际发生的症状”(KSA 12:1[61]),但他并没有提供情感的明确定义。尼采经常用“affect”来指代通常被称为情绪或感觉的东西,比如仇恨、贪婪、嫉妒、勇气、爱和怨恨(BGE 23,192,260;KSA 10:7 [87];13:24[1].2),因此,从广义上讲,学者们将情感理解为“感觉”(Janaway 206;莱特,《道德》第576页;理查森37),或“任何本质上包含赞成或反对态度的心理事件”(波尔纳229)。埃姆登以一种截然不同的立场,强调给予生物学优先权,断言情感不是“离散的精神状态”,而是与斯宾诺莎所说的“情感”(affectus)相同(埃姆登33)。斯宾诺莎对“affect”[affectus]的用法不同于一般意义上的情感,他认为所有的情感都源于三种主要的情感:欲望、快乐和悲伤(III, P11, school)。尼采同样将情感视为身体的一种状态,认为它们源于权力意志,并将“快乐”(欲望)和“不快乐”(不欲望)视为权力意志行动中的“基本事实”(KSA 13:14[80])。然而,由于尼采的文本以及埃姆登的文本中缺乏解释,我们不清楚尼采使用这个术语的意思是否一定受到斯宾诺莎的影响。无论情感是被理解为精神状态还是被强调其生理基础,尼采对情感的评论是解释的工作以及它与权力意志的关系经常被淡化。例如,Gemes认为最好关注驱动力而不是影响,因为“尼采最一贯、最可信地强调的是驱动力是我们本性的基础”,而一种情感或“一种感觉,一种‘感觉是什么’似乎没有正确的时间传播或积极的特征来进行解释”(104)。这种观点主要来源于情感是发生的感觉的理解。 那么,对于驱力的活动来说,情感仅仅是偶然的吗?我们发现尼采经常将“影响”和“驱动”这两个词放在一起使用,例如“灵魂作为驱动和影响的社会结构”[Gesellschaftsbau der tribeund Affekte] (BGE 12)。虽然他似乎并没有明确区分这两者,但学者们已经试图澄清它们之间的区别,尽管并不是特别与权力意志有关。Janaway理解,“驱动力是某种积极行为的相对稳定的倾向,而情感,非常粗略地说,是当一个驱动力在自己内心活跃时的感觉”(214)。同样地,康斯坦斯坦·尼西奥和布兰科在编辑的引言中做出了区分:“尼采所说的‘驱力’是指‘力量’、‘意志之下’或‘权力意志’,它们引导我们的行为朝着满足有机需求的方向发展。‘affect’就是被驱动力驱动的感觉”(16)。Katsafanas将驱动力定义为“产生情感取向的无意识倾向”,从而澄清了驱动力和影响之间的联系(10)。肯定会影响伴随的驱动,我们可以同意这方面的分析。然而,尼采经常把它们放在一起,没有澄清或区分,好像它们是可以互换的。例如,尼采写道:“动物遵循它们的本能和情感:我们是动物. . . .道德只是我们冲动的一种符号语言吗?(王上10:7[76])。后来在另一段中,他假定“道德只是情感的一种手语”(BGE 187);因此,一些学者没有明确区分这两个术语是可以理解的。然而,如果“欲望和情感”不仅仅是一种修辞,它们在某种程度上应该在构成我们的本性中扮演不同的角色,而情感不应该仅仅被认为是欲望的附带因素。首先要指出的是,尼采强调情感的生理基础,它可以在比意识思想和感觉更深的层次上运作。他认为“我们人类情感活动中真正发生的”是“生理运动”(KSA 9:11[128]),而“所有情感”都是“身体的一种状态”(KSA 10:9[44])。由于情感是身体的一种生理运动状态,所以情感不能仅仅被理解为短暂的感觉,而可以具有持续的影响或暂时的传播,如上所述,这与Gemes有关。影响与我们对世界上遇到的事物的生理反应机制有关,这种机制可以在体内根深蒂固。尼采认为,“影响”与“记忆-物质-持续存在和相互作用的形成”(KSA 11:25[514])有关,记忆导致“对特定因果解释的习惯化”(TI ' Errors ' 4)。这种与影响有关的解释观点不仅适用于因果关系,也可以在更广泛的背景下理解。尼采写道,“所有的情感”“首先是身体的一种状态:这是被解释的。”后来的解释自由地产生了状态”(KSA 10:9[44])。这表明,一旦我们对世界做出反应的机制,我们如何解释的机制,在身体中根深蒂固,这种机制或解释就会产生我们的身体状态——所以最终,解释不是发生在事件之后,而是发生在事件发生之前。考虑到这一点,我们需要更密切地研究与驱动力和影响有关的权力意志的概念。在我们有意识的思想和活动的背后是“情感的游戏”(KSA 13:11[113])或“情感的游戏和斗争”(KSA 12:1[75]),这种游戏的性质是agonal (cf. BGE 117)。需要注意的是,尼采并不认为影响或驱动的方式是完全个体的。他在一篇关于斯宾诺莎自我保护思想的笔记中提出了批评:“前利己主义、群体驱力比‘自愿自我保护’更古老。“人首先是作为一
{"title":"Affective Foundation of Society in Nietzsche's Philosophy","authors":"Jihun Jeong","doi":"10.5406/19446489.18.3.01","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/19446489.18.3.01","url":null,"abstract":"Nietzsche believes that the different human types should be allowed to thrive and not be reduced into uniformity, as he says “nothing should be banished more than . . . the approximation and reconciliation” of the different types (KSA 12:10[59]).1 He sees the approximation as a reflection of democratic values and monolithic morality that he opposes. Instead, he believes that humans should be naturalized and allowed to live in accordance with their own nature. To achieve this, Nietzsche proposed “the great politics,” which “makes physiology into the ruler over all other questions” to “breed humanity as a whole” so that “one affirms what one is, one denies what one is not” (KSA 13:25[1]). In this way, Nietzsche thinks the different types should live in accordance with their respective nature.In The Antichrist, Nietzsche argues that “every healthy society” consists of different physiological types.2 He repeatedly says that “Nature, not Manu,” separates these physiological types of the hierarchical order,3 which is “merely the sanction of a natural order, natural lawfulness of the first rank.” While each type has “its own hygiene, its own realm of work, its own feelings of perfection and mastery” (A 57), this rank order is “the sanctioning of a natural distance between several physiological types,” which are “determined and best developed for different activity,” like “division of labor” (KSA 13:14[221]). Therefore, Nietzsche describes the physiological types divided in a healthy society as “differently gravitating” and “mutually conditioning” types (A 57). In order for a society to be healthy as a whole, individuals should be neither uniform nor scattered, but should be in an organized structure together. This structure is “opposed to an atomistic anarchy.” A “human community is a unity [Einheit],” and “all unity is unity only as organization and co-operation.” In this way “a ruling structure,” which does not exist as one, “means one [Eins]” (KSA 12:2[87]).However, what is it that produces this unity? Nietzsche's envisioned “naturalization of human beings” (KSA 9:11[211]) involves a society where different types live actively in accordance with their nature or respective physiological constitution. However, the existence of different types does not ensure the formation of society as a whole. Individuals of different types with different power will not automatically gather to form a society if they remain merely as individuals. In other words, if there is no social character in nature itself, a society could be seen to be formed “by accident,” as Hobbes understands (42). What then is the basis that allows individuals to be incorporated into the social order? This article explores the social aspect of Nietzsche's understanding of nature, particularly with attention to his idea of affects, which will lead us to the idea of the affective foundation of society in his philosophy.4Nietzsche often describes nature as something chaotic that is elusive, uncer","PeriodicalId":42609,"journal":{"name":"Pluralist","volume":"34 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"136203793","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Casting a Vote for Subordination Using a Slur 用诽谤的方式为从属地位投票
4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-01 DOI: 10.5406/19446489.18.3.03
Duckkyun Lee
