Ontology as ideology: A critique of Butler's theory of precariousness

Jeta Mulaj
{"title":"Ontology as ideology: A critique of Butler's theory of precariousness","authors":"Jeta Mulaj","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12673","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>In the past decade, political philosophers have increasingly deployed the concepts of interdependency, equality, and vulnerability to critique contemporary society.<sup>1</sup> Widely popular both within and beyond academia, these concepts offer normative anchors enabling the critique of neoliberal ideals of individuality, independence, and resilience in the name of a more egalitarian society. Consequently, although many scholars denounce violence in existing society, they abstain from denouncing human beings’ interdependency, equality, vulnerability, and precariousness.<sup>2</sup> To the contrary, these concepts are treated as grasping our fundamental, ontological condition. Indeed, their capacity to resist neoliberal illusions of atomistic independence purportedly arises from their ability to reveal the hidden truth that neoliberalism otherwise conceals: that human beings are ontologically interdependent and equal. This truth, then, is said to carry its own ethical principle, demanding the realization of equality through political action. The use of these concepts today thus mobilizes more than an ontology; it also offers an interpretation of existing society—as deviating from and concealing ontology—<i>and</i> a politics that seeks to organize society in accordance with ontology.</p><p>Among the many voices taking up this position, Judith Butler's is perhaps the most prominent, particularly in the ontological theory of precariousness they articulate in their late work.<sup>3</sup> Hence, this article offers a critical engagement with Butler's ontology and the politics they derive therefrom. Butler's work, of course, has not been without criticism. However, the existing debate on their work focuses overwhelmingly on their so-called “ethical turn,” as well as their accounts of vulnerability and responsibility.<sup>4</sup> Important in their own right, these debates have tended to accept or leave unchallenged the basic structure of Butler's ontology.<sup>5</sup> Although critics have scrutinized the critical potential and limits of aspects of Butler's ontology, especially her account of vulnerability (e.g., Gilson, <span>2011</span>), they have left two of its most central features relatively unexamined: interdependency and equality. In doing so, even those critical of Butler's work maintain Butler's presumption that interdependency and equality are ontological features that inherently oppose neoliberal individualism, independence, resilience, and inequality.<sup>6</sup></p><p>In this article, by contrast, I critique Butler's ontology by submitting these two otherwise-accepted concepts to historical materialist analysis. My aim in this regard is to reveal the ideological underpinnings of Butler's ontology, with attention to its capitulations to capitalist society. In doing so, this article reveals the limitations of Butler's ontology and politics. Their theory, it shows, cannot adequately grasp the sources of capitalist violence and domination and thus fails to provide an emancipatory politics. To that end, this article develops two central claims: first, that Butler's ontological theory is transhistorical; second, that this theory is the ontologization of capitalist society.</p><p>Section one sets the stage for this critique, by outlining Butler's ontological critique of neoliberalism. Section two, then, argues that Butler operates with a transhistorical account of interdependency. Drawing on Karl Marx's analysis of capitalist interdependency as personal independence founded on objective dependence, I show that Butler overlooks the historical specificity of interdependency. Contra Butler, this section reveals that interdependency is not a veiled ontological condition <i>to be realized</i> through politics, but rather one that capitalist society has <i>already realized</i>.</p><p>In section three, I turn to Theodor Adorno to show that Butler ontologizes features and relations of capitalist society. I contend that the central feature of Butler's ontology—that we are equal by virtue of our interdependence—is uniquely capitalist. In precapitalist societies, interdependency was characterized by inequality. By contrast, it is only with the emergence of capitalism that interdependency comes to presuppose equality. Finally, in section four and in the conclusion, I explore the detrimental political stakes of Butler's ontologization of historically specific features of capitalist society. In section four, I analyze Butler's account of genocide to show that their ontology elides the violence of equality in capitalist society. And to conclude, I explore the limitations of Butler's ontological approach for theorizing emancipatory politics.</p><p>Before turning to these arguments, however, I wish to clarify this article's central aims. This article does not offer a critique of ontological theorization as such. It also does not attempt to somehow claim that human beings are not interdependent, equal, vulnerable, or precarious. And it does not, I must stress, attempt to provide a new ontology or an alternative to Butler's. Rather, my goal is to highlight the dangers of ontology-centered critiques for questions of social justice and emancipatory theory and praxis. Thus, in exposing the ideological underpinnings of Butler's ontology, my central aspiration is twofold. First, I hope to turn our attention not merely to neoliberal ideologies but to capitalism itself as a distinct form of society. Second, and in so doing, I hope to spur further critical reflection on the ontological claims at play in contemporary philosophy.</p><p>In pursuing these ends through a historical materialist approach, this article builds on a long tradition of philosophy that seeks to expose the ideological features of hegemonic ontological claims. Critiques of universal claims and theories about human nature are no novelty for philosophers. Here, Marx's critique of Adam Smith's naturalization of exchange, R. C. Lewontin's critique of Charles Darwin's theory of evolution by natural selection, and C. B. Macpherson's reading of Thomas Hobbes’ account of the state of nature come to mind.<sup>7</sup> As these theorists and others have shown, truth claims are not valid for all times and places; they are rather reflections of the dominant ideas, values, and structures of the societies from which they emerge. The contributions of feminist thinkers—and amongst them Butler themself—have likewise been invaluable in this vein. Feminists have exposed the ideological components of ontology by interrogating the fabrication of the so-called human nature, and, moreover, critiqued these components for naturalizing and legitimizing existing social inequalities.<sup>8</sup> Critiques targeting obvious cases, such as Darwinism and biological determinism, abound. Yet contemporary philosophy, too, replicates the tendency to naturalize social relations—albeit in more subtle ways. Butler's ontology, as this article shows, is an important example in this regard.</p><p>In subjecting Butler's ontology to a historical materialist critique, one can anticipate at least three primary resistances. First, Butler's early work pioneered the critique of naturalistic conceptions of the body. It could thus appear as a flagrant misreading to accuse their later work of replicating the very tendencies they once vehemently opposed (e.g., Butler, <span>1993</span>). However, as I shall discuss further, their later work manifestly deploys a nature/society dichotomy, as evidenced by their precariousness/precarity distinction (Lloyd, <span>2015</span>). Second, we should recall that Butler's later work purports to mobilize a nontraditional ontology, one they refer to as a “social ontology” (Butler, <span>2009</span>).<sup>9</sup> Social ontology, Butler maintains, is not a “claim to a description of fundamental structures”; rather, they hold, it uniquely refers to the “‘being’ of the body” as “exposed to social crafting and form” (p. 3). Sophisticated as Butler's social ontology may be, however, it is nonetheless ontology. It is so, as we see Butler themself express, because the “social” of social ontology in fact merely denotes a fundamental structure of the human condition: the body's inherent capacity to be affected and formed. Social ontology, thus, simply incorporates that which is supposed to be ontology's other—the social, historical, or contingent—into ontology itself. Indeed, as I show in this article, especially in section three, the social features that Butler ontologizes are those of their own society. Social ontology, like the naturalisms of Darwin or Hobbes, thus, is eminently of its time.</p><p>Finally, there is also a common-sense objection to my argument: “But isn't Butler simply right? Human beings have always been precarious, vulnerable, and interdependent. Surely, then, these are part of our ontology.” The goal of this article is not to argue to the contrary. Instead, my aim in what follows is to show that in Butler's ontological account, society enters through the backdoor: therein, features of capitalist society masquerade as universal, ontological truths. That is, although I grant that interdependency, vulnerability, and precariousness appear in all human societies, I contend that Butler fails to grasp them because they mistake their capitalist forms for universals. However, this fundamental misstep, as this article reveals, traps Butler's theory within the terms of the very society it seeks to critique.</p><p>Butler engages in an ontological critique of neoliberalism. Opposing the ontological condition of precarious, interdependent subjects to the neoliberal conception of the autonomous and independent individual, they argue that the independent individual is fictitious and denies an ontological condition of equality and interdependency. Thus, as this section shows, Butler derives both their critique of neoliberalism and their egalitarian politics from an ontological account of precariousness.</p><p>For Butler, precariousness denotes the ontological condition of interdependency, vulnerability, and bodily exposure to socioeconomic and political forces (Butler, <span>2009</span>). Precariousness, Butler writes, is an inescapable feature of the human condition because it is “coextensive with birth” (p. 14). Indeed, as they also write, it follows “from our social existence as bodily beings who depend upon one another for shelter and sustenance and who, therefore, are at risk of statelessness, homelessness, and destitution under unjust and unequal political conditions” (Butler, <span>2015</span>).</p><p>Implied in the condition of interdependency, Butler argues, is yet a further ontological structure: equality. “Interdependency,” they write, “though accounting for differentials of independence and dependence, implies social equality: each is dependent, or formed and sustained in relations of depending upon, and being depended upon” (Butler, <span>2021</span>). We are all equal, for Butler, because no one is fully independent. Thus, precariousness is a state of natural equal interdependence.</p><p>Butler, however, contrasts the equality of precariousness with the inequality of our social condition. Although vulnerability marks everyone's very existence, they emphasize, particular populations are marked by differential vulnerability (Butler, <span>2009</span>). To capture this unequal distribution of precariousness, Butler introduces the concept of “precarity” (pp. 3, 25–26). They describe precarity as “a more specifically political notion,” (p. 3) one naming the “politically induced condition of maximized precariousness” (p. 26). Specifically, Butler maintains, “precarity” is the “differential distribution of precariousness” where “certain populations suffer from failing social and economic networks of support and become differentially exposed to injury, violence, and death” (p. 26). Precarity, for Butler, names our failure to realize socially the ontological condition of equal interdependence. It thus captures how neoliberal policies, arbitrary state violence, police violence, incarceration, war, and genocide subject certain populations to increased precariousness (pp. 26, 115, 147; 2015, p. 11).</p><p>The sororal concepts of precarity and precariousness are foundational for Butler's politics. As Moya Lloyd points out, they allow Butler to distinguish “primary vulnerability, the ontological condition of being given over to others shared by all” from the “concrete, particular, historical conditions of insecurity and liability faced by some” (Butler, <span>2015</span>). The distinction enables Butler to critique aspects of precariousness, qua precarity, while affirming precariousness as such, and rendering it the ground for a new ethics of responsibility. “The recognition of shared precariousness,” Butler holds, “introduces strong normative commitments of equality and invites a more robust universalizing of rights that seeks to address basic human needs for food, shelter, and other conditions for persisting and flourishing” (Butler, <span>2009</span>). By deriving ethical obligations from the ontological condition of shared vulnerability and interdependency, Butler thus posits that we are obligated to preserve the lives of others because we cannot survive independently (p. 113). More precisely, as precarity is the differential distribution of precariousness, the ethical demand, for Butler, becomes the <i>non</i>differential, or equal, distribution of precariousness (p. 25). They “call for an equally livable life” that “requires the egalitarian distribution of public goods” (2015, p. 69). Butler's politics, thus, is the normative demand for egalitarian distribution.