Expert accountability: What does it mean, why is it challenging—and is it what we need?

Silje Aa. Langvatn, Cathrine Holst
{"title":"Expert accountability: What does it mean, why is it challenging—and is it what we need?","authors":"Silje Aa. Langvatn,&nbsp;Cathrine Holst","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12649","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>When the Norwegian Parliament opened the southeastern Barents Sea for petroleum activity in 2013, it did so based on an impact assessment report prepared by the Ministry of Petroleum and Energy (Norwegian Ministry of Petroleum and Energy, 2012–2013). In 2016 the first licenses to drill in this area were awarded, and two environmental organizations sued the Norwegian state for awarding them. To prepare for the court case the organizations commissioned two economists with expertise in resource and environmental economics to review the impact assessment report and these commissioned economists quickly discovered major errors.</p><p>For one, the report did not discount the expected costs and future incomes—a standard procedure in such reports. Discounting with a 4% real interest rate would have reduced the estimated net income from opening the area by approximately 38%. This would make the opening a net loss (Greaker &amp; Rosendahl, <span>2017a, 2017b</span>). The report also estimated the gross income in the scenario with low petroleum findings to be twice what the underlying numbers showed (Greaker &amp; Rosendahl, <span>2017b</span>). These two mistakes together with optimistic estimates of employment numbers and the future oil price made it seem like there was no economic risk associated with opening, and this may have contributed to the Parliament's decision to open the area in spite of resistance from both environmentalists and the fishing industry (Greaker &amp; Rosendahl, <span>2017a</span>; NTB, <span>2017</span>; Tomassen, <span>2017</span>).</p><p>A standard remedy when mistakes are made in political life is to find someone to hold to account. But when experts are involved in governance processes they are rarely held to account for their mistakes. This is sometimes seen as a legitimacy problem of expert-reliant governance, and warnings are given about handing over more power to “unaccountable” experts. So, is the solution to make experts more accountable?</p><p>The popularity of “accountability” as a remedy for all kinds of problems has led to inflation and fragmentation of meanings attributed to the term, and also to uncritical uses of accountability measures. Still, this article argues that accountability of experts remains crucial for addressing the legitimacy problems brought up by increasing expert dependency. Yet, instead of proposing a new type of accountability regime applicable to all contexts were experts take part, the article takes a step back and asks: What exactly does it mean to hold experts “accountable”? And what are the distinct challenges of expert accountability?</p><p>There are several studies of expert accountability in relation to particular institutions, such as public agencies (e.g., Busuioc, <span>2013</span>; Schillemans et al, <span>2021</span>), central banks (e.g., Heldt &amp; Herzog, <span>2021</span>), judicial review (e.g., Contini &amp; Mohr, <span>2007</span>), and parliaments (e.g., Crum, <span>2017</span>; Eriksen &amp; Katsaitis, <span>2020</span>). Yet, these studies are typically difficult to compare because they define accountability in different ways or leave definitions implicit or underspecified. They also rely on different taxonomies of subtypes, and make different, or have unclear, assumptions about what account-holding is good for. Furthermore, they focus on different types of institutions, and types of experts and expert roles that differ in ways that will be relevant for what can serve an appropriate and balanced set of expert accountability relations.</p><p>We believe there is need for a more general and systematic approach to expert accountability, and in contrast to some previous attempts (e.g., Holst &amp; Molander, <span>2017</span>; Moore, <span>2017</span>), our contribution connects in more detail the literature on expert governance to the vast literature on accountability, so as to tease out the finer set of complexities in a more accurate manner. The aim is to provide conceptual and analytical tools that facilitate further comparative and evaluative research on expert accountability, and in particular for research on experts who take part in governance processes, as many experts do. The article uses the impact assessment case to exemplify definitions and distinctions , but also to illustrate the distinct challenges, and the tradeoffs, that are involved when holding experts to account.</p><p>The first part of the article clarifies our use of the term “expert,” and looks at the wide range of roles that experts can have in the context of governance. The second part works out a narrow but differentiated conception of expert accountability that helps us see how different subtypes of accountability may draw in opposite directions. The third part demonstrates how this conception of expert accountability allows us to map accountability relations that an expert is a part of in a more precise way. Part four looks at the criteria for saying that an expert is, or is not, sufficiently accountable. Part five analyzes the challenges of holding experts accountable. Two special challenges to holding experts to account are identified—the problem of epistemic asymmetry, and the problem of expert biases and mistakes. These influence other more general challenges of accountability, such as the problem of forum drift and the problems of many eyes and hands. The most proper response to these challenges will vary with institutional context and the more particular goal of account-holding, but the article argues that horizontal forms of accountability—peer professional and reputational accountability in particular—are key to expert accountability in many settings. However, expert bias, expert insularity, and forum drift can prevent these relations from functioning properly. There are moreover tensions and tradeoffs between horizontal accountability types and types of accountability which are designed to ensure democratic control and abuse of power. Finally, it is emphasized that expert accountability alone cannot address the normative problems of expert-reliant governance.</p><p>In Norway the decision to open new areas for petroleum activity lies with the Parliament. However, the Ministry of Petroleum and Energy are required by law to prepare an impact assessment report before a parliamentary decision can be made. This report must be sent out for public consultation, and the Ministry must sum up the findings of the study and the inputs from the public consultation in a white paper that should be presented to the Parliament. The decision to open the southeastern Barents Sea thus involved a range of in-house experts in several ministries and agencies, in addition to contracted experts from research and consultancy. Political parties, the media, and stakeholders—from local communities and environmental NGOs to the petroleum and fishing industry—also consulted experts on a range of topics relating to the opening. In short, various types of experts were sitting in several capacities, at all sides of the table, and could exert a significant amount of power.</p><p>The opening of the southeastern Barents Sea is far from special in this regard. Political decisionmaking standardly involves a range of experts, as well as a plethora of expert bodies, from public agencies and central banks, to advisory committees and courts. Commentators have characterized this as the “expertization” of society and policy making (Turner, <span>2003</span>), and as the “rise of the unelected”—the development of a new branch of government made up of those with expert knowledge that cuts across the traditional separation of powers (Vibert, <span>2007</span>), as well as conventional distinctions between government and civil society, public and private (Moore <span>2021</span>).</p><p>To discuss the extent to which accountability is the answer to the challenges of expert-reliant governance, we need at least a working definition of expertise. In line with Alvin I. Goldman's influential approach, we define experts as those with considerable knowledge, and more knowledge than most others, in this or the other domain, who are also able to use this knowledge skillfully on novel problems (2001(<span>2011</span>), p. 114). This makes the scientist or academic an important expert category. In line with this we often see terms such as “experts” and “scientists” used interchangeably, and distinctions between experts drawn based on their disciplinary background (economists, lawyers, engineers, etc.). However, experts can also be identified in other capacities (Grundmann, <span>2016</span>), and there are sources of expertise other than scientific training, such as especially relevant experiences or becoming knowledgeable about something through practical engagement with certain issues over time (Collins &amp; Evans, <span>2007</span>). Experienced civil servants or judges, for example, can possess this kind of practically gained expertise in addition to what they possess of scientific and professional skills; the same can apply to civil society groups with substantive sector expertise.</p><p>Yet, experts as we shall refer to them here, not only have a certain level of competence in some area. Their knowledge must also be of interest to someone and called for by them (Gundersen, <span>2018</span>). Knowledgeable people become then, according to this definition, experts, only when their knowledge is considered significant and relevant, and their guidance is asked for. Finally, within this category of socially recognized knowers, we focus here on those that are included in governance and policy making. Roughly speaking, this adds up to the professional class of “unelected” knowers that are arguably increasingly influential in present day politics (see Habermas, <span>1992</span> for an early diagnosis of “expertocracy”).</p><p>Accordingly, the “governance experts” we have in mind can work in civil service, courts, consultancy, organizations, associations, or in research institutions and universities; they can be information providers, advisors, agenda setters, or even decisionmakers—as when a judge decides a court case, or a central bank board decides on interest rates.</p><p>And we ask, What does it mean to hold this varied, but distinctive, category of experts “accountable”? What is expert accountability?</p><p>Accountability is sometimes used in a wide sense to denote persons and organizations’ inner responsibility to moral values and public interest norms, willingness to be responsible, transparent, and responsive, or to engage in dialog and justification (Behn, <span>2001</span>, p. 3–6; Bovens, <span>2010</span>, p. 946; Dubnick, <span>2007</span>; Mulgan, <span>2000</span>, p. 555). The term may also allude to institutional arrangements such as separation of powers, constitutionalism, and judicial review (Mulgan, <span>2000</span>, p. 563). Such broad approaches tend however to miss what is distinctive about accountability, and our starting point is therefore rather what has been called accountability in the core sense, meaning “answerability for performance” (Romzek, <span>2015</span>, p. 28), or more precisely, “the process of being called 'to account’ to some authority for one's actions” (Bovens, <span>2007</span>, p. 450). Accountability thus understood refers then to a specific social relation<sup>1</sup> between an actor<sup>2</sup>, and a forum<sup>3</sup>, where the actor is under an obligation, formally or informally, to explain and to justify his or her conduct, and the forum has authority to request information and explanation of the actor's actions in a domain, and subsequently to sanction the actions (Bovens, <span>2007</span>, p. 450).