In this paper, I develop an account of slurs focusing on their two underappreciated features. The first underappreciated feature is what I call their “communal nature.” Slurs are communal. The meaning of a slur depends on the existence of a significant number of people who are bigoted against the target. When this condition is not satisfied, a slur loses its power to offend. This can be seen when we consider how philosophers choose examples of slurs to avoid offending people. For example, Williamson, in his essay “Reference, Inference and the Semantics of Pejoratives,” uses a slur for Germans as his main example. What makes the slur for Germans a safe example to use is the fact that there is no widespread bigotry against Germans in any Anglophone country. Had there been strong enmity between Germans and the people in the Anglophone countries, even if Williamson had chosen an outdated slur, his example would not have been such a safe choice. Slurs are words that bigots use to offend and harm the people they are bigoted against. When there are no bigots, neither are there slurs.The focus on the communal nature of slurs leads to the second underappreciated feature of slurs. A bigot does not use a slur just to express his beliefs or feelings, but to subordinate his target. To subordinate others, a bigot needs to cooperate and coordinate with other bigots. In this paper, I will propose a mechanism for how slurs work as a tool for coordinating subordination. To account for the communal and subordinating nature of slurs, I turn to speech act theory and explain what kind of illocutionary act is performed when one uses a slur.1My proposal is to understand utterances made using a slur, or slurring,2 as an act of casting a vote for ranking the target as socially inferior. On this view, a slur is a conventional tool used to cast a vote demanding the subordination of its target. The considerations that motivate this view are as follows: First, the uses of a slur are the results of consciously choosing it over its neutral counterpart. By explicitly avoiding a neutral counterpart term, one can show their support for fellow bigots and the willingness to participate in whatever activity they do. Second, the point of using a slur does not seem to be exhausted by its role of expressing the bigot's negative beliefs about the target. We can see this when we consider that the way to fight a slur is to impose strict prohibitions against its use, not by objecting to the content of the slurring utterance. This can be better explained when we understand the slur as a conventional tool for the performance of a certain type of action, rather than a word that has distinctive descriptive content different from the descriptive content of its neutral counterpart. Finally, the point of some speech acts is not just expressing the state of the mind of the speaker. The point of some speech acts is to change what is the case in society. To make an utterance using a slur seems to fal
在本文中,我开发了一个关于诽谤的帐户,重点关注它们的两个未被重视的特征。第一个未被重视的特点是我称之为“公共性质”。辱骂是公共的。诽谤的意义取决于存在相当数量的人对目标抱有偏见。当这个条件不满足时,诽谤就失去了冒犯的力量。当我们考虑哲学家如何选择诽谤的例子来避免冒犯别人时,就可以看到这一点。例如,威廉姆森在他的文章“参考,推理和贬义词的语义”中,使用了对德国人的诽谤作为他的主要例子。对德国人的诽谤之所以是一个安全的例子,是因为在任何英语国家都没有对德国人的普遍偏见。如果德国人和英语国家的人民之间存在强烈的敌意,即使威廉姆森选择了一个过时的诽谤,他的榜样也不会是这样一个安全的选择。污言秽语是偏执狂用来冒犯和伤害他们所反对的人的词语。没有偏执狂,也就没有诽谤。对辱骂的公共性质的关注导致了辱骂的第二个未被重视的特征。偏执狂不只是为了表达自己的信仰或感受而使用诽谤,而是为了使他的目标屈从。为了使他人服从,偏执者需要与其他偏执者合作和协调。在本文中,我将提出一种机制,如何诽谤工作作为协调下属的工具。为了解释辱骂的共同性和从属性,我转向言语行为理论,并解释当一个人使用辱骂时,会执行什么样的言外行为。我的建议是将使用侮辱性言语或含糊不清的话语理解为一种投票行为,将目标置于社会地位低下的地位。根据这种观点,诽谤是用来投票要求其目标服从的常规工具。促使这一观点的考虑如下:首先,使用诽谤是有意识地选择它而不是其中性对立物的结果。通过明确地避免使用中立的对应词,人们可以表明他们对其他偏执狂的支持,并愿意参与他们所做的任何活动。其次,使用诽谤的意义似乎并没有因为它表达偏执狂对目标的负面信念而耗尽。当我们考虑到打击诽谤的方式是严格禁止使用它,而不是反对诽谤言论的内容时,我们就可以看到这一点。当我们将诽谤理解为执行某种行为的常规工具,而不是具有与其中性对应的描述性内容不同的独特描述性内容的单词时,可以更好地解释这一点。最后,一些言语行为的目的不仅仅是表达说话者的思想状态。一些言语行为的目的是改变社会现状。用污语说话似乎属于后一种言语行为。如果偏执狂不参与创造一个他们的目标不如他们的社会的计划,他们会做什么呢?这一考虑表明,使用诽谤的话语可能属于塞尔称之为声明的言语行为(分类法361-68)。作为一种宣言,模糊化是一种改变社会的尝试,使目标处于从属地位。如果选举被理解为一个过程,在这个过程中,人们通过表明他们支持或反对一项提案的立场,集体决定社会应该发生什么,那么诽谤可以被理解为对选举偏执者的提议投下一票,以使他们的目标服从。我认为,这种说法可以更好地解释为什么如果没有大量的偏执狂,诽谤就不能成为诽谤,以及它是如何被用来协调偏执狂使其目标服从的努力的。论文按以下顺序进行。在第2节中,我简要地描述了我的帐户的目标。在许多不同的贬义词中,我的描述试图调查那些不是针对具有某些特征的个人,而是针对整体群体的诽谤,以及那些有中立对应术语的诽谤。在第3节中,我将详细解释我所说的诽谤具有共同性和从属性的说法是什么意思,以及为什么我认为现有的说法没有给出令人满意的解释。在第4节中,我发展并证明了我自己的建议,即诽谤是执行投票服从的言外行为的传统工具。把含糊不清理解为一种对从属地位的投票行为,可以帮助我们了解社会等级制度是如何形成的;含糊其辞符合重要条件,可以算作投票行为;一个典型的对抗口齿不清的策略也支持我的建议。 最后,在第5节中,我将简要展示我的建议如何能够解释slurs的其他重要特征,就像任何其他竞争账户一样。特别是,我将概述两个重要的解释性挑战:污语的投射行为和我们对带有污语的句子的真值的相互冲突的直觉。在阐述我的观点之前,我想澄清一下我认为什么是诽谤。首先,slurs是针对群体而非个人的贬义词。他们针对不同的群体:种族群体、宗教群体、职业群体、有特定性取向的群体等等。这区分了诽谤和针对个人的贬义词。例如,像“混蛋”这样的词不被认为是诽谤,因为没有社会认可的群体与之相关。其次,slurs是与中性对应词搭配的贬义词。这区别于其他没有相应的中性对应物的群体目标贬义词。例如,“皮条客”是对特定人群的贬义,但由于它缺乏一个中立的对应词,所以我在本文中不将其视为诽谤。Slurs是贬义词。他们非常无礼。是什么让它们的使用如此令人反感?为了回答这个问题,让我们从slurs的一些明显特征开始。污言秽语是偏执狂用的词。诽谤对他们有什么好处?最终,使偏执者成为偏执者的原因是,他有兴趣让他所偏执的人的生活更加艰难。诽谤可能有各种各样的用途,但有一点是肯定的,那就是它是偏执狂实现这一目标的一种手段。诽谤有助于实现这一目标,因为它帮助偏执狂相互认识并相互协调。当一个偏执狂使用侮辱性言论时,他非常清楚还有其他使用侮辱性言论的人,而且通过使用侮辱性言论,他也加入了他们的行列。这些特征表明,污言秽语是偏执狂与其他偏执狂一起创造一个社会的词语,在这个社会中,他们的目标是从属的。我相信,到目前为止,我所说的对于大多数从事诽谤工作的人来说是可以接受的。然而,到目前为止提出的关于诽谤的现有说法并没有对这两个特征给出令人满意的解释。本节的目的就是要说明这一点,并激发对替代帐户的需求。尽管对侮辱性言语的描述多种多样,但我们可以从言语行为理论的角度对现有的描述进行分类,看看每种侮辱性言语认为可以用包含侮辱性言语的话语进行什么样的言语行为。为了简明地概述现有帐户,我将使用Sam、Chris和Alex之间的以下假设对话来说明它们。(在这里和下面,为了避免提及诽谤,我将使用以下符号系统来谈论诽谤。“S*”是对一个群体的蔑称。“G*”是一个中立的对应术语,指的是“S*”所针对的群体。星号用于区分针对不同群体的诽谤。“S*”和“S**”是两种不同的诽谤,针对两个不同的群体,G*和G**。)在这段对话中,Sam回答了Chris的问题,并给了她关于新老板群体身份的信息。Alex除了回答Chris的问题外,还断言Sam提供的信息不正确,并提供了新老板的团体身份的不同信息。然而,上述对对话的描述是对对话中发生的事情的极度扭曲的描述。他们不仅交换了关于新老板的信息。通过使用污言秽语,他们对新老板做了一些不好的事情,G**和G**,这应该被冒犯除了交换有关新老板的团体身份的信息外,所有关于诽谤的描述都试图找出他们做了什么值得冒犯的事情。根据现有的说法,他们除了交换情报外,所做的事情主要分为两类。首先,他们言语的冒犯性在于言语层面。亚历克斯、克里斯和山姆使用侮辱性词语的行为违反了我们在表达有意义的话语时选择词语的准则这并不是说他们的侮辱性话语有一种特殊的非言语力量,足以引起冒犯。问题是,他们违反了禁止使用诽谤的规范。这就是为什么他们的话语如此令人反感,就像在正式讲话中使用脏话一样令人反感。使用侮辱性语言的言语行为并不重要。其次,我们可以将冒犯性理解为来自使用它进行的特定的言外行为。构成冒犯的不仅仅是选择禁忌词的行为,还有使用禁忌词的行为。 采用这种方法的叙述可以再次大致分为三个子类,这取决于他们认为使用诽谤进行的行为是哪种言外行为。首先,使用诽谤是一种传递关于目标的一些虚假、贬损信息的行为。尽管每个人传达贬谤信息的确切机制各不相同,但他们在谈话中除了交换有关新老板群体身份的信息外,还在传递G*