</p><p>Here, however, Butler's egalitarianism is predicated on a peculiar understanding of equality. Because their egalitarianism is derived from an ontological interdependency, Butler describes equality as “non-individualist,” or beyond the equality of individuals (Butler, <span>2021</span>). This ontological equality, Butler maintains, “cannot be reduced to a calculus that accords each abstract person the same value” (p. 16). Thus, the form of equality implied by ontology is not, Butler tells us, a liberal equality of “singular and distinct” individuals; rather, it is an equality of singularities “defined and sustained by virtue of their interrelationality” (p. 16). Ontologically we are equal in a condition of never being “fully individuated” (p. 46).</p><p>Butler's account of ontological nonindividualist equality grounds their critique of capitalism. By contrasting ontological equality with social inequality, Butler portrays capitalism as denying interdependency and equality (Butler, <span>2009</span>, <span>2015</span>). Under “contemporary conditions,” they write, “there is a war on the idea of interdependency” and “the social network of hands that seek to minimize the unlivability of lives” (p. 67). For Butler, moreover, capitalist ideologies of liberalism and neoliberalism promote the falsehood of an independent and self-sufficient individual (Butler, <span>2009</span>, <span>2021</span>). Capitalism and its neoliberal illusion of individualism veil, violate, and deny global interdependency, thus producing precarity (Butler, <span>2021</span>). Neoliberal individualism, Butler claims, depicts precariousness as a threat to be eradicated. Doing so, it propagates the fantasy that life can be protected, thereby justifying the very governmental mechanisms that foster precarity. By contrast, Butler holds that politics that aims to combat inequality by abolishing precariousness is futile, because our ontology cannot be eliminated. The ethical–political task, they write, is “not to overcome dependency in order to achieve self-sufficiency, but to accept interdependency as a condition of equality” (p. 47).</p><p>By contrast, they hold, ontology helps us combat precarity by offering “equality” as “a principle that organizes the social organization of health, food, shelter, employment, sexual life, and civic life” (Butler, <span>2021</span>).<sup>11</sup> Thus, Butler seeks to institute equal interdependency on egalitarian terms: minimize precarity and establish “equally livable life” through an egalitarian distribution of public goods (Butler, <span>2015</span>). In so doing, Butler's politics of equality would eradicate precarity by fully realizing precariousness. As Janell Watson (<span>2012</span>) puts it, Butler's egalitarian solution to unequally imposed neoliberal precarity is “precariousness for all.”</p><p>In opposing precariousness to neoliberalism, Butler simultaneously holds that individual independence exists only in fiction and that we are denied our ontological state of equal interdependence. But is it true that the independent individual is merely an illusion, or does it have an objective reality in existing society? Is interdependency a veiled and as yet unrealized ontological condition or are different societies characterized by different forms of interdependency? Butler, I will show in what follows, is incorrect to describe capitalism as a society somehow lacking or opposed to interdependency. Rather, the emergence of capitalism does not mark the transition from an interdependent society to an individualistic one; it constitutes a transition from <i>one</i> form of interdependency to <i>another</i>. In theorizing these changing forms, this section offers a non-ontological account of interdependency. This account, in turn, reveals the transhistorical character of Butler's ontology.</p><p>In offering such an account, to clarify, I am not denying that interdependency has been a feature of every society. However, to accept the persistence of certain features across distinct human societies is not to immediately engage in transhistorical theorization. When Marx, for instance, states that all hitherto existing societies have been class societies, the implication is not that class is an inescapable feature of ontology—in fact, his conclusion is precisely the opposite (Marx &amp; Engels, <span>[1848] 2010</span>). Furthermore, the acknowledgment of historically specific formations of something called “class” methodologically precludes us from treating class as “class as such.” That is, the content of what class is, in each case, is entirely determined by the society in which it appears. Thus, Marx's claim that all hitherto existing societies have been class societies is a <i>historical</i>, rather than a transhistorical claim. Following Marx, the historical account of interdependency I offer articulates the specific forms it assumes in the different societies in which it exists. This reveals Butler's transhistoricism: their tendency to elide historical specificity and thus reduce interdependency to a static, unchanging ontological feature true for all times and all places.</p><p>To analyze interdependency historically, we can begin by examining its shape in capitalism. Here, consider that Butler's claim that capitalism and its neoliberal ideology are expressions of independent and atomistic individuality is not so much false as it is partial. Although Butler sets up a dichotomy between ontological interdependency and the social illusion of independence, capitalist interdependency must be understood <i>in relation</i> to the fact that its social relations appear like independence. Grasping the form interdependency takes in capitalism, thus, requires explaining its dialectical relationship to independence as one of capitalism's unique features.</p><p>Rather than rendering interdependence natural and independence socially imposed, Marx recognizes that both are features of capitalist society. As he demonstrates in the <i>Grundrisse</i>, capitalist interdependency marks the transition from fixed relations of personal dependence to “personal independence founded on <i>objective</i> [<i>sachlicher</i>] dependence” (Marx, <span>1993</span>). Marx analyzes capitalist interdependency in relation to the individual freedom that arises from the dissolution of personal bonds of dependence constitutive of feudal society, the emergence of the capitalist mode of production, and its concomitant social relations. Capitalist society, for Marx, constitutes a totality in which individuals, regardless of their social roles, are fully integrated. That is, to survive as independent producers, all individuals must take part in the division of labor.<sup>12</sup> This integration forms a taut network of interdependencies, yet it does not entirely negate the personal independence of the individual. Rather, capitalist interdependency constitutes an opposition between the individual—as self-determining, free, and autonomous—and the sphere of objective necessity. It thus characterizes individual freedom within, what historian Moishe Postone has referred to as, “a more overarching form of unfreedom” rooted in a set of historically specific conditions in which “people make history in a form that dominates and compels them” (Postone, <span>2012</span>).</p><p>In breaking with feudal forms of interdependence, in other words, the capitalist mode of production constitutes a society characterized by a <i>new</i> form of interdependence. Specifically, what gives rise to interdependency in capitalism is that labor comes to mediate social relations. In previous societies, labor and its products were produced and distributed in accordance with various traditional norms and overt relations of power and domination (such as slave, feudal, kinship relations, or personal and direct subordination to others).<sup>13</sup> In capitalism, by contrast, one no longer consumes what one produces; rather, one's labor and its products serve as means for obtaining the products of others for consumption and survival. That is, it is not sufficient to merely produce; one must also exchange. In mediating exchange, labor in capitalism brings about a new form of interdependency whereby each is dependent on everyone else for their survival. Thus, labor comes to mediate all social relations, rather than being mediated by them, as was the case in precapitalist society.</p><p>The unique character of labor in capitalism brings about a peculiar form of interdependency. In capitalist society, each individual's labor functions in the same socially mediating way: each individual's concrete labor is a part of the whole and, as abstract labor, it is a moment of a homogeneous, general, social mediation that constitutes the capitalist social totality (Postone, <span>1993</span>). Here, the specificity of labor is abstracted while labor and its objectifications become the means through which single individuals acquire the products of others. By this process, capitalist production generates its unique form of interdependency: each individual is dependent on others for their livelihood, insofar as everyone's labor mediates all social relations.<sup>14</sup> Contrary to Butler's supposition, thus, capitalism does not dissolve interdependency “as such”; rather, in dissolving feudal interdependency, it simultaneously gives way to a new form of interdependency.</p><p>Further complicating Butler's account, moreover, Marx's analysis reveals that interdependency is not naturally given but socially imposed. In capitalism, interdependency is not a fragile, ontological condition to be protected, as Butler presumes, but a compulsory form of integration. Labor in capitalism ceases to function as a direct means of subsistence, functioning rather as a means for the acquisition of others’ goods (Postone, <span>2012</span>).<sup>15</sup> In predicating survival upon exchange relations, capitalist labor compels us to integrate in the process of commodity production.</p><p>Capitalism's compulsory interdependency is best understood as domination. The mediation of social relations described thus far—as indirect, covert, and abstract—gives rise to a form of domination that shares these characteristics. Contrasting ancient slave or feudal societies, for instance, capitalist domination is uniquely abstract. As Postone explains, this domination “is not grounded in any person, class or institution; its ultimate locus is the pervasive structuring of social forms of capitalist society that are constituted by determinate forms of social practice” (Postone, <span>1993</span>). Capitalist domination, that is, cannot be traced to the agency of particular groups or individuals; rather, it is the product of the activity of all individuals engaged in capitalist relations for survival. The compulsory character of interdependency is, simultaneously, its form of domination.</p><p>The abstract nature of capitalist interdependence itself helps us explain why Butler concludes that capitalism is principally characterized by individual independence. As Marx recognizes, it is precisely because capitalism's objective form of interdependency is covert that it does not immediately appear to be a form of interdependency at all (Marx, <span>1993</span>). That is, unlike earlier societies, people in capitalism <i>appear</i> independent even though they are interdependent. Marx's concept of alienation helps explain this appearance. Famously, alienation for Marx expresses the process by which human beings are dominated by their own productive activities and the product thereof—capital. Though this process is a social relation between individuals, it appears to them as their “subordination to relations which subsist independently of them and which arise out of collisions between mutually indifferent individuals” (Marx, <span>1993</span>). Individuals’ basic interdependency as expressed in these social relations, that is, is obscured by the interdependent, and yet alien, mode of production. Consequently, Marx explains, “[t]he general exchange of activities and products, which has become a vital condition for each individual—their mutual interconnection—here appears as something alien to them, autonomous, as a thing” (p. 157). The appearance of independence, thus, emerges from the alienating condition of the capitalist mode of production.</p><p>Marx's account of alienation, however, does not negate the formal, independence of the individual in capitalism. Rather, it conserves the dialectical relationship of independence and interdependence. In Marx's historical analysis, the course of the individual earning a historically unprecedented level of independence from interpersonal relations of domination—through the dissolution of traditional social ties—is coeval with the increased dependency of individuals on objectified, abstract, impersonal, economic relations of domination (p. 158). He thus explains the emergence of the independent individual in capitalism as a phenomenon existing only in connection to the relations of interdependence that dominate it. Doing so, Marx's account undermines the dichotomy Butler imposes between independent individuals and interdependency.</p><p>This dialectic, Marx's analysis reveals, expresses the heart of capitalist interdependency itself. As Marx explains in the <i>Grundrisse</i>, interdependency, as an objective bond, exists as the historical product of human activity, one belonging to a specific phase in the development of the individual (p. 162). That this interdependency takes an alien and objective form in capitalism only proves that individuals “are still engaged in the creation of the conditions of their social life” (p. 162). The individuality found in capitalism, Marx holds, presupposes “production on the basis of exchange values as a prior condition” (p. 162). In other words, capitalist interdependency is intimately tied to the individual as an independent producer and exchanger, a social role that capitalist production uniquely necessitates.