</p><p>When trying to delineate what accountability of experts in this core sense means, a first observation is that the governance experts we have in mind, despite their internal diversity, generally have a considerable scope of discretion in virtue of their expertise and thus typically have comparatively wide agent autonomy (Lindberg, <span>2013</span>, p. 209). Accordingly, even if these experts may be held to account for many aspects of their performance, expert accountability is first and foremost a relation or mechanism aimed at controlling or constraining this scope. Accountability according to the core definition is furthermore <i>ex post facto</i>, meaning that the expert is held accountable for past (and not for future) performance.</p><p>Importantly, for an expert to stand in an accountability relationship, all of the things listed do <i>not</i> have to take place. What is important is that they <i>can</i> happen, and that all involved are aware of this, something which presumably shapes the expert's expectations and behavior.<sup>7</sup></p><p>It is often said that experts in governance processes are unaccountable, but at a closer look we find that experts typically stand in multiple accountability relationships. Take an in-house economist of the Ministry of Petroleum and Energy, one whose area of responsibility includes writing the part of the impact assessment report that summarizes the commissioned expert reports on the social and economic consequences of petroleum development in the Barents Sea. Obviously, such an expert will stand in a <i>bureaucratic accountability</i> relation to his administrative superiors in the Ministry, a type of accountability relationship that is internal to the organization, vertical upwards hierarchical, and marked by high control. In this type of accountability relationship, the expert will primarily be accountable for abiding by the rules and procedures (procedural accountability), how money is spent, both for private expenses such as travel allowances and budgets for research (financial accountability, auditing), but also accountable for outputs and outcomes (product accountability). The expert is <i>legally accountable</i> for every part of his job that is regulated by laws, and he can be summoned before a court and held legally accountable in a civil case for things like harassment, and in a criminal case for things like corruption. Also, the expert will be <i>audited</i> internally or be held <i>fiscally accountable</i>, or both, for private expenses such as travel allowances and budgets for research.</p><p>The in-house economy expert is not in any direct <i>political</i> or <i>democratic accountability relationship</i> to voters. However, he can in theory be summoned before a parliamentary committee, but unless the expert has done something that can be punished in criminal law, it is the Minister who will ultimately be held to account for mistakes made in his ministry (a hierarchical accountability relation). The Minister of Petroleum and Energy may be said to be the expert's direct political principal and will have a strong interest in the content of his report. While there are no formal procedures for holding the expert politically accountable, the political leadership of the Ministry is likely to assess the outcome of this experts’ work also based on political considerations. Formally, the political leadership may not interfere in the expert economist's expert judgments, but it is not unlikely that political principals will have a heightened level of scrutiny vis-à-vis in-house and contracted experts if the expert's findings go against the principal's political wishes. If so, the in-house expert stands in an <i>informal political accountability relation</i>.</p><p>Importantly, the expert also stands in a <i>peer professional accountability relation</i> internal to the organization. Peers here would be other experts in the same domain. This type of accountability relation is horizontal and typically marked by a low degree of formal control and assesses the expert's work based on professional norms and standards. In addition, comes <i>reputational accountability</i> to peers outside the state apparatus, such as professors of economics in academia. Civil society and media can also try to hold the expert to account in a <i>societal accountability</i> relationship.<sup>9</sup> Activist groups may for example ask the expert to explain and engage in a discussion of his assessment of the existing research. In our case Greenpeace and Nature and Youth tried to hold those responsible for the impact assessment report, including the experts writing it, accountable by pursuing both legal, reputational, and societal accountability simultaneously, that is, by suing the state for the opening decision, hiring external expert economists to help them document the mistakes, and simultaneously bringing media attention to the mistakes of the report.</p><p>This attempt to capture accountability relations for one of the many types of experts involved in the opening of the southeastern Barents Sea is incomplete but suffices to illustrate how one may embark on a mapping of the different accountability relationships which experts involved in governance are part of. Yet, mappings of this sort do not directly address the legitimacy worry connected to expert's influence on public policy. Yes, experts stand de facto in multiple accountability relations, but are they held <i>sufficiently</i> to account? Or, put differently, when is there an “accountability deficit”?</p><p>Let us once more concretize by going back to our case. Some of the things for which the impact assessment report was criticized were noticed already in the public consultation, such as not including the social and economic costs of increased carbon emissions. Other omissions were first discovered by the two economists commissioned by the environmental organizations. The two economists discovered that the report had failed to discount the expected costs and future incomes, and also that the estimated future gross income on the low scenario (with small petroleum findings) was the double of what one would expect. The latter mistake was traced back to a single Excel-typo in an underlying report provided by the Petroleum Directorate (Greaker &amp; Rosendahl, <span>2017b</span>; Taraldsen, 2017b). Also, other methodological choices in the report strengthened the impression that opening would be very profitable, for instance the projection that the oil price would remain at 120 USD per barrel. By the time the first licenses were awarded the oil price was down to 45 USD. Some of these mistakes in the report also found their way into the white paper presented to Parliament (Norwegian Ministry of Petroleum and Energy, <span>2013b</span>). The result was that the economic risks of opening this part of the Barents Sea were underplayed, and this is likely to have influenced Parliament's decision to open. In such a situation, what would it mean for the expert economists in the Ministry who wrote up the Impact Assessment report, and the experts in the Petroleum Directorate who prepared the underlying report with the Excel-typo, to be <i>sufficiently</i> held to account?</p><p>When we ask whether an economic expert preparing an impact assessment report is sufficiently accountable, we must reflect on the implicit normative criteria relied on: Is the main problem one of ensuring more political or democratic accountability? Prevent corruption and power abuse, or secure epistemic quality, professionalism and induce learning cycles within the organization? Or some specific combination of these goals or values?</p><p>In general, some types of accountability relations are more conducive to securing the aim of a democratic rule than others, for example, the possibility of democratically elected forums, like parliaments, to hold actors to account. A mix of audit, bureaucratic, and legal accountability relations is typically seen as contributing to preventing corruption, while peer professional and reputational accountability relations are often considered to be primarily conducive to securing epistemic standards and learning. Thus, it is natural that actors with different roles and normative priorities in a case will be led to focus on different types of accountabilities. Yet, often one wants to achieve all these goals, but as we shall see, different types of accountabilities can easily come into conflict and also create accountability overloads.</p><p>Political and societal actors tend moreover to disagree on what the main normative problem is, and who should be held to account: When the expert mistakes in the impact assessment report became known, there were several calls for heads to roll: Some asked the Director of the Petroleum Directorate to step down (an example of hierarchical bureaucratic accountability where the leader is held to account for mistakes made in the organization), while others demanded a hearing with the sitting Minister of Petroleum and Energy in the Parliament's Standing Committee of Scrutiny and Constitutional Affairs (hierarchical political accountability). One also called for the very practice of impact assessment studies to be reviewed by the Office of the General Auditor (a horizontal audit relation) (NTB, <span>2017</span>; Taraldsen, 2017b; Tomassen, <span>2017</span>).</p><p>These calls for accountability were primarily voiced by environmental activists and by politicians who were critical of opening new areas for petroleum activity. Some of these critics characterized the mistakes and what they saw as a skewed focus in the report as possible <i>corruption</i>, or deliberate fraud, with the purpose of securing continued petroleum production in Norway, while some framed the report's mistakes primarily as a <i>democratic problem</i>, arguing that the government had presented Parliament with an inadequate knowledge basis for opening the area. Other actors, like the Director of the Petroleum Directorate, focused primarily on the Excel typo and characterized it as a “human mistake,” arguing that it had no significant impact<sup>10</sup>—a problem characterization that would point in the direction of accountability measures that could improve learning and the epistemic quality of future impact reports.<sup>11</sup></p><p>As we have seen, economic experts in the Ministry of Petroleum and Energy are not directly democratically accountable to voters, but they can be called to give an account of their performance to a democratically authorized forum such as a minister or a parliamentary committee. These indirect political accountability relations give a certain democratic control, and they can in some cases help prevent certain types of corruption and also induce learning. Yet, as we shall see, strong accountability relations to a minister or a minister's proxies, can also compromise an expert's professionalism and independence, and thus undermine the epistemic qualities of the outcomes which are central to legitimizing experts’ role in governance in the first place.