{"title":"Casting a Vote for Subordination Using a Slur","authors":"Duckkyun Lee","doi":"10.5406/19446489.18.3.03","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/19446489.18.3.03","url":null,"abstract":"In this paper, I develop an account of slurs focusing on their two underappreciated features. The first underappreciated feature is what I call their “communal nature.” Slurs are communal. The meaning of a slur depends on the existence of a significant number of people who are bigoted against the target. When this condition is not satisfied, a slur loses its power to offend. This can be seen when we consider how philosophers choose examples of slurs to avoid offending people. For example, Williamson, in his essay “Reference, Inference and the Semantics of Pejoratives,” uses a slur for Germans as his main example. What makes the slur for Germans a safe example to use is the fact that there is no widespread bigotry against Germans in any Anglophone country. Had there been strong enmity between Germans and the people in the Anglophone countries, even if Williamson had chosen an outdated slur, his example would not have been such a safe choice. Slurs are words that bigots use to offend and harm the people they are bigoted against. When there are no bigots, neither are there slurs.The focus on the communal nature of slurs leads to the second underappreciated feature of slurs. A bigot does not use a slur just to express his beliefs or feelings, but to subordinate his target. To subordinate others, a bigot needs to cooperate and coordinate with other bigots. In this paper, I will propose a mechanism for how slurs work as a tool for coordinating subordination. To account for the communal and subordinating nature of slurs, I turn to speech act theory and explain what kind of illocutionary act is performed when one uses a slur.1My proposal is to understand utterances made using a slur, or slurring,2 as an act of casting a vote for ranking the target as socially inferior. On this view, a slur is a conventional tool used to cast a vote demanding the subordination of its target. The considerations that motivate this view are as follows: First, the uses of a slur are the results of consciously choosing it over its neutral counterpart. By explicitly avoiding a neutral counterpart term, one can show their support for fellow bigots and the willingness to participate in whatever activity they do. Second, the point of using a slur does not seem to be exhausted by its role of expressing the bigot's negative beliefs about the target. We can see this when we consider that the way to fight a slur is to impose strict prohibitions against its use, not by objecting to the content of the slurring utterance. This can be better explained when we understand the slur as a conventional tool for the performance of a certain type of action, rather than a word that has distinctive descriptive content different from the descriptive content of its neutral counterpart. Finally, the point of some speech acts is not just expressing the state of the mind of the speaker. The point of some speech acts is to change what is the case in society. To make an utterance using a slur seems to fal","PeriodicalId":42609,"journal":{"name":"Pluralist","volume":"136 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"136203781","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Dramatization of Absolute Idealism: Gabriel Marcel and F. H. Bradley 绝对理想主义的戏剧化:加布里埃尔·马塞尔和f·h·布拉德利
4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-01 DOI: 10.5406/19446489.18.3.02
Joseph Gamache
This paper consists of an observation, a suggestion, and an illustration. First, the observation: in the English-language literature on the philosophy of Gabriel Marcel, there is, so far as I have discovered, a lack of attention paid to the relationship between Marcel and the British philosopher F. H. Bradley (1846–1924).1 Why might be this be? I speculate (this is not the suggestion previously advertised) that the following are possible reasons for this omission. First, Bradley's influence is neglected in favor of what some might regard as the more obvious influence of Josiah Royce (1855–1916). After all, Marcel wrote a series of articles on Royce early in his career that were subsequently published as a monograph and eventually translated into English as Royce's Metaphysics. Second, there is the confluence of narratives concerning Marcel's philosophical development and the dethronement of Bradley and of idealism by figures such as Russell and Moore. According to the former narrative, Marcel's idealist phase ends with the first part of the Metaphysical Journal (about 1915).2 Since Bradley is less widely read these days and is treated simply as one more (even if the chief) representative of British idealism, it is easy to infer that, when he shed his idealism, Marcel also shed any connection with Bradley.But all that I have achieved thus far is the articulation of two reasons why people interested in Marcel have not also been interested in Bradley. Are there any reasons to believe that Marcel was influenced by Bradley in a positive way? Here, we can do no better than to gather some selected texts. In his preface to the English translation of the Metaphysical Journal, Marcel writes: Meditations on the implications of the word “with” and on metaphysical fruitfulness must in my opinion be counted among the most valuable contributions of the Metaphysical Journal. Later, in the collected writings published under the title Du Refus à l'invocation [translated into English as Creative Fidelity], I was to submit to similar analyses the relations, or rather the super-relations, implies by the French word “chez.” Here, unless I am mistaken, I made use of the word super-relation for the first time. The vigorous criticism made by F. H. Bradley (in Appearance and Reality) of the current notion of relation—considered as a pure makeshift—is there extended, and I think I will be never be able to recognize too explicitly what I owe to that great thinker. (Marcel, Metaphysical Journal xii)In the foreword to his pre-Metaphysical Journal works published as Philosophical Fragments 1909–1914, Marcel writes of his early (idealist) phase: I find it hard to understand today how, during the years immediately following the reception of my aggregation degree, and even after having had the privilege of hearing Henri Bergson at the College de France, I could still feel the need to undertake a groping inquiry in such a rarefied atmosphere and with the help of tools borrowed fro