</p><p>The historical specificity of capitalist interdependency highlights the transhistoricism of Butler's account. Butler's naturalization of capitalist interdependency can be explained by the fact that interdependency both has a specific character in capitalist society and is a necessary feature of all human existence. In Butler, this necessity is conflated with its historically determined form in capitalism, appearing as an expression of the human condition: one is dependent on others for survival (Butler, <span>2015</span>).<sup>16</sup> As mentioned in the introduction, Marx (<span>1992</span>) famously critiques the political economists for manifesting the same tendency, revealing the failure of Adam Smith's analysis as lying in its treatment of historical formations as innate characteristics of human beings. In presenting features of capitalism as eternal and naturally given, Butler's account preserves this tendency, thus failing to analyze the capitalist mode of production and its social relations.</p><p>In treating interdependency as a natural fact, Butler's social ontology fails to communicate anything beyond the truism that interdependency changes over time. Thus, social ontology neglects to accomplish its purpose: rather than analyzing the social forces that form the individual, it dilutes and flattens them into general features of the human condition. Capturing the processes that bear on the body in capitalism, by contrast, requires a historical description of those processes. In indicating what such a description would look like, the foregoing account exposes interdependency as the principal mode of domination in capitalism.</p><p>Distinguishing between historically distinct forms of interdependency reveals a crucial fact about Butler's account: that the form of interdependency their theory ontologizes is <i>capitalist</i>. Indeed, the tendency to ontologize historically specific features of capitalism is the modus operandi of Butler's theory. This is most evident in their theory of ontological equality. Recall that for Butler ontological equality is not an equality of independent individuals but denotes an equality of “beings” characterized by “[s]ingularity” and “defined and sustained by virtue of their interrelationality” (2020, p. 16). This ontological condition contains two key features: <i>nonindividual singularity</i> and <i>equality</i>. In examining each of these features, this section argues that each is unique to capitalist society. In turn, this analysis shows that Butler's theory of the natural human condition is the ontologization of a condition that is unique to capitalist society: equal interdependence.</p><p>The political implication of Butler's transhistoricism and ontologization is that it severs the relation between equality and violence in capitalism. An essential thesis in Butler's work is that equality and violence are mutually exclusive and thus that equality can combat violence.<sup>21</sup> Indeed, they firmly hold that “most forms of violence are committed to inequality, whether or not that commitment is explicitly thematized” (Butler, <span>2021</span>). The idea that violence expresses and intensifies social inequality leads them to argue for “radical equality” (p. 142). This commitment is founded on a double oversight: first, of equality in capitalism and, second, of radical equality as mass extermination. It is only by overlooking these two sociohistorical manifestations of equality that Butler can present it as an ontological good to be realized.</p><p>Butler cleanses equality of violence in indicating that the social realization of the radical equality characterizing our ontology necessarily challenges neoliberal precarity. However, equality, as theorists like Tocqueville, Arendt, and Marx have warned, is no safeguard against violence. In particular, Adorno extends the analysis of equality to genocide, arguing that genocide is inextricably linked to capitalism's tendency to integrate by equalization (Adorno, <span>2007</span>). Integration, as we saw earlier, as a process of sameness, expresses capitalist equality. Thus, without denying or discrediting forms of hyperinequality and their violence, Adorno shows how violence itself can be a manifestation of equality as the reduction of all to the same. “[G]enocide is the absolute integration. It is on its way wherever men are leveled off—‘polished off,’ as the German military called it—until one exterminates them literally, as deviations from the concept of their total nullity” (p. 362). The liquidation of the particular is, for Adorno, a manifestation of exchangeability—the making of nonidentical things commensurable—and thus equality (p. 362).</p><p>Adorno further theorizes the liquation of the individual in total integration through fungibility (p. 362). “[T]here could be no swapping,” Adorno writes, “without disregard for living human beings” (p. 354). The disregard that makes possible the swapping of individuals as the condition of possibility for fungibility is, for Adorno, equality. Particularly, the equality expressed in capitalist exchange reaches its radical manifestation in the camps (p. 146). But, for this very reason, the significance of Auschwitz, for Adorno, goes beyond the camp. The latter, for him, is just the most extreme manifestation of the regressive tendencies of modernity, both of which function through the principle of equality in equalizing human beings to death (Adorno, <span>2005</span>). The advent of Auschwitz, in other words, indexes the utilization of the achievements of modern civilization for systemic mass murder. The principle of equality is realized in genocide.</p><p>If equality is a principle of genocide, then Butler's “radical equality” itself can manifest in absolute integration, utter exchangeability, and redundancy. An examination of their understanding of genocide illuminates the shortcomings of their politics of equality. Critiquing Arendt's analysis of Eichmann, Butler predicates their understanding of genocide on the argument that Eichmann's crimes against humanity were ultimately an effect of his inability to recognize ontological precariousness and thus the normative demands it purportedly placed on him (Butler, <span>2015</span>). In their reading, Butler discards Arendt's understanding of genocide as intimately tied to superfluity (Birmingham, <span>2018</span>). Note, however, that superfluity for Arendt is not transhistorical but rooted in capitalist and imperialist attempts to render humans equally superfluous. Arendt grounds this tendency in capitalist laws themselves, understanding genocide as a manifestation of capitalism's tendency to reduce all to the same. That is, contra Butler, genocide is not a product of one's ignorance of ontology; it is capital's movement of equalization that generates superfluity and genocide.</p><p>Butler's idealist solution to genocide elucidates the dangers of their framework. Having dissociated Arendt's critique of Eichmann from her critique of capitalism, Butler argues that Eichmann's actions would have been avoidable if his attitude had been different. As Birmingham puts it: “[T]he thought seems to be that had Eichmann understood the shared condition of precariousness, he might have been less vulnerable to the dominant norms of whose lives were grieveable and whose could be eradicated from the face of the earth” (<span>2018</span>). In other words, the complex problem of genocide is given the simple idealist solution of a change in perspective.</p><p>Butler's reading of Eichmann and account of genocide is a direct result of their ontology. They cannot think of genocide as a total integration—as a historical expression of exchangeability—because they understand equality and interdependency to be inherently opposed to capitalism. Their framework, thus, elides capitalism's most egregious forms of violence.</p><p>To conclude, I want to suggest that Butler's transhistorical and ontologizing tendencies preclude the possibility of emancipatory theory and praxis. This shortcoming can be located in Butler's categories, which, I contend, are not emancipatory because they terminate <i>in</i> existing society, rather than reaching beyond it.</p><p>Capitalism, contrary to Butler's analysis, is not the unequal distribution of a prior, ontological state, but the domination of fragmented individuals by social labor that produces a historically unprecedented interdependency. Therefore, the interdependency in which we find ourselves locked is not an idyllic ontological condition veiled by superimposed capitalist relations, but our domination by our own product: capital. Lacking an analysis of capitalist interdependence, Butler confuses the violent historical formation of capitalist interdependency with an ontological claim to a shared world. Consequently, they not only mask historical relations as facts of nature but also treat existing relations as an ontology <i>to be</i> realized.</p><p>While at first blush admirable in its aspiration, a close examination of Butler's politics, as this article has sought to provide, reveals that it capitulates into capitalism's status quo. Masquerading capitalist relations as ontological truths enables Butler to demand the realization of an already existing condition. Of course, I am not suggesting that we live in a society of equality and interdependency <i>as such</i>; rather, what I have endeavored to show is that it is precisely the <i>forms</i> equality and interdependency take in capitalism that Butler renders as ontological conditions to be socially realized. Butler's politics of equality is, thus, nothing other than a concealed version of bourgeois egalitarianism. If the state of equality shared by nonindividuals is a core feature of capitalism, and one of its most brutal expressions of the degradation of human beings, then it cannot challenge neoliberal ideology as Butler suggests.</p><p>Butler's theory testifies to the fact that one cannot escape the determinations of their own society. Indeed, their attempts to do so merely result in features of society sneaking in and infiltrating their theory nonetheless, thus rendering them impotent to either escape or critique them. Thus, the liberalism they attempt to overcome is replicated in their theory, leading them, alongside a long tradition of bourgeoise thinkers to call for equality. The categories Butler deploys—from interdependence to nonindividual singularity, and equality—do not negate but reproduce existing society. And indeed, their categories cannot help but terminate in existing society; they are, after all, borrowed from it.</p><p>Butler, therefore, cannot theorize beyond the present. Consequently, they can neither critique nor immanently elucidate historical dynamics intrinsic to capitalist social formations—such as interdependency and equality—that necessarily point beyond themselves. Having ontologized capitalist interdependency, they are trapped within it and forced to maintain that there is no way out. Accordingly, they render the task of politics as <i>“accept[ing]</i> interdependency as a condition of equality” (Butler, <span>2021</span>). In this framework, the condition for emancipation is not the abolition of precariousness but the realization of an unhindered, equal distribution of precariousness. In other words, Butler perceives emancipation as emancipation <i>in</i> precariousness not <i>from</i> precariousness. But if precariousness itself, as we saw, is largely the ontologization of capitalist structures, then the emancipation Butler seeks lies strictly within the capitalism.</p><p>The necessity of critiquing Butler's theory is that it illuminates dangers potentially inhering in ontologically derived politics. The issue with political theories rooted in ontology is not merely that their ideological function is to provide naturalistic explanations of social phenomena; it is also that they attempt to <i>shape</i> human nature in accordance with the social phenomena they purport to explain. To expose the ideological components of such theories is, simultaneously, to struggle for the transformation of society. Thus, in contrast to Butler, a historical account of interdependency serves as a starting point for an articulation of emancipation as emancipation from capitalism.</p><p>My argument here opens a number of avenues for future work, which would more fully develop an ideology critique of existing ontologies that inform so much of contemporary political philosophy and ethics. A critical theory of society that begins from the specific structure and determinations of <i>our</i> society as a capitalist one can reveal otherwise abstract forms of oppression, violence, and domination. Critiques emerging from the historical specificity of our society—i.e., from the standpoint of capitalist production—allow us to think about emancipation <i>from</i> capitalism. To that end, a historical account of interdependency is imperative, not only for the sake of historical accuracy but also to reveal the sources of violence in capitalism and the praxis necessary to overcome them. Because, as I argue, capitalist domination functions through, not against, interdependency and equality, denunciations of violence today must simultaneously denounce the forms interdependency and equality take in capitalist society.</p>","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":"31 4","pages":"491-505"},"PeriodicalIF":1.2000,"publicationDate":"2023-04-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12673","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12673","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"POLITICAL SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