</p><p>Including experts in the process of governance has been presented as the “filter” that ensures the “truth-sensitivity” of political decisions, reflecting how the primary normative justification of involving expertise is typically epistemic (Christiano, <span>2012</span>): If we at all find it defensible to consult or delegate decisions to the most knowledgeable in some area, we do it because we believe their extra knowledge can enlighten policy making and political processes. On this assumption, the main focus of proper accountability regimes for experts should be to ensure the epistemic quality of experts’ work (Holst &amp; Molander, <span>2017</span>), meaning also that there should be a particular attention to induce learning from past mistakes. This typically requires an emphasis on horizontal forms of accountability. However, shifts toward more horizontal accountability—such as more internal or external peer review—may often be resisted, for example within a ministry, because it can reduce the democratic or bureaucratic control over the experts and the outcomes.</p><p>Still, it is important to see that even when there is agreement on the right balance of normative aims, a range of challenges will occur in trying to hold experts accountable.</p><p>There are at least two particular challenges when holding experts to account. One of them, <i>the problem of epistemic asymmetry</i>, stems from the specific characteristics of the expert/nonexpert relationship. The other, <i>the problem of expert biases and mistakes</i>, connects with some well-known distinctive features of expert behavior. Besides, there are several general challenges of holding actors to account that tend to intensify when the actor is an expert, such as <i>the problem of forum drift, the problem of many eyes</i>, and <i>the problem of many hands</i>.</p><p>Expert accountability—in the core sense which we have delineated—can contribute to preventing corruption and undue inequalities in political power, as well as to minimizing plain mistakes, agency drift, sloppy work, overconfidence, group-think, and ideological bias in policy- and decisionmaking. Initially, holding experts to account is thus essential to addressing the legitimacy problems of contemporary expert-reliant governance. Still, these problems come in many different varieties, and there are inevitably tradeoffs, so no accountability regime can achieve all goals even when they are settled.</p><p>When experts are “decision-makers,” such as a judge or the chair of a central bank, there will, at least in well-functioning political systems, be formal accountability mechanisms in place that are deliberately designed to balance concerns about professional integrity and epistemic quality, possible corruption, and sufficient democratic control and separation of powers. In many other cases, for example, when experts shape policies primarily as knowledge-providers and agenda setters, accountability regimes are typically more haphazard, and not necessarily designed with enough attention to the overall balance between professional integrity, preventing undue influence, and democratic accountability. Lack of attention to professional integrity is likely to be most intense for governmental in-house experts, and particularly in cases where the political and bureaucratic principals do not respect the experts’ professional independence and integrity.</p><p>The Excel-typo that was made by an expert in the Petroleum Directorate was most certainly a “human error.” However, the ministry's failure to notice the resulting high gross income on the low scenario, and some other mistakes of the report, seem to point to biases or groupthink in a self-selected group of energy economists working in an institutional setting where it has been taken for granted that petroleum activity is highly profitable. The mistakes in the report also suggests insufficient internal and external peer professional relations and review procedures. Yet, as it became clear in the third round of the climate court case, too strong political and bureaucratic accountability relations also seem to have been an important factor for the mistakes. Here it was revealed that the Petroleum Directorate had made a more updated estimate of the economic potential of opening the southeastern Barents see on their own initiative, and that this new report estimated a significant risk of net loss. But the findings of this new report were not included in the ministry's impact assessment report and not presented to Parliament (Fjeld, <span>2020</span>). When this was revealed in the court proceedings, it led to a political accountability process in which the former Minister of Petroleum and Energy had to answer questions in a parliamentary hearing.</p><p>In this article we have suggested a context-sensitive approach to expert accountability, where we start by identifying the problems the accountability regime is supposed to solve: In the case under scrutiny, is the main problem that the involved experts are sloppy or make mistakes? Is it that they are biased, have vested interests, or insufficient independence? Or is the main problem rather that they misuse their power, or have the power to make decisions that they should not be authorized to do? And what is the optimal balance between these aims, for these types of experts, in the given context?</p><p>As we have seen, it is itself often controversial to diagnose what is the main normative problem. Yet, given that experts’ role as a filter for more truth-sensitive decisions is what justifies giving experts a special role in governance in the first place, attempts to hold experts to account must have a special focus on upholding epistemic quality. The problems of epistemic asymmetry and expert mistakes threaten, however, the fulfillment of this filter function and generate particular challenges for expert accountability. Other general challenges to accountability, such as the problems of many eyes and hands, may also be larger when the accountee is an expert.</p><p>We have argued that horizontal forms of accountability, and peer professional and reputational accountability relationships in particular, are generally vital to address these problems. Yet, the persistent problem of expert bias suggests that internal peer accountability may be insufficient. Both external peer accountability and accountability to peers in neighboring domains of expertise—and in some cases also to affected parties and stakeholders—can thus be necessary to prevent mistakes, bias, and induce learning.</p><p>Forum drift may be the most acute challenge for well-functioning horizontal forms of accountability such as peer review and reputational accountability. Many factors contribute to expert forum drift, and no simple solutions are available. A sufficient number of permanent academic positions with the academic freedom, time, and job security to be able to take on peer review tasks seem important. Changes in academic institutional incentives and culture may also be necessary to ensure that peer accountability tasks are seen as meriting and prestigious, especially those that are voluntary.</p><p>Also, journalists with relevant sector and case knowledge and opportunities for doing investigative journalism seem crucial. Public consultation regarding legislative proposals and the knowledge basis of policies and political decisions—such as impact assessment reports—is furthermore important both for transparency in policy processes and for getting epistemic input from different relevant sectors and perspectives. Such input may uncover specific mistakes, but it may be more difficult to correct for bias and narrow framings, in particular if the public consultation takes place late in the political process.</p><p>Often then, a combination of internal and external peer review, including stakeholder involvement, early in the process, or on a regular basis, would be a way to go. As our case shows, highly motivated civil society actors who have their own experts, or who commission experts, may play a very important role. Still, for expert accountability to work effectively, it will often be necessary to have someone who is accountable for the horizontal account holding to actually take place. This may require an increased formalizing of horizontal accountability relationships. Again there is a delicate balance to be upheld, and there will often be unavoidable tradeoffs between the goal of increasing epistemic quality, and sufficient democratic control and reducing abuse of power: Adding too much political and bureaucratic or managerial accountability of experts, or ongoing control, will typically be counterproductive, both because the epistemic asymmetry is considerable, and because expert knowledge is particularly vulnerable to conflicting accountabilities and accountability overloads.</p><p>Finally, even the right, and rightly tuned, kind of horizontal accountability is not a panacea for all problems of expert-reliant governance. In particular it seems necessary to cultivate both <i>individual and collective epistemic norms and virtues in expert communities</i>. Any expert accountability regime will tend to be ineffective if expert accountees are not committed to a proper professional ethos, and if there is a lack of long-term cultivation of well-functioning expert cultures in society, including in higher education and professional training.</p><p>This article's conception of expert accountability provides analytical tools to discern between different types of accountabilities and aspects thereof, that makes us better equipped to locate the right balance of the right kind of accountability types. Contriving a meaningful accountability regime aimed at holding experts in governance to account, requires an awareness of the potentially conflicting aims and functions of account holding, and conscious treatment of what we have listed as five key challenges to holding experts to account. We have identified forum drift as a particular challenge for expert accountability that calls for structural changes to be overcome. Our discussion has also helped us see that accountability cannot be the only answer to the pressing legitimacy challenges posed by the “expertization” of governance.</p><p>We hope this approach can stimulate more research, both empirical and normative, on expert accountability. Nontrivially, we believe our notion of accountability in the core sense, and our way of analyzing sub-types of accountability relationships may be useful for conducting descriptive and comparative <i>mapping of</i> expert accountability in particular cases or contexts. More importantly, we think our approach will enable better normative <i>assessments</i> of expert accountability relationships. First, because it provides a systematic overview of implicit normative standards, and also an overview of challenges and dilemmas for setting up accountability regimes for experts; this can be further developed into case- and context-sensitive assessment schemes. Such schemes can then be applied in evaluations and critiques of existing expert accountability regimes, and in turn stimulate <i>recommendations</i> for re-designing them.</p>","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":"31 1","pages":"98-113"},"PeriodicalIF":1.2000,"publicationDate":"2022-10-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12649","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12649","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"POLITICAL SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