每个号角都有哪些马塞利亚主题?第一个角对应的是马塞尔对他所谓的“抽象精神”的恐惧。第二个角对应了马塞尔对二十世纪身份形式激增的恐慌。困境的第一个角(将A简化为一个属性)在现实生活中被马塞尔称为“抽象精神”的东西戏剧化了。抽象精神表现在对形式的主张上:一个人(a)只不过是Y(她的某些属性)。在其鼎盛时期,抽象精神将所有的人简化为“大众”或“暴民”,在这一点上,抽象实现了“实用主义的存在”,因为它成为一种不可忽视的力量,甚至被机会主义的领导人利用(马塞尔,《反对大众社会的人》116)。除了这些邪恶的后果之外,抽象精神的问题在于,它暗示了一种分离的方法来处理受害者的其他属性,这种方法,无论采用哪种方式,都涉及伪造另一个人的身份。因为如果一个人a除了Y什么都不是,那么,如果这个实践抽象精神的人是一致的,那么他的受害者的所有其他属性必须要么被否定(a除了Y什么都不是,所以她不能也是Z),要么简单地以片面的方式相互认同(a既是Y又是Z,但Y和Z实际上是一样的)。所谓“片面的时尚”,我的意思是,正如上一段所述,这种认同是通过“是________,只不过是________”这句话进行的。因此,如果斯密仅仅被认为是一个天主教徒,那么,要么他的其他属性被当作无关的而搁置一边,要么他的所有其他属性都同样被归结为他是一个天主教徒。后一种可能性表现为倾向于只通过关于他们的一条信息来解释其他人。知道斯密是天主教徒,我们就可以把他的天主教信仰理解为他是天主教徒,把他的神学著作理解为他是天主教徒的表现,把他对英国国教内部某些发展的反对理解为他是天主教徒的表现,等等。简而言之,即使没有对属性的字面识别(如史密斯的天主教只是他是天主教徒,或者天主教只是天主教徒),也有一种解释还原论,具有相同的效果。抽象的精神不仅说明了布拉德利困境的第一个角(将A简化为一个属性),而且还说明了上面讨论的第二个和第三个逻辑警告:简单地识别一个连接的连接(史密斯的天主教和他的罗马天主教),并将一个质量作为一个整体减少到单独考虑的相同质量我们需要的是,布拉德利关于矛盾和结合的文章也提出了这一点,我们将史密斯视为一个完整的人,被他的属性所限定,这些属性在他身上都不存在,仅仅作为类型。简而言之:斯密是一个人,而不是不同类型的人或更广泛意义上的不同品质的典范的集合在讨论布拉德利关于关系的观点时,我将回到这些主题;现在,我转向马塞尔对这个困境的第二个角的戏剧化描述:将A简化为他的几个(也许是全部)属性。布拉德利的逻辑警告将再次伴随着我们。在吉福德系列讲座的第五讲中,Marcel探讨了身份形式的存在和日益流行。他让我印象深刻的是,他特别关注这些形式的伪装,以真正识别人,这种伪装与一个人对自己是谁的感觉之间的紧张关系,以及这些形式对人们在20世纪和21世纪如何理解自己的不良影响。这里,为了我们的目的,是中心文本:我没有意识到自己是一个人,被输入到各种标题下:星座,出生,职业,等等。然而,我在这些标题下输入的所有内容都是严格正确的。(马塞尔《生命的奥秘》)这些表格的自命不凡之处在于,根据标题下输入的信息,将表格上输入的信息结合起来就足以识别出一个人。Marcel想象着被一个公务员问他是不是那个回答了表单生成的连词的“某某先生”。如果他(马塞尔)回答“不是”,那么公务员就会得出结论,要么马塞尔疯了,要么他是用假身份通过的。这个没有思考的公务员从来没有想到,这个连词是由关于Marcel的真句组成的,但尽管如此,Marcel并不是最终的连词。这就引出了我所说的马塞尔编号论证。公务员的问题是针对某个人的。我们可以给这个人编号,比如,98号。 他们最终的非实在性,这并不意味着关系不是表象,或者关系是幻觉,或者关系思维在人类知识的进步中既不是必要的也不是有用的);(二)关系既不单纯是外在的,也不单纯是内在的(或者积极地说,一种关系必须同时具有外在性和内在性的标志)。(C1)的论点在于明确了困扰关系的几个矛盾。这些可以简单地表述如下:(1)1:一个关系既是完整的关系情境,又不是完整的关系情境。(2)2a:一个关系既限定了它的条件,又不限定了它的条件。(3)2b:一个关系既限定了它的条件,又不限定了它的条件。一个关系既存在又不存在整个关系情境的原因,与一个关系既存在又不存在、被其条件限定(既限定又不限定)的原因是相同的。因为任何实际的关系都不是抽象的,而关系是抽象的,这正是关系思维的过程所要求的。为了了解这一点,让我们以父/子关系为例。对这种关系情况的分析产生以下组成部分:父关系、子关系和父-子关系。布拉德利的主要论点是,这种把整体分解为部分的分析所产生的“关系”并不是实际的关系(《关系》2:636,2:638)一个人与他的孩子的父母关系并不是通过分析得出的抽象概念,“父母的”,因为这种抽象概念不能像亲子关系那样限定父母与孩子的关系。换句话说:关系应该限定它们的条件,但是如果我们把关系等同于分析的产物,它们就不能做它们应该做的事情。因此,我们似乎必须将关系与整个关系情境等同起来。然而,有了这种认同,我们就落入了另一个陷阱。如果我们从事关系思维,我们需要那些不能简化为其关系的术语,以及那些不能简化为其术语的关系。换句话说,要进行关系思维,要把世界解释为关系中的术语之一,关系就必须是与术语无关的东西,这似乎要求我们把它们与分析的抽象产物——在本例中,与“父-物”关系——等同起来。关系,由其条件限定并限定其条件,是整个关系情境;但是关系,既不受条件的限制,也不受条件的限制,只是分析的抽象产物。我们也不能简单地把它们区分开来,用两种“关系”的意义来解决矛盾。因为对于关系思维来说,作为整个关系情境的“关系”感是不存在的。换句话说:关系思维与它的抽象性一起工作,并以关系前的、直接的经验或对所讨论的统一性的感觉为基础。因此,任何以这种方式解决矛盾的尝试,实际上并没有给我们留下两种意义上的“关系”。相反,它一方面留给我们抽象的分析关系,另一方面又完全没有关系,因为没有思维的产物。换句话说,对于话语思维来说,整个关系情境必须被分解成关系中的术语,因此,话语思维没有两种“关系”的意义。它用它手头上唯一的工具来操作,而这本身并不能完成联系的工作,并且不可避免地依赖于对所讨论的统一性的前话语经验或感觉(布拉德利,“关系”2:637)因此,对于布拉德利来说,要真正理解这种关系情况,需要进一步发展经验(即绝对)。前面的论证可以映射到内部关系和外部关系的区别,以及布拉德利的结论,即没有绝对的外部关系或绝对的内部关系。作为一种外部关系,亲子关系(或任何你选择的例子)不能把它的术语联系起来。如果把关系设想为一种外在于它的规定的东西,那么关系就需要有一种与规定相联系的进一步的关系。这就是臭名昭著且被误解的连锁论证,它首次出现在《表象与现实》的第三章中。需要注意的是,布拉德利本人并不赞同关系的物化,他只是简单地提出了将关系视为绝对外部的结果。没有绝对的外部关系,因为这种关系不能把它们的条件联系起来。绝对的内部关系呢?已经说得够多了,这个问题应该已经考虑进去了。内部关系(那些影响它们的术语,即限定它们的条件和被它们限定的条件)可以解释它们术语的“团结”,但它们不能站在它们之间。 既然我们需要在各项的关系之外,在各项
{"title":"The Dramatization of Absolute Idealism: Gabriel Marcel and F. H. Bradley","authors":"Joseph Gamache","doi":"10.5406/19446489.18.3.02","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/19446489.18.3.02","url":null,"abstract":"This paper consists of an observation, a suggestion, and an illustration. First, the observation: in the English-language literature on the philosophy of Gabriel Marcel, there is, so far as I have discovered, a lack of attention paid to the relationship between Marcel and the British philosopher F. H. Bradley (1846–1924).1 Why might be this be? I speculate (this is not the suggestion previously advertised) that the following are possible reasons for this omission. First, Bradley's influence is neglected in favor of what some might regard as the more obvious influence of Josiah Royce (1855–1916). After all, Marcel wrote a series of articles on Royce early in his career that were subsequently published as a monograph and eventually translated into English as Royce's Metaphysics. Second, there is the confluence of narratives concerning Marcel's philosophical development and the dethronement of Bradley and of idealism by figures such as Russell and Moore. According to the former narrative, Marcel's idealist phase ends with the first part of the Metaphysical Journal (about 1915).2 Since Bradley is less widely read these days and is treated simply as one more (even if the chief) representative of British idealism, it is easy to infer that, when he shed his idealism, Marcel also shed any connection with Bradley.But all that I have achieved thus far is the articulation of two reasons why people interested in Marcel have not also been interested in Bradley. Are there any reasons to believe that Marcel was influenced by Bradley in a positive way? Here, we can do no better than to gather some selected texts. In his preface to the English translation of the Metaphysical Journal, Marcel writes: Meditations on the implications of the word “with” and on metaphysical fruitfulness must in my opinion be counted among the most valuable contributions of the Metaphysical Journal. Later, in the collected writings published under the title Du Refus à l'invocation [translated into English as Creative Fidelity], I was to submit to similar analyses the relations, or rather the super-relations, implies by the French word “chez.” Here, unless I am mistaken, I made use of the word super-relation for the first time. The vigorous criticism made by F. H. Bradley (in Appearance and Reality) of the current notion of relation—considered as a pure makeshift—is there extended, and I think I will be never be able to recognize too explicitly what I owe to that great thinker. (Marcel, Metaphysical Journal xii)In the foreword to his pre-Metaphysical Journal works published as Philosophical Fragments 1909–1914, Marcel writes of his early (idealist) phase: I find it hard to understand today how, during the years immediately following the reception of my aggregation degree, and even after having had the privilege of hearing Henri Bergson at the College de France, I could still feel the need to undertake a groping inquiry in such a rarefied atmosphere and with the help of tools borrowed fro","PeriodicalId":42609,"journal":{"name":"Pluralist","volume":"53 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"136206374","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Philosophy and the Modern African American Freedom Struggle: A Freedom Gaze 哲学与现代非裔美国人的自由斗争:自由的视角