In the past decade, political philosophers have increasingly deployed the concepts of interdependency, equality, and vulnerability to critique contemporary society.1 Widely popular both within and beyond academia, these concepts offer normative anchors enabling the critique of neoliberal ideals of individuality, independence, and resilience in the name of a more egalitarian society. Consequently, although many scholars denounce violence in existing society, they abstain from denouncing human beings’ interdependency, equality, vulnerability, and precariousness.2 To the contrary, these concepts are treated as grasping our fundamental, ontological condition. Indeed, their capacity to resist neoliberal illusions of atomistic independence purportedly arises from their ability to reveal the hidden truth that neoliberalism otherwise conceals: that human beings are ontologically interdependent and equal. This truth, then, is said to carry its own ethical principle, demanding the realization of equality through political action. The use of these concepts today thus mobilizes more than an ontology; it also offers an interpretation of existing society—as deviating from and concealing ontology—and a politics that seeks to organize society in accordance with ontology.

Among the many voices taking up this position, Judith Butler's is perhaps the most prominent, particularly in the ontological theory of precariousness they articulate in their late work.3 Hence, this article offers a critical engagement with Butler's ontology and the politics they derive therefrom. Butler's work, of course, has not been without criticism. However, the existing debate on their work focuses overwhelmingly on their so-called “ethical turn,” as well as their accounts of vulnerability and responsibility.4 Important in their own right, these debates have tended to accept or leave unchallenged the basic structure of Butler's ontology.5 Although critics have scrutinized the critical potential and limits of aspects of Butler's ontology, especially her account of vulnerability (e.g., Gilson, 2011), they have left two of its most central features relatively unexamined: interdependency and equality. In doing so, even those critical of Butler's work maintain Butler's presumption that interdependency and equality are ontological features that inherently oppose neoliberal individualism, independence, resilience, and inequality.6

In this article, by contrast, I critique Butler's ontology by submitting these two otherwise-accepted concepts to historical materialist analysis. My aim in this regard is to reveal the ideological underpinnings of Butler's ontology, with attention to its capitulations to capitalist society. In doing so, this article reveals the limitations of Butler's ontology and politics. Their theory, it shows, cannot adequately grasp the sources of capitalist violence and domination and thus fails to provide an emancipatory politics. To that end, this article develops two central claims: first, that Butler's ontological theory is transhistorical; second, that this theory is the ontologization of capitalist society.