When the Norwegian Parliament opened the southeastern Barents Sea for petroleum activity in 2013, it did so based on an impact assessment report prepared by the Ministry of Petroleum and Energy (Norwegian Ministry of Petroleum and Energy, 2012–2013). In 2016 the first licenses to drill in this area were awarded, and two environmental organizations sued the Norwegian state for awarding them. To prepare for the court case the organizations commissioned two economists with expertise in resource and environmental economics to review the impact assessment report and these commissioned economists quickly discovered major errors.

For one, the report did not discount the expected costs and future incomes—a standard procedure in such reports. Discounting with a 4% real interest rate would have reduced the estimated net income from opening the area by approximately 38%. This would make the opening a net loss (Greaker & Rosendahl, 2017a, 2017b). The report also estimated the gross income in the scenario with low petroleum findings to be twice what the underlying numbers showed (Greaker & Rosendahl, 2017b). These two mistakes together with optimistic estimates of employment numbers and the future oil price made it seem like there was no economic risk associated with opening, and this may have contributed to the Parliament's decision to open the area in spite of resistance from both environmentalists and the fishing industry (Greaker & Rosendahl, 2017a; NTB, 2017; Tomassen, 2017).

A standard remedy when mistakes are made in political life is to find someone to hold to account. But when experts are involved in governance processes they are rarely held to account for their mistakes. This is sometimes seen as a legitimacy problem of expert-reliant governance, and warnings are given about handing over more power to “unaccountable” experts. So, is the solution to make experts more accountable?

The popularity of “accountability” as a remedy for all kinds of problems has led to inflation and fragmentation of meanings attributed to the term, and also to uncritical uses of accountability measures. Still, this article argues that accountability of experts remains crucial for addressing the legitimacy problems brought up by increasing expert dependency. Yet, instead of proposing a new type of accountability regime applicable to all contexts were experts take part, the article takes a step back and asks: What exactly does it mean to hold experts “accountable”? And what are the distinct challenges of expert accountability?

There are several studies of expert accountability in relation to particular institutions, such as public agencies (e.g., Busuioc, 2013; Schillemans et al, 2021), central banks (e.g., Heldt & Herzog, 2021), judicial review (e.g., Contini & Mohr, 2007), and parliaments (e.g., Crum, 2017; Eriksen & Katsaitis, 2020). Yet, these studies are typically difficult to compare because they define accountability in different ways or leave definitions implicit or underspecified. They also rely on different taxonomies of subtypes, and make different, or have unclear, assumptions about what account-holding is good for. Furthermore, they focus on different types of institutions, and types of experts and expert roles that differ in ways that will be relevant for what can serve an appropriate and balanced set of expert accountability relations.