4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-01 DOI: 10.5406/19446489.18.3.05
Kordell Dixon
Philosophy and the Modern African American Freedom Struggle begins with a clear and concise establishment of its aim: to analyze and expand upon those figures mentioned when discussing the academic project of studying black people. Neal broadens the account of black scholars examining racialized existence by centering his work on the modern era and its initiator W. E. B Du Bois. Neal develops an ethnic reflective canon that documents the long history of black thinkers attempting to define their blackness and advance the conception of freedom. This book does an excellent job of capturing the genealogical structure of the struggle for freedom. Within the work, Neal denotes that all relevant figures in this tradition are freedom gazers. These gazers are spectators of a radically imagined future liberated from the oppressive systems that encumber the persecuted. Du Bois's approach to freedom gazing uses academic training to examine his blackness and inevitably to solve the “race problem.” What Neal provides the reader is a road map of the intellectual work of black scholars. This road map details the common themes among black thinkers and how these themes relate to Du Bois. Neal's intricate network of philosophers uses their experience and their expertise to write about what is necessary for black people to obtain freedom. Neal composes a complex and remarkable catalog of black scholars that demonstrates the interconnectedness and progression of black thought on oppression and liberation.In the second chapter, Neal elucidates why Du Bois is chosen as the inaugurator of the modern era. As a formally educated black man, Du Bois questions his experience and what tethers him to oppression. Neal uses Du Bois as a focal point, not because Du Bois is the first black person to document their struggle with their racialized existence, but because he believes that Du Bois is the first scholar to analyze the black experience completely. The holistic nature of Du Bois's study of the existential conflict that race can manifest within its subjects allows Du Bois's analysis to be used as a tool to unify other works that discuss race and the struggle for freedom. Neal expresses how other scholars such as Frederick Douglass, Martin Delany, and Anna Julia Cooper all had work that takes up a similar task as Du Bois's but lacks the fullness of Du Bois's study. Here, Neal does not articulate clearly how these figures are inadequate with respect to their work. It could be argued that each scholar named could be said to have accomplished a task similar to that of Du Bois. However, how these figures are studied throughout different disciplines gives the impression that their examination of race and freedom is much more focused on one specific field. This point speaks to how we interpret the work of these scholars and not to these scholars’ work itself. Neal proceeds to describe Du Bois as a freedom gazer and explains how Du Bois's imagining of black persons as freed would al
相反,他关心的是压迫者是否遵守法律。黑人的价值是显而易见的,运用法律来捍卫他们的权利应该是一个自然的结果。然而,黑人人性的贬低使他们的政治权利和社会权利得以逃避。在哈里森看来,黑人存在的社会真理及其价值应该得到维护,每个人都有责任相应地尊重这种价值。尼尔将洛克和哈里森描述为如何理解黑人价值的两个极端。此外,尼尔声称费里斯是这两个极点之间的中间值。费里斯对黑人生命的价值持存在主义的理想主义立场。尼尔解释说,费里斯的观众和哈里森一样,都是黑人社区。然而,与哈里森不同的是,费里斯认为摆脱肉体和精神奴役残余的关键在于黑人的思想。费里斯支持这样一种理论,即黑人必须认识到自己的价值,而不是被白人至上主义的非人性化宣传所陶醉,驳斥这种宣传必然是一项精神任务。尼尔认出洛克、哈里森和费里斯是“新黑人”三合会。作为自由的观察者,他们发起了关于激进社会变革的对话,这导致了鼓舞人心的艺术家和其他学者。在第四章中,尼尔调查了有关黑人影响的问题。黑色被表示为他者性或差异性。尼尔强调,黑人是一种二分法的结构,当白人社会以自己为中心时,黑人就会被边缘化。尼尔在本章中介绍的三人组是夸梅·恩克鲁玛、马丁·路德·金和霍华德·瑟曼。这群学者回答了黑人如何影响其研究对象的问题。尼尔通过将奥利弗·克伦威尔·考克斯和弗朗茨·法农的作品置于与另类主题相一致的语境中,为撰写种族反思经典的学者目录做出了贡献。考克斯和法农详细描述了他们作为黑人学生在白人占主导地位的空间(法国)生活的经历,并阐明了他们的种族身份是如何导致社会心理和文化隔阂的。尼尔向观众传达了这种隔阂如何影响种族关系中的双方。随着尼尔介绍夸梅·恩克鲁玛的奖学金,隔阂的主题继续下去。对Nkrumah来说,以一种规范的方式对待其他黑人导致个人被迫消除作为存在属性的黑人。没有意识到种族主义两极的阴险本质的健忘黑人可能会成为压迫性意识形态寄生本质的牺牲品。恩克鲁玛认为,这导致被压迫者成为非人性化制度的代言人。接下来,尼尔引用了霍华德·瑟曼,他声称种族的差异性在形而上学上和社会上把白人和黑人都束缚住了。在这里,尼尔讨论了另类的后果之一:种族隔离。当白人和黑人被种族认同的两极性所束缚时,白人社会仍然可以在人类的位置上休息。作为人类,白人群体获得了作为人的所有物质和政治利益。另一方面,另类将黑人牢牢地置于非人或次等人的范畴。这种二分法为黑人社区的隔离辩护,因为隔离限制了黑人获得为人类保留的物质、社会和政治资源。最后,尼尔介绍了马丁·路德·金,并描述了在金的观点下,另类如何导致美国社会的分裂。金认为黑人对人类概念的疏远注定了美国的停滞。殖民主义和奴役造成了黑人身体上的伤痕,并建立了一个无人驾驶的压迫制度。这些系统是由其他黑人社区预测和维持的。对于马丁·路德·金来说,如果我们能够拆除另类,我们就可以开始拆除压迫性的制度。尼尔改善了他的读者对黑人存在的理解,并通过将读者置于一个关于黑人的社会地位如何导致各种形式的非人化以及现代学者如何想象一种脱离这种另类的存在的话语中来扩展它。尼尔在书的最后一章讨论了现代结束的地点。尼尔继续黑社会的主题;然而,Neal没有使用individual。相反,尼尔提供了黑人思想家的三个担忧,他们表明现代时代正在结束。尼尔用这个三位一体来解决的第一个问题是是否有一种黑人自由的概念不包括黑人社区的概念。 第二:日益扩大的阶级分化如何阻碍了争取自由的斗争?最后:保留黑人的概念会阻碍进步吗?尼尔分析了这些问题,并得出结论:与生存作斗争会使人陷入绝望,并使自己陷入个人主义,使黑人社区支离破碎。尼尔汇集了一大批黑人学者,他们为黑人争取自由的历史做出了巨大贡献。尼尔理解黑人激进思想的复杂性,并认识到知识分子的美丽可以吸引读者。因此,他优先展示了理论、信念和研究是如何交织在一起的。因此,他绘制了一幅深刻的地图,描绘了黑人生存哲学思想的转变和对解放的渴望。虽然我强烈推荐尼尔的书在课堂上使用和作为参考,但我认为对提到的学者的贡献的讨论过于狭隘。尼尔的重点是在整个现代学者的工作之间的关系。由于共同的主题是黑暗和对自由的渴望,每位学者都相互联系;然而,所提供的奖学金仅足以建立这些联系,更多的背景知识将有助于读者的经验。尽管如此,尼尔所呈现的优秀作品无疑将推动关于现代黑人学者的论述。
{"title":"Philosophy and the Modern African American Freedom Struggle: A Freedom Gaze","authors":"Kordell Dixon","doi":"10.5406/19446489.18.3.05","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/19446489.18.3.05","url":null,"abstract":"Philosophy and the Modern African American Freedom Struggle begins with a clear and concise establishment of its aim: to analyze and expand upon those figures mentioned when discussing the academic project of studying black people. Neal broadens the account of black scholars examining racialized existence by centering his work on the modern era and its initiator W. E. B Du Bois. Neal develops an ethnic reflective canon that documents the long history of black thinkers attempting to define their blackness and advance the conception of freedom. This book does an excellent job of capturing the genealogical structure of the struggle for freedom. Within the work, Neal denotes that all relevant figures in this tradition are freedom gazers. These gazers are spectators of a radically imagined future liberated from the oppressive systems that encumber