Section one sets the stage for this critique, by outlining Butler's ontological critique of neoliberalism. Section two, then, argues that Butler operates with a transhistorical account of interdependency. Drawing on Karl Marx's analysis of capitalist interdependency as personal independence founded on objective dependence, I show that Butler overlooks the historical specificity of interdependency. Contra Butler, this section reveals that interdependency is not a veiled ontological condition to be realized through politics, but rather one that capitalist society has already realized.

In section three, I turn to Theodor Adorno to show that Butler ontologizes features and relations of capitalist society. I contend that the central feature of Butler's ontology—that we are equal by virtue of our interdependence—is uniquely capitalist. In precapitalist societies, interdependency was characterized by inequality. By contrast, it is only with the emergence of capitalism that interdependency comes to presuppose equality. Finally, in section four and in the conclusion, I explore the detrimental political stakes of Butler's ontologization of historically specific features of capitalist society. In section four, I analyze Butler's account of genocide to show that their ontology elides the violence of equality in capitalist society. And to conclude, I explore the limitations of Butler's ontological approach for theorizing emancipatory politics.

Before turning to these arguments, however, I wish to clarify this article's central aims. This article does not offer a critique of ontological theorization as such. It also does not attempt to somehow claim that human beings are not interdependent, equal, vulnerable, or precarious. And it does not, I must stress, attempt to provide a new ontology or an alternative to Butler's. Rather, my goal is to highlight the dangers of ontology-centered critiques for questions of social justice and emancipatory theory and praxis. Thus, in exposing the ideological underpinnings of Butler's ontology, my central aspiration is twofold. First, I hope to turn our attention not merely to neoliberal ideologies but to capitalism itself as a distinct form of society. Second, and in so doing, I hope to spur further critical reflection on the ontological claims at play in contemporary philosophy.

In pursuing these ends through a historical materialist approach, this article builds on a long tradition of philosophy that seeks to expose the ideological features of hegemonic ontological claims. Critiques of universal claims and theories about human nature are no novelty for philosophers. Here, Marx's critique of Adam Smith's naturalization of exchange, R. C. Lewontin's critique of Charles Darwin's theory of evolution by natural selection, and C. B. Macpherson's reading of Thomas Hobbes’ account of the state of nature come to mind.7 As these theorists and others have shown, truth claims are not valid for all times and places; they are rather reflections of the dominant ideas, values, and structures of the societies from which they emerge. The contributions of feminist thinkers—and amongst them Butler themself—have likewise been invaluable in this vein. Feminists have exposed the ideological components of ontology by interrogating the fabrication of the so-called human nature, and, moreover, critiqued these components for naturalizing and legitimizing existing social inequalities.8 Critiques targeting obvious cases, such as Darwinism and biological determinism, abound. Yet contemporary philosophy, too, replicates the tendency to naturalize social relations—albeit in more subtle ways. Butler's ontology, as this article shows, is an important example in this regard.

In subjecting Butler's ontology to a historical materialist critique, one can anticipate at least three primary resistances. First, Butler's early work pioneered the critique of naturalistic conceptions of the body. It could thus appear as a flagrant misreading to accuse their later work of replicating the very tendencies they once vehemently opposed (e.g., Butler, 1993). However, as I shall discuss further, their later work manifestly deploys a nature/society dichotomy, as evidenced by their precariousness/precarity distinction (Lloyd, 2015). Second, we should recall that Butler's later work purports to mobilize a nontraditional ontology, one they refer to as a “social ontology” (Butler, 2009).9 Social ontology, Butler maintains, is not a “claim to a description of fundamental structures”; rather, they hold, it uniquely refers to the “‘being’ of the body” as “exposed to social crafting and form” (p. 3). Sophisticated as Butler's social ontology may be, however, it is nonetheless ontology. It is so, as we see Butler themself express, because the “social” of social ontology in fact merely denotes a fundamental structure of the human condition: the body's inherent capacity to be affected and formed. Social ontology, thus, simply incorporates that which is supposed to be ontology's other—the social, historical, or contingent—into ontology itself. Indeed, as I show in this article, especially in section three, the social features that Butler ontologizes are those of their own society. Social ontology, like the naturalisms of Darwin or Hobbes, thus, is eminently of its time.

Finally, there is also a common-sense objection to my argument: “But isn't Butler simply right? Human beings have always been precarious, vulnerable, and interdependent. Surely, then, these are part of our ontology.” The goal of this article is not to argue to the contrary. Instead, my aim in what follows is to show that in Butler's ontological account, society enters through the backdoor: therein, features of capitalist society masquerade as universal, ontological truths. That is, although I grant that interdependency, vulnerability, and precariousness appear in all human societies, I contend that Butler fails to grasp them because they mistake their capitalist forms for universals. However, this fundamental misstep, as this article reveals, traps Butler's theory within the terms of the very society it seeks to critique.

Butler engages in an ontological critique of neoliberalism. Opposing the ontological condition of precarious, interdependent subjects to the neoliberal conception of the autonomous and independent individual, they argue that the independent individual is fictitious and denies an ontological condition of equality and interdependency. Thus, as this section shows, Butler derives both their critique of neoliberalism and their egalitarian politics from an ontological account of precariousness.

For Butler, precariousness denotes the ontological condition of interdependency, vulnerability, and bodily exposure to socioeconomic and political forces (Butler, 2009). Precariousness, Butler writes, is an inescapable feature of the human condition because it is “coextensive with birth” (p. 14). Indeed, as they also write, it follows “from our social existence as bodily beings who depend upon one another for shelter and sustenance and who, therefore, are at risk of statelessness, homelessness, and destitution under unjust and unequal political conditions” (Butler, 2015).

Implied in the condition of interdependency, Butler argues, is yet a further ontological structure: equality. “Interdependency,” they write, “though accounting for differentials of independence and dependence, implies social equality: each is dependent, or formed and sustained in relations of depending upon, and being depended upon” (Butler, 2021). We are all equal, for Butler, because no one is fully independent. Thus, precariousness is a state of natural equal interdependence.

Butler, however, contrasts the equality of precariousness with the inequality of our social condition. Although vulnerability marks everyone's very existence, they emphasize, particular populations are marked by differential vulnerability (Butler, 2009). To capture this unequal distribution of precariousness, Butler introduces the concept of “precarity” (pp. 3, 25–26). They describe precarity as “a more specifically political notion,” (p. 3) one naming the “politically induced condition of maximized precariousness” (p. 26). Specifically, Butler maintains, “precarity” is the “differential distribution of precariousness” where “certain populations suffer from failing social and economic networks of support and become differentially exposed to injury, violence, and death” (p. 26). Precarity, for Butler, names our failure to realize socially the ontological condition of equal interdependence. It thus captures how neoliberal policies, arbitrary state violence, police violence, incarceration, war, and genocide subject certain populations to increased precariousness (pp. 26, 115, 147; 2015, p. 11).

The sororal concepts of precarity and precariousness are foundational for Butler's politics. As Moya Lloyd points out, they allow Butler to distinguish “primary vulnerability, the ontological condition of being given over to others shared by all” from the “concrete, particular, historical conditions of insecurity and liability faced by some” (Butler, 2015). The distinction enables Butler to critique aspects of precariousness, qua precarity, while affirming precariousness as such, and rendering it the ground for a new ethics of responsibility. “The recognition of shared precariousness,” Butler holds, “introduces strong normative commitments of equality and invites a more robust universalizing of rights that seeks to address basic human needs for food, shelter, and other conditions for persisting and flourishing” (Butler, 2009). By deriving ethical obligations from the ontological condition of shared vulnerability and interdependency, Butler thus posits that we are obligated to preserve the lives of others because we cannot survive independently (p. 113). More precisely, as precarity is the differential distribution of precariousness, the ethical demand, for Butler, becomes the nondifferential, or equal, distribution of precariousness (p. 25). They “call for an equally livable life” that “requires the egalitarian distribution of public goods” (2015, p. 69). Butler's politics, thus, is the normative demand for egalitarian distribution.