We believe there is need for a more general and systematic approach to expert accountability, and in contrast to some previous attempts (e.g., Holst & Molander, 2017; Moore, 2017), our contribution connects in more detail the literature on expert governance to the vast literature on accountability, so as to tease out the finer set of complexities in a more accurate manner. The aim is to provide conceptual and analytical tools that facilitate further comparative and evaluative research on expert accountability, and in particular for research on experts who take part in governance processes, as many experts do. The article uses the impact assessment case to exemplify definitions and distinctions , but also to illustrate the distinct challenges, and the tradeoffs, that are involved when holding experts to account.

The first part of the article clarifies our use of the term “expert,” and looks at the wide range of roles that experts can have in the context of governance. The second part works out a narrow but differentiated conception of expert accountability that helps us see how different subtypes of accountability may draw in opposite directions. The third part demonstrates how this conception of expert accountability allows us to map accountability relations that an expert is a part of in a more precise way. Part four looks at the criteria for saying that an expert is, or is not, sufficiently accountable. Part five analyzes the challenges of holding experts accountable. Two special challenges to holding experts to account are identified—the problem of epistemic asymmetry, and the problem of expert biases and mistakes. These influence other more general challenges of accountability, such as the problem of forum drift and the problems of many eyes and hands. The most proper response to these challenges will vary with institutional context and the more particular goal of account-holding, but the article argues that horizontal forms of accountability—peer professional and reputational accountability in particular—are key to expert accountability in many settings. However, expert bias, expert insularity, and forum drift can prevent these relations from functioning properly. There are moreover tensions and tradeoffs between horizontal accountability types and types of accountability which are designed to ensure democratic control and abuse of power. Finally, it is emphasized that expert accountability alone cannot address the normative problems of expert-reliant governance.

In Norway the decision to open new areas for petroleum activity lies with the Parliament. However, the Ministry of Petroleum and Energy are required by law to prepare an impact assessment report before a parliamentary decision can be made. This report must be sent out for public consultation, and the Ministry must sum up the findings of the study and the inputs from the public consultation in a white paper that should be presented to the Parliament. The decision to open the southeastern Barents Sea thus involved a range of in-house experts in several ministries and agencies, in addition to contracted experts from research and consultancy. Political parties, the media, and stakeholders—from local communities and environmental NGOs to the petroleum and fishing industry—also consulted experts on a range of topics relating to the opening. In short, various types of experts were sitting in several capacities, at all sides of the table, and could exert a significant amount of power.

The opening of the southeastern Barents Sea is far from special in this regard. Political decisionmaking standardly involves a range of experts, as well as a plethora of expert bodies, from public agencies and central banks, to advisory committees and courts. Commentators have characterized this as the “expertization” of society and policy making (Turner, 2003), and as the “rise of the unelected”—the development of a new branch of government made up of those with expert knowledge that cuts across the traditional separation of powers (Vibert, 2007), as well as conventional distinctions between government and civil society, public and private (Moore 2021).

To discuss the extent to which accountability is the answer to the challenges of expert-reliant governance, we need at least a working definition of expertise. In line with Alvin I. Goldman's influential approach, we define experts as those with considerable knowledge, and more knowledge than most others, in this or the other domain, who are also able to use this knowledge skillfully on novel problems (2001(2011), p. 114). This makes the scientist or academic an important expert category. In line with this we often see terms such as “experts” and “scientists” used interchangeably, and distinctions between experts drawn based on their disciplinary background (economists, lawyers, engineers, etc.). However, experts can also be identified in other capacities (Grundmann, 2016), and there are sources of expertise other than scientific training, such as especially relevant experiences or becoming knowledgeable about something through practical engagement with certain issues over time (Collins & Evans, 2007). Experienced civil servants or judges, for example, can possess this kind of practically gained expertise in addition to what they possess of scientific and professional skills; the same can apply to civil society groups with substantive sector expertise.

Yet, experts as we shall refer to them here, not only have a certain level of competence in some area. Their knowledge must also be of interest to someone and called for by them (Gundersen, 2018). Knowledgeable people become then, according to this definition, experts, only when their knowledge is considered significant and relevant, and their guidance is asked for. Finally, within this category of socially recognized knowers, we focus here on those that are included in governance and policy making. Roughly speaking, this adds up to the professional class of “unelected” knowers that are arguably increasingly influential in present day politics (see Habermas, 1992 for an early diagnosis of “expertocracy”).

Accordingly, the “governance experts” we have in mind can work in civil service, courts, consultancy, organizations, associations, or in research institutions and universities; they can be information providers, advisors, agenda setters, or even decisionmakers—as when a judge decides a court case, or a central bank board decides on interest rates.

And we ask, What does it mean to hold this varied, but distinctive, category of experts “accountable”? What is expert accountability?

Accountability is sometimes used in a wide sense to denote persons and organizations’ inner responsibility to moral values and public interest norms, willingness to be responsible, transparent, and responsive, or to engage in dialog and justification (Behn, 2001, p. 3–6; Bovens, 2010, p. 946; Dubnick, 2007; Mulgan, 2000, p. 555). The term may also allude to institutional arrangements such as separation of powers, constitutionalism, and judicial review (Mulgan, 2000, p. 563). Such broad approaches tend however to miss what is distinctive about accountability, and our starting point is therefore rather what has been called accountability in the core sense, meaning “answerability for performance” (Romzek, 2015, p. 28), or more precisely, “the process of being called 'to account’ to some authority for one's actions” (Bovens, 2007, p. 450). Accountability thus understood refers then to a specific social relation1 between an actor2, and a forum3, where the actor is under an obligation, formally or informally, to explain and to justify his or her conduct, and the forum has authority to request information and explanation of the actor's actions in a domain, and subsequently to sanction the actions (Bovens, 2007, p. 450).

When trying to delineate what accountability of experts in this core sense means, a first observation is that the governance experts we have in mind, despite their internal diversity, generally have a considerable scope of discretion in virtue of their expertise and thus typically have comparatively wide agent autonomy (Lindberg, 2013, p. 209). Accordingly, even if these experts may be held to account for many aspects of their performance, expert accountability is first and foremost a relation or mechanism aimed at controlling or constraining this scope. Accountability according to the core definition is furthermore ex post facto, meaning that the expert is held accountable for past (and not for future) performance.