the persecuted. Du Bois's approach to freedom gazing uses academic training to examine his blackness and inevitably to solve the “race problem.” What Neal provides the reader is a road map of the intellectual work of black scholars. This road map details the common themes among black thinkers and how these themes relate to Du Bois. Neal's intricate network of philosophers uses their experience and their expertise to write about what is necessary for black people to obtain freedom. Neal composes a complex and remarkable catalog of black scholars that demonstrates the interconnectedness and progression of black thought on oppression and liberation.In the second chapter, Neal elucidates why Du Bois is chosen as the inaugurator of the modern era. As a formally educated black man, Du Bois questions his experience and what tethers him to oppression. Neal uses Du Bois as a focal point, not because Du Bois is the first black person to document their struggle with their racialized existence, but because he believes that Du Bois is the first scholar to analyze the black experience completely. The holistic nature of Du Bois's study of the existential conflict that race can manifest within its subjects allows Du Bois's analysis to be used as a tool to unify other works that discuss race and the struggle for freedom. Neal expresses how other scholars such as Frederick Douglass, Martin Delany, and Anna Julia Cooper all had work that takes up a similar task as Du Bois's but lacks the fullness of Du Bois's study. Here, Neal does not articulate clearly how these figures are inadequate with respect to their work. It could be argued that each scholar named could be said to have accomplished a task similar to that of Du Bois. However, how these figures are studied throughout different disciplines gives the impression that their examination of race and freedom is much more focused on one specific field. This point speaks to how we interpret the work of these scholars and not to these scholars’ work itself. Neal proceeds to describe Du Bois as a freedom gazer and explains how Du Bois's imagining of black persons as freed would al","PeriodicalId":42609,"journal":{"name":"Pluralist","volume":"18 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"136203795","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Collective Regret and Guilt and Heroic Agency: A Pro-Existential Approach 集体遗憾、内疚和英雄代理:一种亲存在主义的方法
4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-01 DOI: 10.5406/19446489.18.3.04
Ionut Untea
Studies in social psychology point out that feelings of guilt are more likely than feelings of regret to occur in an interpersonal context (Wagner et al. 1) marked by “interpersonal harm,” or harm done to others (Berndsen et al. 55, 66). In keeping with these studies, in social ontology, regret seems to involve an evaluation of the kind of wrongdoing that is out of someone's control (Konzelmann Ziv 488), while the feeling of guilt implies the self-attribution of blame over something that is connected, even in a loose manner, to a blameworthy action (Gilbert, “Group Wrongs” 65, 66n3).In order to advance the argument of the reasonableness of a person's feeling of guilt if that person is part of a group that has acted wrongfully, Margaret Gilbert distinguishes between feelings of personal guilt and feelings of collective guilt (“Group Wrongs” 76), with the latter still impacting on the individual feelings of guilt. From this point of view, a person may be “personally guiltless,” but can still reasonably feel guilt if that person's group behaves in a morally unacceptable way (“Group Wrongs” 66). By distinguishing between personal and collective guilt, Gilbert intends to give an “intelligible” dimension to what she calls Jaspers's “dilemma” (“Collective Guilt” 135, 136). She emphasizes Karl Jaspers's hesitation in categorizing his own feeling of guilt for what his people have done: “There is a way that he ‘cannot help feeling’ which is ‘rationally refutable’” (Gilbert “Collective Guilt” 135; Jaspers 74). As a philosopher, Gilbert argues, Jaspers finds this existential dilemma “extremely problematic” (“Collective Guilt” 135). Nonetheless, Gilbert also concedes that these two types of guilt may be difficult to distinguish in regard to their “phenomenological conditions” at the level of the “pangs and twinges” experienced by each person, but rather on the basis of the “judgment or thought” involved with that feeling (“Collective Guilt” 135).Gilbert argues that “it is indeed intelligible for group members to feel guilt over the action in question” by virtue of what she calls a “foundational joint commitment,” which brings together a number of people to “intend as a body” to carry out certain actions (“Collective Guilt” 136). Although not committed to the goal of showing the intelligibility of the feeling of membership guilt as is Gilbert, I favor the acceptance of a kind of reasonableness of such a feeling, even when it conserves its “rationally refutable” character. This even applies when membership guilt may not so easily be distinguished from personal guilt. Gilbert sees joint commitment as “authority-creating,” in the sense that “a person or body” may become “authorized” to apply the collective intention to the concrete settings. This is realized by making decisions for the entire group, thus bringing the collective intention into effect (“Collective Guilt” 136). This joint commitment becomes binding for individual members of the group since once they