Here, however, Butler's egalitarianism is predicated on a peculiar understanding of equality. Because their egalitarianism is derived from an ontological interdependency, Butler describes equality as “non-individualist,” or beyond the equality of individuals (Butler, 2021). This ontological equality, Butler maintains, “cannot be reduced to a calculus that accords each abstract person the same value” (p. 16). Thus, the form of equality implied by ontology is not, Butler tells us, a liberal equality of “singular and distinct” individuals; rather, it is an equality of singularities “defined and sustained by virtue of their interrelationality” (p. 16). Ontologically we are equal in a condition of never being “fully individuated” (p. 46).

Butler's account of ontological nonindividualist equality grounds their critique of capitalism. By contrasting ontological equality with social inequality, Butler portrays capitalism as denying interdependency and equality (Butler, 2009, 2015). Under “contemporary conditions,” they write, “there is a war on the idea of interdependency” and “the social network of hands that seek to minimize the unlivability of lives” (p. 67). For Butler, moreover, capitalist ideologies of liberalism and neoliberalism promote the falsehood of an independent and self-sufficient individual (Butler, 2009, 2021). Capitalism and its neoliberal illusion of individualism veil, violate, and deny global interdependency, thus producing precarity (Butler, 2021). Neoliberal individualism, Butler claims, depicts precariousness as a threat to be eradicated. Doing so, it propagates the fantasy that life can be protected, thereby justifying the very governmental mechanisms that foster precarity. By contrast, Butler holds that politics that aims to combat inequality by abolishing precariousness is futile, because our ontology cannot be eliminated. The ethical–political task, they write, is “not to overcome dependency in order to achieve self-sufficiency, but to accept interdependency as a condition of equality” (p. 47).

By contrast, they hold, ontology helps us combat precarity by offering “equality” as “a principle that organizes the social organization of health, food, shelter, employment, sexual life, and civic life” (Butler, 2021).11 Thus, Butler seeks to institute equal interdependency on egalitarian terms: minimize precarity and establish “equally livable life” through an egalitarian distribution of public goods (Butler, 2015). In so doing, Butler's politics of equality would eradicate precarity by fully realizing precariousness. As Janell Watson (2012) puts it, Butler's egalitarian solution to unequally imposed neoliberal precarity is “precariousness for all.”

In opposing precariousness to neoliberalism, Butler simultaneously holds that individual independence exists only in fiction and that we are denied our ontological state of equal interdependence. But is it true that the independent individual is merely an illusion, or does it have an objective reality in existing society? Is interdependency a veiled and as yet unrealized ontological condition or are different societies characterized by different forms of interdependency? Butler, I will show in what follows, is incorrect to describe capitalism as a society somehow lacking or opposed to interdependency. Rather, the emergence of capitalism does not mark the transition from an interdependent society to an individualistic one; it constitutes a transition from one form of interdependency to another. In theorizing these changing forms, this section offers a non-ontological account of interdependency. This account, in turn, reveals the transhistorical character of Butler's ontology.

In offering such an account, to clarify, I am not denying that interdependency has been a feature of every society. However, to accept the persistence of certain features across distinct human societies is not to immediately engage in transhistorical theorization. When Marx, for instance, states that all hitherto existing societies have been class societies, the implication is not that class is an inescapable feature of ontology—in fact, his conclusion is precisely the opposite (Marx & Engels, [1848] 2010). Furthermore, the acknowledgment of historically specific formations of something called “class” methodologically precludes us from treating class as “class as such.” That is, the content of what class is, in each case, is entirely determined by the society in which it appears. Thus, Marx's claim that all hitherto existing societies have been class societies is a historical, rather than a transhistorical claim. Following Marx, the historical account of interdependency I offer articulates the specific forms it assumes in the different societies in which it exists. This reveals Butler's transhistoricism: their tendency to elide historical specificity and thus reduce interdependency to a static, unchanging ontological feature true for all times and all places.

To analyze interdependency historically, we can begin by examining its shape in capitalism. Here, consider that Butler's claim that capitalism and its neoliberal ideology are expressions of independent and atomistic individuality is not so much false as it is partial. Although Butler sets up a dichotomy between ontological interdependency and the social illusion of independence, capitalist interdependency must be understood in relation to the fact that its social relations appear like independence. Grasping the form interdependency takes in capitalism, thus, requires explaining its dialectical relationship to independence as one of capitalism's unique features.

Rather than rendering interdependence natural and independence socially imposed, Marx recognizes that both are features of capitalist society. As he demonstrates in the Grundrisse, capitalist interdependency marks the transition from fixed relations of personal dependence to “personal independence founded on objective [sachlicher] dependence” (Marx, 1993). Marx analyzes capitalist interdependency in relation to the individual freedom that arises from the dissolution of personal bonds of dependence constitutive of feudal society, the emergence of the capitalist mode of production, and its concomitant social relations. Capitalist society, for Marx, constitutes a totality in which individuals, regardless of their social roles, are fully integrated. That is, to survive as independent producers, all individuals must take part in the division of labor.12 This integration forms a taut network of interdependencies, yet it does not entirely negate the personal independence of the individual. Rather, capitalist interdependency constitutes an opposition between the individual—as self-determining, free, and autonomous—and the sphere of objective necessity. It thus characterizes individual freedom within, what historian Moishe Postone has referred to as, “a more overarching form of unfreedom” rooted in a set of historically specific conditions in which “people make history in a form that dominates and compels them” (Postone, 2012).

In breaking with feudal forms of interdependence, in other words, the capitalist mode of production constitutes a society characterized by a new form of interdependence. Specifically, what gives rise to interdependency in capitalism is that labor comes to mediate social relations. In previous societies, labor and its products were produced and distributed in accordance with various traditional norms and overt relations of power and domination (such as slave, feudal, kinship relations, or personal and direct subordination to others).13 In capitalism, by contrast, one no longer consumes what one produces; rather, one's labor and its products serve as means for obtaining the products of others for consumption and survival. That is, it is not sufficient to merely produce; one must also exchange. In mediating exchange, labor in capitalism brings about a new form of interdependency whereby each is dependent on everyone else for their survival. Thus, labor comes to mediate all social relations, rather than being mediated by them, as was the case in precapitalist society.

The unique character of labor in capitalism brings about a peculiar form of interdependency. In capitalist society, each individual's labor functions in the same socially mediating way: each individual's concrete labor is a part of the whole and, as abstract labor, it is a moment of a homogeneous, general, social mediation that constitutes the capitalist social totality (Postone, 1993). Here, the specificity of labor is abstracted while labor and its objectifications become the means through which single individuals acquire the products of others. By this process, capitalist production generates its unique form of interdependency: each individual is dependent on others for their livelihood, insofar as everyone's labor mediates all social relations.14 Contrary to Butler's supposition, thus, capitalism does not dissolve interdependency “as such”; rather, in dissolving feudal interdependency, it simultaneously gives way to a new form of interdependency.

Further complicating Butler's account, moreover, Marx's analysis reveals that interdependency is not naturally given but socially imposed. In capitalism, interdependency is not a fragile, ontological condition to be protected, as Butler presumes, but a compulsory form of integration. Labor in capitalism ceases to function as a direct means of subsistence, functioning rather as a means for the acquisition of others’ goods (Postone, 2012).15 In predicating survival upon exchange relations, capitalist labor compels us to integrate in the process of commodity production.

Capitalism's compulsory interdependency is best understood as domination. The mediation of social relations described thus far—as indirect, covert, and abstract—gives rise to a form of domination that shares these characteristics. Contrasting ancient slave or feudal societies, for instance, capitalist domination is uniquely abstract. As Postone explains, this domination “is not grounded in any person, class or institution; its ultimate locus is the pervasive structuring of social forms of capitalist society that are constituted by determinate forms of social practice” (Postone, 1993). Capitalist domination, that is, cannot be traced to the agency of particular groups or individuals; rather, it is the product of the activity of all individuals engaged in capitalist relations for survival. The compulsory character of interdependency is, simultaneously, its form of domination.