Importantly, for an expert to stand in an accountability relationship, all of the things listed do not have to take place. What is important is that they can happen, and that all involved are aware of this, something which presumably shapes the expert's expectations and behavior.7

It is often said that experts in governance processes are unaccountable, but at a closer look we find that experts typically stand in multiple accountability relationships. Take an in-house economist of the Ministry of Petroleum and Energy, one whose area of responsibility includes writing the part of the impact assessment report that summarizes the commissioned expert reports on the social and economic consequences of petroleum development in the Barents Sea. Obviously, such an expert will stand in a bureaucratic accountability relation to his administrative superiors in the Ministry, a type of accountability relationship that is internal to the organization, vertical upwards hierarchical, and marked by high control. In this type of accountability relationship, the expert will primarily be accountable for abiding by the rules and procedures (procedural accountability), how money is spent, both for private expenses such as travel allowances and budgets for research (financial accountability, auditing), but also accountable for outputs and outcomes (product accountability). The expert is legally accountable for every part of his job that is regulated by laws, and he can be summoned before a court and held legally accountable in a civil case for things like harassment, and in a criminal case for things like corruption. Also, the expert will be audited internally or be held fiscally accountable, or both, for private expenses such as travel allowances and budgets for research.

The in-house economy expert is not in any direct political or democratic accountability relationship to voters. However, he can in theory be summoned before a parliamentary committee, but unless the expert has done something that can be punished in criminal law, it is the Minister who will ultimately be held to account for mistakes made in his ministry (a hierarchical accountability relation). The Minister of Petroleum and Energy may be said to be the expert's direct political principal and will have a strong interest in the content of his report. While there are no formal procedures for holding the expert politically accountable, the political leadership of the Ministry is likely to assess the outcome of this experts’ work also based on political considerations. Formally, the political leadership may not interfere in the expert economist's expert judgments, but it is not unlikely that political principals will have a heightened level of scrutiny vis-à-vis in-house and contracted experts if the expert's findings go against the principal's political wishes. If so, the in-house expert stands in an informal political accountability relation.

Importantly, the expert also stands in a peer professional accountability relation internal to the organization. Peers here would be other experts in the same domain. This type of accountability relation is horizontal and typically marked by a low degree of formal control and assesses the expert's work based on professional norms and standards. In addition, comes reputational accountability to peers outside the state apparatus, such as professors of economics in academia. Civil society and media can also try to hold the expert to account in a societal accountability relationship.9 Activist groups may for example ask the expert to explain and engage in a discussion of his assessment of the existing research. In our case Greenpeace and Nature and Youth tried to hold those responsible for the impact assessment report, including the experts writing it, accountable by pursuing both legal, reputational, and societal accountability simultaneously, that is, by suing the state for the opening decision, hiring external expert economists to help them document the mistakes, and simultaneously bringing media attention to the mistakes of the report.

This attempt to capture accountability relations for one of the many types of experts involved in the opening of the southeastern Barents Sea is incomplete but suffices to illustrate how one may embark on a mapping of the different accountability relationships which experts involved in governance are part of. Yet, mappings of this sort do not directly address the legitimacy worry connected to expert's influence on public policy. Yes, experts stand de facto in multiple accountability relations, but are they held sufficiently to account? Or, put differently, when is there an “accountability deficit”?

Let us once more concretize by going back to our case. Some of the things for which the impact assessment report was criticized were noticed already in the public consultation, such as not including the social and economic costs of increased carbon emissions. Other omissions were first discovered by the two economists commissioned by the environmental organizations. The two economists discovered that the report had failed to discount the expected costs and future incomes, and also that the estimated future gross income on the low scenario (with small petroleum findings) was the double of what one would expect. The latter mistake was traced back to a single Excel-typo in an underlying report provided by the Petroleum Directorate (Greaker & Rosendahl, 2017b; Taraldsen, 2017b). Also, other methodological choices in the report strengthened the impression that opening would be very profitable, for instance the projection that the oil price would remain at 120 USD per barrel. By the time the first licenses were awarded the oil price was down to 45 USD. Some of these mistakes in the report also found their way into the white paper presented to Parliament (Norwegian Ministry of Petroleum and Energy, 2013b). The result was that the economic risks of opening this part of the Barents Sea were underplayed, and this is likely to have influenced Parliament's decision to open. In such a situation, what would it mean for the expert economists in the Ministry who wrote up the Impact Assessment report, and the experts in the Petroleum Directorate who prepared the underlying report with the Excel-typo, to be sufficiently held to account?

When we ask whether an economic expert preparing an impact assessment report is sufficiently accountable, we must reflect on the implicit normative criteria relied on: Is the main problem one of ensuring more political or democratic accountability? Prevent corruption and power abuse, or secure epistemic quality, professionalism and induce learning cycles within the organization? Or some specific combination of these goals or values?

In general, some types of accountability relations are more conducive to securing the aim of a democratic rule than others, for example, the possibility of democratically elected forums, like parliaments, to hold actors to account. A mix of audit, bureaucratic, and legal accountability relations is typically seen as contributing to preventing corruption, while peer professional and reputational accountability relations are often considered to be primarily conducive to securing epistemic standards and learning. Thus, it is natural that actors with different roles and normative priorities in a case will be led to focus on different types of accountabilities. Yet, often one wants to achieve all these goals, but as we shall see, different types of accountabilities can easily come into conflict and also create accountability overloads.

Political and societal actors tend moreover to disagree on what the main normative problem is, and who should be held to account: When the expert mistakes in the impact assessment report became known, there were several calls for heads to roll: Some asked the Director of the Petroleum Directorate to step down (an example of hierarchical bureaucratic accountability where the leader is held to account for mistakes made in the organization), while others demanded a hearing with the sitting Minister of Petroleum and Energy in the Parliament's Standing Committee of Scrutiny and Constitutional Affairs (hierarchical political accountability). One also called for the very practice of impact assessment studies to be reviewed by the Office of the General Auditor (a horizontal audit relation) (NTB, 2017; Taraldsen, 2017b; Tomassen, 2017).

These calls for accountability were primarily voiced by environmental activists and by politicians who were critical of opening new areas for petroleum activity. Some of these critics characterized the mistakes and what they saw as a skewed focus in the report as possible corruption, or deliberate fraud, with the purpose of securing continued petroleum production in Norway, while some framed the report's mistakes primarily as a democratic problem, arguing that the government had presented Parliament with an inadequate knowledge basis for opening the area. Other actors, like the Director of the Petroleum Directorate, focused primarily on the Excel typo and characterized it as a “human mistake,” arguing that it had no significant impact10—a problem characterization that would point in the direction of accountability measures that could improve learning and the epistemic quality of future impact reports.11

As we have seen, economic experts in the Ministry of Petroleum and Energy are not directly democratically accountable to voters, but they can be called to give an account of their performance to a democratically authorized forum such as a minister or a parliamentary committee. These indirect political accountability relations give a certain democratic control, and they can in some cases help prevent certain types of corruption and also induce learning. Yet, as we shall see, strong accountability relations to a minister or a minister's proxies, can also compromise an expert's professionalism and independence, and thus undermine the epistemic qualities of the outcomes which are central to legitimizing experts’ role in governance in the first place.

Including experts in the process of governance has been presented as the “filter” that ensures the “truth-sensitivity” of political decisions, reflecting how the primary normative justification of involving expertise is typically epistemic (Christiano, 2012): If we at all find it defensible to consult or delegate decisions to the most knowledgeable in some area, we do it because we believe their extra knowledge can enlighten policy making and political processes. On this assumption, the main focus of proper accountability regimes for experts should be to ensure the epistemic quality of experts’ work (Holst & Molander, 2017), meaning also that there should be a particular attention to induce learning from past mistakes. This typically requires an emphasis on horizontal forms of accountability. However, shifts toward more horizontal accountability—such as more internal or external peer review—may often be resisted, for example within a ministry, because it can reduce the democratic or bureaucratic control over the experts and the outcomes.