社会心理学研究指出,在以“人际伤害”或对他人造成伤害为标志的人际环境中(Wagner et al. 1),内疚感比后悔感更容易发生(Berndsen et al. 55,66)。与这些研究相一致的是,在社会本体论中,后悔似乎涉及对不受某人控制的不法行为的评估(Konzelmann Ziv 488),而内疚的感觉意味着对与应受谴责的行为有关的事情的自我归因,即使是以一种松散的方式(Gilbert,“Group errors”65,66n3)。如果一个人是一个行为错误的群体的一部分,为了推进这个人的内疚感的合理性的论点,Margaret Gilbert区分了个人内疚感和集体内疚感(“group wrong76”),后者仍然影响个人的内疚感。从这个角度来看,一个人可能是“个人无罪的”,但如果他所在的群体以一种道德上不可接受的方式行事,他仍然可以合理地感到内疚(“群体错误”66)。通过区分个人罪责和集体罪责,吉尔伯特打算给她所谓的雅斯贝尔斯的“困境”提供一个“可理解的”维度(“集体罪责”135,136)。她强调了卡尔·雅斯贝尔斯(Karl Jaspers)在对他自己对他的人民所做的事情的负罪感进行分类时的犹豫:“有一种方式是他‘无法控制的感觉’,这是‘理性地可以反驳的’”(吉尔伯特《集体内疚》135;雅斯贝尔斯74)。吉尔伯特认为,作为一名哲学家,雅斯贝尔斯发现这种存在主义困境“极其成问题”(“集体内疚”135页)。尽管如此,吉尔伯特也承认,这两种类型的罪恶感可能很难在每个人所经历的“痛苦和刺痛”层面上的“现象学条件”上加以区分,而是基于与这种感觉相关的“判断或思想”(“集体罪恶感”135)。吉尔伯特认为,由于她所说的“基本的共同承诺”,“群体成员对有问题的行为感到内疚确实是可以理解的”,这种承诺将一些人聚集在一起,“作为一个整体”来执行某些行为(“集体内疚”136页)。虽然我不像吉尔伯特那样致力于表明成员负罪感的可理解性,但我赞成接受这种感觉的一种合理性,即使它保留了“理性可辩驳”的特征。这甚至适用于成员内疚与个人内疚不那么容易区分的情况。吉尔伯特将共同承诺视为“创造权威”,在某种意义上,“一个人或一个身体”可能被“授权”将集体意图应用于具体环境。这是通过为整个群体做出决策来实现的,从而使集体意图生效(“集体内疚”136)。这种共同的承诺对团体的个体成员具有约束力,因为一旦他们对团体的意图作出承诺,“他们就不能单方面地改变集体的想法。”这不适用于“经双方同意可以这样做”的情况(“集体罪行”127)。关于吉尔伯特在成员罪疚的维度中参与“创造权威”(“集体罪疚”136)共同承诺的争论,我发现,它恰恰阻碍了对决定集体意图内容的权威的任何争论,除非这是通过“相互同意”完成的(“集体罪疚”127)。这使得集体成员相当被动,不愿意挑战通过他们参与共同承诺而产生的权威。一个集体的成员不愿挑战给予他们集体意图内容的权威,这在历史和当代政治权威的格局中很容易被发现,特别是在几十年来一直由威权领导人领导的国家。尽管他们的领导具有压迫性,但很少有人对这些意见提出异议,然后只有零星的声音,这些声音无法从其他小组成员那里产生连贯的长期承诺。从这个意义上说,吉尔伯特的论点假设,只有当那些零星的声音获得足够的吸引力,产生一种普遍的“相互同意”,剥夺特定的个人或掌权的群体的权威,并产生新的权威来取代旧的权威时,群体的“思想”才能改变(“集体内疚”127)。尽管如此,吉尔伯特并没有把重点放在从群体成员的被动到主动的共同协议来改变他们的统治权威的转变上,而是简单地指出这种转变确实发生了。事实上,她把这方面留给了社会在特定地理、文化和政治背景下的偶然性。 从长远来看,随着当权者在集体的制度和习惯纽带中巩固他们的影响力,个人的单纯怀疑将发展成为一种强烈的理性信念,即“主体在领导犯下的不法行为中缺乏影响力”(Konzelmann Ziv 490)。剩下的就是感谢领导人的行动,这些行动仍然服务于集体利益和保护的总体目标,同时将批评的声音保持在私下的嘀咕水平。对统治者在征服其他国家荣耀的道路上取得的伟大成就的敬畏之情,或对失去社会地位、财产、亲人或自己身体的恐惧和焦虑,可能会使道德悔恨的动机力量看起来完全是非理性的。在集体不愿反对现状的背景下,即使这不利于自己在社会群体中的地位,最终不利于整个群体,并且考虑到争论的明显非理性,社会群体的成员正在走向所谓的“自然主义谬误”。这种判断谬误被描述为“推理中的任何飞跃,其中一个人推断出一个应该”,也就是说,“关于事物应该如何的假设”,从“现状”,仅仅是对“事物存在的方式”的观察(Kay et al. 431)。如果现状对许多人来说是不公平的,他们可能会接受它,认为它是基于一个更高的集体意图的合理性,他们与这个意图有着不可救药的联系,而这个意图的内容是由那些拥有权威和权力的人赋予的。此外,对他人,甚至对自己的处境感到遗憾的动机力量,被当前制度使社会车轮转动和庞大的集体运动这一事实削弱了,这对个人或小群体来说可能是压倒性的。这可能并不意味着道德悔恨的动机力量完全消失了,而仅仅是点燃每个人心中潜伏的道德不满的火花消失了。只有当一个人或一小群人做了一些被认为是非理性的事情时,这种火花才会出现,这是一种高风险的行为,可能会给他们和他们的朋友和家人带来可怕的后果。然而,一旦这一行为被群体中的其他成员所知,它就会面对——并给大多数人心中根深蒂固的那种推理带来耻辱。这种明显不合理的姿态影响了集体对事物的理性认识,唤醒了一种道德感觉,即既定的生活方式存在严重的错误,这种生活方式要求牺牲少数人的利益来换取多数人的利益,而且,为了少数人的舒适而对多数人不公平。这种新情况唤醒了集体后悔的道德感觉,并将其扩大到更直观、更令人震惊的内疚动力。内疚的动力影响着那些意识到由于缺乏行动动力,他们已经容忍、鼓励和合法化了集体习俗和制度太久的人。这些给那些被认为太不同的人带来了难以想象的痛苦和折磨,比如种族、性别、宗教少数群体、原住民或非白人社区:简而言之,所有那些被当权者想象中的集体大厦视为不重要的部分。其他国家对荣誉的集体需要在很大程度上促成了成员国对其政权所犯下的社会不公正视而不见。正如彼得·福雷斯特所说,与荣耀感完全相反的是罪恶感(145)。无论这个建议是否正确,荣誉的论点确实被专制领导人用来影响集体的成员,使他们忽视个人和集体的罪恶问题,这些问题涉及社会中一些成员的边缘化或公开迫害,作为集体荣誉的代价。我反对把追求荣誉作为逃避罪恶感的工具的态度,我认为,通过集体接受罪恶感和由此产生的责任,可以在国家之间展示一种更清晰、更令人印象深刻的荣耀。这并不意味着罪恶感仅仅是一种非理性的、对个人幸福有潜在危险的感觉,而是与过去和现在的错误行为的集体责任联系在一起。这种由内疚感所孕育的集体责任决定了“情感主体作为负责任的主体参与情感内容”(Konzelmann Ziv 476),然而,这种集体责任却被改变整个社区思维模式的火花点燃了。这种火花是非理性的,但却是非常令人向往的英雄主义行为。 为了扩展英雄行为对成员集体罪恶感的转化力量,它将消极的感觉转化为积极的感觉,旨在产生,而不是阻止,合作和相互同意之前的罪行,我将简要地批判性地讨论和发展
{"title":"Collective Regret and Guilt and Heroic Agency: A Pro-Existential Approach","authors":"Ionut Untea","doi":"10.5406/19446489.18.3.04","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/19446489.18.3.04","url":null,"abstract":"Studies in social psychology point out that feelings of guilt are more likely than feelings of regret to occur in an interpersonal context (Wagner et al. 1) marked by “interpersonal harm,” or harm done to others (Berndsen et al. 55, 66). In keeping with these studies, in social ontology, regret seems to involve an evaluation of the kind of wrongdoing that is out of someone's control (Konzelmann Ziv 488), while the feeling of guilt implies the self-attribution of blame over something that is connected, even in a loose manner, to a blameworthy action (Gilbert, “Group Wrongs” 65, 66n3).In order to advance the argument of the reasonableness of a person's feeling of guilt if that person is part of a group that has acted wrongfully, Margaret Gilbert distinguishes between feelings of personal guilt and feelings of collective guilt (“Group Wrongs” 76), with the latter still impacting on the individual feelings of guilt. From this point of view, a person may be “personally guiltless,” but can still reasonably feel guilt if that person's group behaves in a morally unacceptable way (“Group Wrongs” 66). By distinguishing between personal and collective guilt, Gilbert intends to give an “intelligible” dimension to what she calls Jaspers's “dilemma” (“Collective Guilt” 135, 136). She emphasizes Karl Jaspers's hesitation in categorizing his own feeling of guilt for what his people have done: “There is a way that he ‘cannot help feeling’ which is ‘rationally refutable’” (Gilbert “Collective Guilt” 135; Jaspers 74). As a philosopher, Gilbert argues, Jaspers finds this existential dilemma “extremely problematic” (“Collective Guilt” 135). Nonetheless, Gilbert also concedes that these two types of guilt may be difficult to distinguish in regard to their “phenomenological conditions” at the level of the “pangs and twinges” experienced by each person, but rather on the basis of the “judgment or thought” involved with that feeling (“Collective Guilt” 135).Gilbert argues that “it is indeed intelligible for group members to feel guilt over the action in question” by virtue of what she calls a “foundational joint commitment,” which brings together a number of people to “intend as a body” to carry out certain actions (“Collective Guilt” 136). Although not committed to the goal of showing the intelligibility of the feeling of membership guilt as is Gilbert, I favor the acceptance of a kind of reasonableness of such a feeling, even when it conserves its “rationally refutable” character. This even applies when membership guilt may not so easily be distinguished from personal guilt. Gilbert sees joint commitment as “authority-creating,” in the sense that “a person or body” may become “authorized” to apply the collective intention to the concrete settings. This is realized by making decisions for the entire group, thus bringing the collective intention into effect (“Collective Guilt” 136). This joint commitment becomes binding for individual members of the group since once they","PeriodicalId":42609,"journal":{"name":"Pluralist","volume":"57 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"136206375","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Latinx Sexual Minority Adolescent Substance Use: State of the Science and Call for Intersectional Minority Stressors and Protective Factors. 拉丁裔性少数群体青少年的物质使用:科学现状及对少数群体交叉压力和保护因素的呼吁》(Latinx Sexual Minority Adolescent Substance Use: State of the Science and Call for Intersectional Minority Stressors and Protective Factors.