The abstract nature of capitalist interdependence itself helps us explain why Butler concludes that capitalism is principally characterized by individual independence. As Marx recognizes, it is precisely because capitalism's objective form of interdependency is covert that it does not immediately appear to be a form of interdependency at all (Marx, 1993). That is, unlike earlier societies, people in capitalism appear independent even though they are interdependent. Marx's concept of alienation helps explain this appearance. Famously, alienation for Marx expresses the process by which human beings are dominated by their own productive activities and the product thereof—capital. Though this process is a social relation between individuals, it appears to them as their “subordination to relations which subsist independently of them and which arise out of collisions between mutually indifferent individuals” (Marx, 1993). Individuals’ basic interdependency as expressed in these social relations, that is, is obscured by the interdependent, and yet alien, mode of production. Consequently, Marx explains, “[t]he general exchange of activities and products, which has become a vital condition for each individual—their mutual interconnection—here appears as something alien to them, autonomous, as a thing” (p. 157). The appearance of independence, thus, emerges from the alienating condition of the capitalist mode of production.

Marx's account of alienation, however, does not negate the formal, independence of the individual in capitalism. Rather, it conserves the dialectical relationship of independence and interdependence. In Marx's historical analysis, the course of the individual earning a historically unprecedented level of independence from interpersonal relations of domination—through the dissolution of traditional social ties—is coeval with the increased dependency of individuals on objectified, abstract, impersonal, economic relations of domination (p. 158). He thus explains the emergence of the independent individual in capitalism as a phenomenon existing only in connection to the relations of interdependence that dominate it. Doing so, Marx's account undermines the dichotomy Butler imposes between independent individuals and interdependency.

This dialectic, Marx's analysis reveals, expresses the heart of capitalist interdependency itself. As Marx explains in the Grundrisse, interdependency, as an objective bond, exists as the historical product of human activity, one belonging to a specific phase in the development of the individual (p. 162). That this interdependency takes an alien and objective form in capitalism only proves that individuals “are still engaged in the creation of the conditions of their social life” (p. 162). The individuality found in capitalism, Marx holds, presupposes “production on the basis of exchange values as a prior condition” (p. 162). In other words, capitalist interdependency is intimately tied to the individual as an independent producer and exchanger, a social role that capitalist production uniquely necessitates.

The historical specificity of capitalist interdependency highlights the transhistoricism of Butler's account. Butler's naturalization of capitalist interdependency can be explained by the fact that interdependency both has a specific character in capitalist society and is a necessary feature of all human existence. In Butler, this necessity is conflated with its historically determined form in capitalism, appearing as an expression of the human condition: one is dependent on others for survival (Butler, 2015).16 As mentioned in the introduction, Marx (1992) famously critiques the political economists for manifesting the same tendency, revealing the failure of Adam Smith's analysis as lying in its treatment of historical formations as innate characteristics of human beings. In presenting features of capitalism as eternal and naturally given, Butler's account preserves this tendency, thus failing to analyze the capitalist mode of production and its social relations.

In treating interdependency as a natural fact, Butler's social ontology fails to communicate anything beyond the truism that interdependency changes over time. Thus, social ontology neglects to accomplish its purpose: rather than analyzing the social forces that form the individual, it dilutes and flattens them into general features of the human condition. Capturing the processes that bear on the body in capitalism, by contrast, requires a historical description of those processes. In indicating what such a description would look like, the foregoing account exposes interdependency as the principal mode of domination in capitalism.

Distinguishing between historically distinct forms of interdependency reveals a crucial fact about Butler's account: that the form of interdependency their theory ontologizes is capitalist. Indeed, the tendency to ontologize historically specific features of capitalism is the modus operandi of Butler's theory. This is most evident in their theory of ontological equality. Recall that for Butler ontological equality is not an equality of independent individuals but denotes an equality of “beings” characterized by “[s]ingularity” and “defined and sustained by virtue of their interrelationality” (2020, p. 16). This ontological condition contains two key features: nonindividual singularity and equality. In examining each of these features, this section argues that each is unique to capitalist society. In turn, this analysis shows that Butler's theory of the natural human condition is the ontologization of a condition that is unique to capitalist society: equal interdependence.

The political implication of Butler's transhistoricism and ontologization is that it severs the relation between equality and violence in capitalism. An essential thesis in Butler's work is that equality and violence are mutually exclusive and thus that equality can combat violence.21 Indeed, they firmly hold that “most forms of violence are committed to inequality, whether or not that commitment is explicitly thematized” (Butler, 2021). The idea that violence expresses and intensifies social inequality leads them to argue for “radical equality” (p. 142). This commitment is founded on a double oversight: first, of equality in capitalism and, second, of radical equality as mass extermination. It is only by overlooking these two sociohistorical manifestations of equality that Butler can present it as an ontological good to be realized.

Butler cleanses equality of violence in indicating that the social realization of the radical equality characterizing our ontology necessarily challenges neoliberal precarity. However, equality, as theorists like Tocqueville, Arendt, and Marx have warned, is no safeguard against violence. In particular, Adorno extends the analysis of equality to genocide, arguing that genocide is inextricably linked to capitalism's tendency to integrate by equalization (Adorno, 2007). Integration, as we saw earlier, as a process of sameness, expresses capitalist equality. Thus, without denying or discrediting forms of hyperinequality and their violence, Adorno shows how violence itself can be a manifestation of equality as the reduction of all to the same. “[G]enocide is the absolute integration. It is on its way wherever men are leveled off—‘polished off,’ as the German military called it—until one exterminates them literally, as deviations from the concept of their total nullity” (p. 362). The liquidation of the particular is, for Adorno, a manifestation of exchangeability—the making of nonidentical things commensurable—and thus equality (p. 362).

Adorno further theorizes the liquation of the individual in total integration through fungibility (p. 362). “[T]here could be no swapping,” Adorno writes, “without disregard for living human beings” (p. 354). The disregard that makes possible the swapping of individuals as the condition of possibility for fungibility is, for Adorno, equality. Particularly, the equality expressed in capitalist exchange reaches its radical manifestation in the camps (p. 146). But, for this very reason, the significance of Auschwitz, for Adorno, goes beyond the camp. The latter, for him, is just the most extreme manifestation of the regressive tendencies of modernity, both of which function through the principle of equality in equalizing human beings to death (Adorno, 2005). The advent of Auschwitz, in other words, indexes the utilization of the achievements of modern civilization for systemic mass murder. The principle of equality is realized in genocide.

If equality is a principle of genocide, then Butler's “radical equality” itself can manifest in absolute integration, utter exchangeability, and redundancy. An examination of their understanding of genocide illuminates the shortcomings of their politics of equality. Critiquing Arendt's analysis of Eichmann, Butler predicates their understanding of genocide on the argument that Eichmann's crimes against humanity were ultimately an effect of his inability to recognize ontological precariousness and thus the normative demands it purportedly placed on him (Butler, 2015). In their reading, Butler discards Arendt's understanding of genocide as intimately tied to superfluity (Birmingham, 2018). Note, however, that superfluity for Arendt is not transhistorical but rooted in capitalist and imperialist attempts to render humans equally superfluous. Arendt grounds this tendency in capitalist laws themselves, understanding genocide as a manifestation of capitalism's tendency to reduce all to the same. That is, contra Butler, genocide is not a product of one's ignorance of ontology; it is capital's movement of equalization that generates superfluity and genocide.

Butler's idealist solution to genocide elucidates the dangers of their framework. Having dissociated Arendt's critique of Eichmann from her critique of capitalism, Butler argues that Eichmann's actions would have been avoidable if his attitude had been different. As Birmingham puts it: “[T]he thought seems to be that had Eichmann understood the shared condition of precariousness, he might have been less vulnerable to the dominant norms of whose lives were grieveable and whose could be eradicated from the face of the earth” (2018). In other words, the complex problem of genocide is given the simple idealist solution of a change in perspective.

Butler's reading of Eichmann and account of genocide is a direct result of their ontology. They cannot think of genocide as a total integration—as a historical expression of exchangeability—because they understand equality and interdependency to be inherently opposed to capitalism. Their framework, thus, elides capitalism's most egregious forms of violence.

To conclude, I want to suggest that Butler's transhistorical and ontologizing tendencies preclude the possibility of emancipatory theory and praxis. This shortcoming can be located in Butler's categories, which, I contend, are not emancipatory because they terminate in existing society, rather than reaching beyond it.