Still, it is important to see that even when there is agreement on the right balance of normative aims, a range of challenges will occur in trying to hold experts accountable.

There are at least two particular challenges when holding experts to account. One of them, the problem of epistemic asymmetry, stems from the specific characteristics of the expert/nonexpert relationship. The other, the problem of expert biases and mistakes, connects with some well-known distinctive features of expert behavior. Besides, there are several general challenges of holding actors to account that tend to intensify when the actor is an expert, such as the problem of forum drift, the problem of many eyes, and the problem of many hands.

Expert accountability—in the core sense which we have delineated—can contribute to preventing corruption and undue inequalities in political power, as well as to minimizing plain mistakes, agency drift, sloppy work, overconfidence, group-think, and ideological bias in policy- and decisionmaking. Initially, holding experts to account is thus essential to addressing the legitimacy problems of contemporary expert-reliant governance. Still, these problems come in many different varieties, and there are inevitably tradeoffs, so no accountability regime can achieve all goals even when they are settled.

When experts are “decision-makers,” such as a judge or the chair of a central bank, there will, at least in well-functioning political systems, be formal accountability mechanisms in place that are deliberately designed to balance concerns about professional integrity and epistemic quality, possible corruption, and sufficient democratic control and separation of powers. In many other cases, for example, when experts shape policies primarily as knowledge-providers and agenda setters, accountability regimes are typically more haphazard, and not necessarily designed with enough attention to the overall balance between professional integrity, preventing undue influence, and democratic accountability. Lack of attention to professional integrity is likely to be most intense for governmental in-house experts, and particularly in cases where the political and bureaucratic principals do not respect the experts’ professional independence and integrity.

The Excel-typo that was made by an expert in the Petroleum Directorate was most certainly a “human error.” However, the ministry's failure to notice the resulting high gross income on the low scenario, and some other mistakes of the report, seem to point to biases or groupthink in a self-selected group of energy economists working in an institutional setting where it has been taken for granted that petroleum activity is highly profitable. The mistakes in the report also suggests insufficient internal and external peer professional relations and review procedures. Yet, as it became clear in the third round of the climate court case, too strong political and bureaucratic accountability relations also seem to have been an important factor for the mistakes. Here it was revealed that the Petroleum Directorate had made a more updated estimate of the economic potential of opening the southeastern Barents see on their own initiative, and that this new report estimated a significant risk of net loss. But the findings of this new report were not included in the ministry's impact assessment report and not presented to Parliament (Fjeld, 2020). When this was revealed in the court proceedings, it led to a political accountability process in which the former Minister of Petroleum and Energy had to answer questions in a parliamentary hearing.

In this article we have suggested a context-sensitive approach to expert accountability, where we start by identifying the problems the accountability regime is supposed to solve: In the case under scrutiny, is the main problem that the involved experts are sloppy or make mistakes? Is it that they are biased, have vested interests, or insufficient independence? Or is the main problem rather that they misuse their power, or have the power to make decisions that they should not be authorized to do? And what is the optimal balance between these aims, for these types of experts, in the given context?

As we have seen, it is itself often controversial to diagnose what is the main normative problem. Yet, given that experts’ role as a filter for more truth-sensitive decisions is what justifies giving experts a special role in governance in the first place, attempts to hold experts to account must have a special focus on upholding epistemic quality. The problems of epistemic asymmetry and expert mistakes threaten, however, the fulfillment of this filter function and generate particular challenges for expert accountability. Other general challenges to accountability, such as the problems of many eyes and hands, may also be larger when the accountee is an expert.

We have argued that horizontal forms of accountability, and peer professional and reputational accountability relationships in particular, are generally vital to address these problems. Yet, the persistent problem of expert bias suggests that internal peer accountability may be insufficient. Both external peer accountability and accountability to peers in neighboring domains of expertise—and in some cases also to affected parties and stakeholders—can thus be necessary to prevent mistakes, bias, and induce learning.

Forum drift may be the most acute challenge for well-functioning horizontal forms of accountability such as peer review and reputational accountability. Many factors contribute to expert forum drift, and no simple solutions are available. A sufficient number of permanent academic positions with the academic freedom, time, and job security to be able to take on peer review tasks seem important. Changes in academic institutional incentives and culture may also be necessary to ensure that peer accountability tasks are seen as meriting and prestigious, especially those that are voluntary.

Also, journalists with relevant sector and case knowledge and opportunities for doing investigative journalism seem crucial. Public consultation regarding legislative proposals and the knowledge basis of policies and political decisions—such as impact assessment reports—is furthermore important both for transparency in policy processes and for getting epistemic input from different relevant sectors and perspectives. Such input may uncover specific mistakes, but it may be more difficult to correct for bias and narrow framings, in particular if the public consultation takes place late in the political process.

Often then, a combination of internal and external peer review, including stakeholder involvement, early in the process, or on a regular basis, would be a way to go. As our case shows, highly motivated civil society actors who have their own experts, or who commission experts, may play a very important role. Still, for expert accountability to work effectively, it will often be necessary to have someone who is accountable for the horizontal account holding to actually take place. This may require an increased formalizing of horizontal accountability relationships. Again there is a delicate balance to be upheld, and there will often be unavoidable tradeoffs between the goal of increasing epistemic quality, and sufficient democratic control and reducing abuse of power: Adding too much political and bureaucratic or managerial accountability of experts, or ongoing control, will typically be counterproductive, both because the epistemic asymmetry is considerable, and because expert knowledge is particularly vulnerable to conflicting accountabilities and accountability overloads.

Finally, even the right, and rightly tuned, kind of horizontal accountability is not a panacea for all problems of expert-reliant governance. In particular it seems necessary to cultivate both individual and collective epistemic norms and virtues in expert communities. Any expert accountability regime will tend to be ineffective if expert accountees are not committed to a proper professional ethos, and if there is a lack of long-term cultivation of well-functioning expert cultures in society, including in higher education and professional training.

This article's conception of expert accountability provides analytical tools to discern between different types of accountabilities and aspects thereof, that makes us better equipped to locate the right balance of the right kind of accountability types. Contriving a meaningful accountability regime aimed at holding experts in governance to account, requires an awareness of the potentially conflicting aims and functions of account holding, and conscious treatment of what we have listed as five key challenges to holding experts to account. We have identified forum drift as a particular challenge for expert accountability that calls for structural changes to be overcome. Our discussion has also helped us see that accountability cannot be the only answer to the pressing legitimacy challenges posed by the “expertization” of governance.

We hope this approach can stimulate more research, both empirical and normative, on expert accountability. Nontrivially, we believe our notion of accountability in the core sense, and our way of analyzing sub-types of accountability relationships may be useful for conducting descriptive and comparative mapping of expert accountability in particular cases or contexts. More importantly, we think our approach will enable better normative assessments of expert accountability relationships. First, because it provides a systematic overview of implicit normative standards, and also an overview of challenges and dilemmas for setting up accountability regimes for experts; this can be further developed into case- and context-sensitive assessment schemes. Such schemes can then be applied in evaluations and critiques of existing expert accountability regimes, and in turn stimulate recommendations for re-designing them.