IF 4.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-01 Epub Date: 2023-07-26 DOI: 10.1007/s40429-023-00503-5
Robert Rosales, David G Zelaya, Oswaldo Moreno, Victor Figuereo, Sarah J Chavez, Sophia Ordoñez, Isabel Costas, Melissa Ponce, Robert Miranda

Purpose of review: Latinx sexual minority adolescents (LSMA) are at an intersection of ethnic and sexual minority (SM) status and may experience heighten risk of substance use and related problems. These youth may also hold unique protective factors that help mitigate the effects of minority stress and curb substance use. Little is known, however, about the intersectional minority stressors (i.e., due to ethnicity and SM status) and protective factors related to substance use among this population.

Recent findings: According to the minority stress model, there are unique minority stressors and resiliency factors that can help explain differences in behavioral health rates between white SM and SM of color. Research supports the notion that minority stressors (e.g., stigma/risk, homophobic bullying, and family rejection of SM status) confer risk for substance use among LSMA. In terms of resilience, less is known, but there may be some protective factors that have not been measured that could explain lower rates in some substances (i.e., club drugs and methamphetamine).

Summary: Little is known about how the intersections of ethnicity and SM status are associated with substance use in adolescence. Future research should assess the temporal relationship of multilevel (i.e., intrapersonal, relational, and system), intersectional (i.e., ethnicity and SM status) minority stressors and protective factors unique to LSMA on substance use. We propose that the findings from these future studies will help to create socioculturally appropriate behavioral health treatments that consider the intersectional risks and strengths within the LSMA population.

审查目的:拉丁裔性少数群体青少年(LSMA)处于种族和性少数群体(SM)身份的交叉点,可能会面临更高的药物使用风险和相关问题。这些青少年也可能拥有独特的保护因素,有助于减轻少数群体压力的影响并抑制药物使用。然而,人们对这一人群中与药物使用有关的交叉性少数群体压力因素(即由于种族和性少数群体身份)和保护因素知之甚少:根据少数群体压力模型,少数群体有独特的压力因素和复原因素,这些因素有助于解释白人 SM 和有色人种 SM 之间行为健康率的差异。研究支持这样一种观点,即少数群体的压力因素(如污名化/风险、仇视同性恋的欺凌以及家庭对 SM 身份的排斥)会给 LSMA 带来使用药物的风险。就复原力而言,目前所知较少,但可能存在一些尚未测量的保护性因素,可以解释某些物质(即俱乐部毒品和甲基苯丙胺)使用率较低的原因。未来的研究应评估多层次(即人际、关系和系统)、交叉性(即种族和 SM 身份)的少数群体压力因素和 LSMA 独有的保护因素对药物使用的时间关系。我们建议,这些未来研究的结果将有助于创造适合社会文化的行为健康治疗方法,以考虑 LSMA 群体中的交叉风险和优势。
{"title":"Latinx Sexual Minority Adolescent Substance Use: State of the Science and Call for Intersectional Minority Stressors and Protective Factors.","authors":"Robert Rosales, David G Zelaya, Oswaldo Moreno, Victor Figuereo, Sarah J Chavez, Sophia Ordoñez, Isabel Costas, Melissa Ponce, Robert Miranda","doi":"10.1007/s40429-023-00503-5","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s40429-023-00503-5","url":null,"abstract":"<p><strong>Purpose of review: </strong>Latinx sexual minority adolescents (LSMA) are at an intersection of ethnic and sexual minority (SM) status and may experience heighten risk of substance use and related problems. These youth may also hold unique protective factors that help mitigate the effects of minority stress and curb substance use. Little is known, however, about the intersectional minority stressors (i.e., due to ethnicity and SM status) and protective factors related to substance use among this population.</p><p><strong>Recent findings: </strong>According to the minority stress model, there are unique minority stressors and resiliency factors that can help explain differences in behavioral health rates between white SM and SM of color. Research supports the notion that minority stressors (e.g., stigma/risk, homophobic bullying, and family rejection of SM status) confer risk for substance use among LSMA. In terms of resilience, less is known, but there may be some protective factors that have not been measured that could explain lower rates in some substances (i.e., club drugs and methamphetamine).</p><p><strong>Summary: </strong>Little is known about how the intersections of ethnicity and SM status are associated with substance use in adolescence. Future research should assess the temporal relationship of multilevel (i.e., intrapersonal, relational, and system), intersectional (i.e., ethnicity and SM status) minority stressors and protective factors unique to LSMA on substance use. We propose that the findings from these future studies will help to create socioculturally appropriate behavioral health treatments that consider the intersectional risks and strengths within the LSMA population.</p>","PeriodicalId":42609,"journal":{"name":"Pluralist","volume":"1 1","pages":"396-411"},"PeriodicalIF":4.3,"publicationDate":"2023-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC11104555/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"90440662","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Peirce on Realism and Idealism 皮尔斯谈现实主义与唯心主义
IF 0.2 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-07-01 DOI: 10.5406/19446489.18.2.06
A. Wilson
{"title":"Peirce on Realism and Idealism","authors":"A. Wilson","doi":"10.5406/19446489.18.2.06","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/19446489.18.2.06","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":42609,"journal":{"name":"Pluralist","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42208444","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Dewey and the Aesthetic Unconsciousness: The Vital Depths of Experience by Bethany Henning (review) 杜威与审美无意识:经验的生命深度(综述)
IF 0.2 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-06-22 DOI: 10.5406/19446489.18.2.07
F. Ryan
{"title":"Dewey and the Aesthetic Unconsciousness: The Vital Depths of Experience by Bethany Henning (review)","authors":"F. Ryan","doi":"10.5406/19446489.18.2.07","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/19446489.18.2.07","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":42609,"journal":{"name":"Pluralist","volume":"18 1","pages":"114 - 121"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2023-06-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45955400","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The World of Appreciation as Lebenswelt: The Value of Pre-scientific Experience in the Philosophy of Josiah Royce and Edmund Husserl 作为Lebenswelt的欣赏世界——罗伊斯和胡塞尔哲学的前科学经验价值
IF 0.2 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-06-22 DOI: 10.5406/19446489.18.2.04
Massimo Cisternino
siNCe its origiNs iN herbert spiegelberg’s 1960 Phenomenological Movement: A Historical Introduction, the question of the rapport between Royce and Husserl has been generally framed according to a perspective that is at once conceptual and methodological. More specifically, Spiegelberg’s attempt has been that of finding an equilibrium among this twofold perspective and Royce’s theory of meaning and social self:
从赫伯特·施皮格尔伯格1960年的《现象学运动:历史导论》开始,罗伊斯和胡塞尔之间的关系问题通常是根据一个既概念性又方法论的视角来构建的。更具体地说,Spiegelberg的尝试是在这种双重视角和Royce的意义和社会自我理论之间找到平衡:
{"title":"The World of Appreciation as Lebenswelt: The Value of Pre-scientific Experience in the Philosophy of Josiah Royce and Edmund Husserl","authors":"Massimo Cisternino","doi":"10.5406/19446489.18.2.04","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/19446489.18.2.04","url":null,"abstract":"siNCe its origiNs iN herbert spiegelberg’s 1960 Phenomenological Movement: A Historical Introduction, the question of the rapport between Royce and Husserl has been generally framed according to a perspective that is at once conceptual and methodological. More specifically, Spiegelberg’s attempt has been that of finding an equilibrium among this twofold perspective and Royce’s theory of meaning and social self:","PeriodicalId":42609,"journal":{"name":"Pluralist","volume":"18 1","pages":"66 - 79"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2023-06-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41635805","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Crisis of Meaning in Sartor Resartus—Thomas Carlyle's Pioneering Work in Articulating and Addressing the Existential Confrontation 萨特的意义危机——托马斯·卡莱尔对生存对峙的阐释与应对
IF 0.2 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-06-22 DOI: 10.5406/19446489.18.2.05
Frank Martela
{"title":"Crisis of Meaning in Sartor Resartus—Thomas Carlyle's Pioneering Work in Articulating and Addressing the Existential Confrontation","authors":"Frank Martela","doi":"10.5406/19446489.18.2.05","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/19446489.18.2.05","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":42609,"journal":{"name":"Pluralist","volume":"18 1","pages":"106 - 80"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2023-06-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45140854","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Pluralist
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1