Abstract Image

查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
专家问责制:这意味着什么?为什么具有挑战性?这是我们需要的吗?
2013 年,挪威议会根据石油与能源部编写的影响评估报告(挪威石油与能源部,2012-2013 年),开放巴伦支海东南部进行石油开采活动。2016 年,该地区的第一批钻探许可证颁发,两个环保组织起诉挪威政府颁发许可证。首先,报告没有对预期成本和未来收入进行贴现--这是此类报告的标准程序。如果按照 4% 的实际利率进行折现,则开放该地区的估计净收入将减少约 38%。这将使开放成为净亏损(Greaker &amp; Rosendahl, 2017a, 2017b)。该报告还将低石油开采量情况下的总收入估计为基本数字的两倍(Greaker &amp; Rosendahl, 2017b)。这两个错误加上对就业人数和未来油价的乐观估计,让人觉得开放该地区似乎不存在经济风险,这可能促成了议会不顾环保主义者和渔业的抵制,决定开放该地区(Greaker &amp; Rosendahl, 2017a;NTB, 2017;Tomassen, 2017)。但当专家参与治理过程时,他们却很少为自己的错误承担责任。这有时被视为依赖专家的治理的合法性问题,并被警告不要将更多权力交给 "不负责任 "的专家。问责 "作为解决各种问题的良方大行其道,导致该词的含义膨胀和支离破碎,也导致对问责措施的不加批判的使用。尽管如此,本文认为,专家问责制对于解决日益增长的专家依赖性所带来的合法性问题仍然至关重要。然而,本文并没有提出一种适用于有专家参与的所有情况的新型问责制度,而是退后一步提出了一个问题:让专家 "负责 "究竟意味着什么?有一些关于特定机构专家问责的研究,如公共机构(如 Busuioc, 2013; Schillemans et al, 2021)、中央银行(如 Heldt &amp; Herzog, 2021)、司法审查(如 Contini &amp; Mohr, 2007)和议会(如 Crum, 2017; Eriksen &amp; Katsaitis, 2020)。然而,这些研究通常很难进行比较,因为它们对问责制的定义各不相同,或定义含糊不清,或定义不够明确。它们还依赖于不同的子类型分类法,并对持有账户的好处做出不同或不明确的假设。此外,它们关注的是不同类型的机构、专家类型和专家角色,而这些机构、专家类型和专家角色的不同,将关系到怎样才能服务于一套适当而平衡的专家问责关系。我们认为,有必要对专家问责采取一种更普遍、更系统的方法,与之前的一些尝试(例如,Holst &amp; Molander, 2017; Moore, 2017)不同,我们的贡献是更详细地将专家治理方面的文献与问责方面的大量文献联系起来,从而以更准确的方式揭示出更精细的复杂性。我们的目的是提供概念和分析工具,促进对专家问责的进一步比较和评估研究,尤其是对参与治理过程的专家的研究,因为许多专家都是这样做的。文章第一部分澄清了我们对 "专家 "一词的使用,并探讨了专家在治理过程中可能扮演的各种角色。文章第一部分阐明了 "专家 "一词的用法,并探讨了专家在治理中可能扮演的各种角色。第二部分提出了一个狭义但有区别的专家问责概念,帮助我们了解不同子类型的问责如何可能走向相反的方向。第三部分论证了专家问责制的这一概念如何使我们能够更准确地描绘专家所参与的问责关系。第四部分探讨了专家充分或不充分承担责任的标准。第五部分分析了追究专家责任所面临的挑战。 然而,人们往往希望实现所有这些目标,但正如我们将看到的那样,不同类型的问责很 容易发生冲突,也会造成问责超载。此外,政治和社会行为者往往对主要的规范性问题是什 么以及谁应该承担责任存在分歧:当专家在影响评估报告中的错误被揭露出来时,就有一些人呼吁要追究责任:一些人要求石油局局长下台(这是等级官僚问责制的一个例子,即领导者要对组织中的错误负责),而另一些人则要求在议会审查和宪法事务常设委员会中听取现任石油和能源部长的意见(等级政治问责制)。还有人呼吁由总审计长办公室对影响评估研究的做法进行审查(横向审计关系)(NTB,2017;Taraldsen,2017b;Tomassen,2017)。这些问责呼吁主要是由环保活动家和批评开放新的石油活动区的政治家发出的。其中一些批评者将报告中的错误和他们认为的重点偏差描述为可能的腐败或蓄意欺诈,目的是确保挪威继续进行石油生产,而另一些批评者则将报告中的错误主要归结为民主问题,认为政府向议会提供的开放该地区的知识基础不足。11 正如我们所见,石油和能源部的经济专家并不直接以民主方式向选民负责,但 他们可以被要求向民主授权的论坛(如部长或议会委员会)汇报工作。这些间接的政治问责关系给予了一定的民主监督,在某些情况下有助于防止某些类型的腐败,也有助于促进学习。然而,正如我们将看到的那样,对部长或部长代理人的强烈问责关系也会损害专家的专业性和独立性,从而破坏结果的认识论特质,而这正是专家在治理中的作用合法化的核心所在。将专家纳入治理过程被视为确保政治决策 "真理敏感性 "的 "过滤器",反映了专家参与的主要规范理由通常是认识论的(Christiano,2012):如果我们认为向某个领域最有知识的人咨询或委托其决策是合理的,那么我们这样做是因为我们相信他们的额外知识能够启迪政策制定和政治进程。根据这一假设,适当的专家问责制度的主要重点应是确保专家工作的认识论质量(Holst &amp; Molander, 2017),这也意味着应特别关注从过去的错误中吸取教训。这通常需要强调横向问责形式。然而,向更多横向问责形式的转变--如更多的内部或外部同行评审--往往会受到抵制,例如在部委内部,因为这会减少对专家和结果的民主或官僚控制。不过,重要的是要看到,即使在规范性目标的正确平衡上达成了一致,在试图让专家承担责任时也会出现一系列挑战。其中之一,即认识不对称问题,源于专家与非专家关系的特殊性。另一个是专家偏见和错误问题,这与专家行为的一些众所周知的显著特征有关。此外,在追究行为者责任方面还存在一些普遍挑战,当行为者是专家时,这些挑战往往会加剧,如论坛漂移问题、多眼问题和多手问题。我们所界定的核心意义上的专家问责制有助于防止腐败和政治权力的不当不平等,也有助于最大限度地减少政策和决策中的明显错误、机构漂移、工作马虎、过度自信、群体思维和意识形态偏见。因此,让专家承担责任对于解决当代依赖专家治理的合法性问题至关重要。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
52
期刊最新文献
Issue Information Issue Information Issue Information Fear of Black Consciousness By Lewis R. Gordon. Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2022 Deparochializing Political Theory By Melissa S. Williams, New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 2020
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1