Capitalism, contrary to Butler's analysis, is not the unequal distribution of a prior, ontological state, but the domination of fragmented individuals by social labor that produces a historically unprecedented interdependency. Therefore, the interdependency in which we find ourselves locked is not an idyllic ontological condition veiled by superimposed capitalist relations, but our domination by our own product: capital. Lacking an analysis of capitalist interdependence, Butler confuses the violent historical formation of capitalist interdependency with an ontological claim to a shared world. Consequently, they not only mask historical relations as facts of nature but also treat existing relations as an ontology to be realized.

While at first blush admirable in its aspiration, a close examination of Butler's politics, as this article has sought to provide, reveals that it capitulates into capitalism's status quo. Masquerading capitalist relations as ontological truths enables Butler to demand the realization of an already existing condition. Of course, I am not suggesting that we live in a society of equality and interdependency as such; rather, what I have endeavored to show is that it is precisely the forms equality and interdependency take in capitalism that Butler renders as ontological conditions to be socially realized. Butler's politics of equality is, thus, nothing other than a concealed version of bourgeois egalitarianism. If the state of equality shared by nonindividuals is a core feature of capitalism, and one of its most brutal expressions of the degradation of human beings, then it cannot challenge neoliberal ideology as Butler suggests.

Butler's theory testifies to the fact that one cannot escape the determinations of their own society. Indeed, their attempts to do so merely result in features of society sneaking in and infiltrating their theory nonetheless, thus rendering them impotent to either escape or critique them. Thus, the liberalism they attempt to overcome is replicated in their theory, leading them, alongside a long tradition of bourgeoise thinkers to call for equality. The categories Butler deploys—from interdependence to nonindividual singularity, and equality—do not negate but reproduce existing society. And indeed, their categories cannot help but terminate in existing society; they are, after all, borrowed from it.

Butler, therefore, cannot theorize beyond the present. Consequently, they can neither critique nor immanently elucidate historical dynamics intrinsic to capitalist social formations—such as interdependency and equality—that necessarily point beyond themselves. Having ontologized capitalist interdependency, they are trapped within it and forced to maintain that there is no way out. Accordingly, they render the task of politics as “accept[ing] interdependency as a condition of equality” (Butler, 2021). In this framework, the condition for emancipation is not the abolition of precariousness but the realization of an unhindered, equal distribution of precariousness. In other words, Butler perceives emancipation as emancipation in precariousness not from precariousness. But if precariousness itself, as we saw, is largely the ontologization of capitalist structures, then the emancipation Butler seeks lies strictly within the capitalism.

The necessity of critiquing Butler's theory is that it illuminates dangers potentially inhering in ontologically derived politics. The issue with political theories rooted in ontology is not merely that their ideological function is to provide naturalistic explanations of social phenomena; it is also that they attempt to shape human nature in accordance with the social phenomena they purport to explain. To expose the ideological components of such theories is, simultaneously, to struggle for the transformation of society. Thus, in contrast to Butler, a historical account of interdependency serves as a starting point for an articulation of emancipation as emancipation from capitalism.

My argument here opens a number of avenues for future work, which would more fully develop an ideology critique of existing ontologies that inform so much of contemporary political philosophy and ethics. A critical theory of society that begins from the specific structure and determinations of our society as a capitalist one can reveal otherwise abstract forms of oppression, violence, and domination. Critiques emerging from the historical specificity of our society—i.e., from the standpoint of capitalist production—allow us to think about emancipation from capitalism. To that end, a historical account of interdependency is imperative, not only for the sake of historical accuracy but also to reveal the sources of violence in capitalism and the praxis necessary to overcome them. Because, as I argue, capitalist domination functions through, not against, interdependency and equality, denunciations of violence today must simultaneously denounce the forms interdependency and equality take in capitalist society.

查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
作为意识形态的本体论:巴特勒不稳定性理论批判
在过去的十年里,政治哲学家们越来越多地运用相互依存、平等和脆弱性的概念来批判当代社会这些概念在学术界内外都广受欢迎,它们提供了规范性的锚点,使人们能够以更平等的社会的名义批评新自由主义的个性、独立和弹性理想。因此,尽管许多学者谴责现有社会中的暴力,但他们回避谴责人类的相互依赖、平等、脆弱性和不稳定性相反,这些概念被视为掌握了我们基本的本体论条件。事实上,他们抵抗新自由主义原子独立幻想的能力据称源于他们揭示新自由主义隐藏的真相的能力:人类在本体论上是相互依存和平等的。因此,这一真理被认为带有自己的伦理原则,要求通过政治行动实现平等。因此,今天对这些概念的使用动员的不仅仅是一个本体论;它还提供了一种对现存社会的解释——偏离和隐藏本体论——以及一种寻求根据本体论组织社会的政治。在许多持这一立场的声音中,朱迪思·巴特勒的可能是最突出的,特别是他们在后期作品中阐明的不稳定性的本体论因此,本文对巴特勒的本体论及其由此衍生的政治进行了批判性的探讨。当然,巴特勒的工作并非没有受到批评。然而,现有的关于他们工作的争论主要集中在他们所谓的“道德转向”上,以及他们对脆弱性和责任的描述这些争论本身就很重要,它们要么倾向于接受巴特勒本体论的基本结构,要么不去挑战它尽管评论家们仔细审视了巴特勒本体论的批判潜力和局限性,尤其是她对脆弱性的描述(例如,Gilson, 2011),但他们却没有审视巴特勒本体论的两个最核心的特征:相互依赖和平等。在这样做的过程中,即使是那些批评巴特勒工作的人也坚持巴特勒的假设,即相互依赖和平等是本质上反对新自由主义个人主义、独立性、弹性和不平等的本体论特征。相比之下,在本文中,我通过将这两个原本被接受的概念提交给历史唯物主义分析来批判巴特勒的本体论。在这方面,我的目的是揭示巴特勒本体论的意识形态基础,并注意它对资本主义社会的投降。在此过程中,本文揭示了巴特勒本体论和政治学的局限性。它表明,他们的理论不能充分把握资本主义暴力和统治的根源,因此不能提供一种解放的政治。为此,本文提出了两个中心主张:第一,巴特勒的本体论是超历史的;第二,这一理论是资本主义社会的本体论。第一节通过概述巴特勒对新自由主义的本体论批判,为这一批判奠定了基础。第二部分认为,巴特勒运用了一种超越历史的方式来描述相互依赖。借鉴卡尔·马克思对资本主义相互依赖的分析,即建立在客观依赖基础上的个人独立,我表明巴特勒忽视了相互依赖的历史特殊性。与巴特勒的观点相反,这一节揭示了相互依存并不是一个需要通过政治来实现的隐蔽的本体论条件,而是资本主义社会已经实现的条件。在第三部分,我转向西奥多·阿多诺,以表明巴特勒对资本主义社会的特征和关系进行了本体论化。我认为巴特勒本体论的核心特征——我们通过相互依赖而平等——是资本主义特有的。在前资本主义社会,相互依赖的特点是不平等。相比之下,只有在资本主义出现之后,相互依存才以平等为前提。最后,在第四部分和结论部分,我探讨了巴特勒对资本主义社会历史特征的本体论所带来的有害政治风险。在第四部分,我分析了巴特勒对种族灭绝的描述,以表明他们的本体论忽略了资本主义社会中平等的暴力。最后,我探讨了巴特勒的本体论方法在解放政治理论化方面的局限性。然而,在讨论这些论点之前,我希望澄清本文的中心目的。这篇文章不提供本体论理论化的批判。它也没有试图以某种方式宣称人类不是相互依赖的、平等的、脆弱的或不稳定的。我必须强调的是,它并没有试图提供一种新的本体论或巴特勒的替代方案。 相反,我的目标是强调以本体论为中心的批评对社会正义和解放理论与实践问题的危险。因此,在揭示巴特勒本体论的意识形态基础时,我的核心愿望是双重的。首先,我希望将我们的注意力不仅转向新自由主义意识形态,而且转向作为一种独特社会形式的资本主义本身。其次,通过这样做,我希望激发对当代哲学中发挥作用的本体论主张的进一步批判性反思。在通过历史唯物主义方法追求这些目标的过程中,本文建立在一个长期的哲学传统之上,试图揭示霸权本体论主张的意识形态特征。对关于人性的普遍主张和理论的批判对哲学家来说并不新鲜。在这里,马克思对亚当·斯密的交换归化理论的批判,列万廷对查尔斯·达尔文的自然选择进化论的批判,以及c.b.麦克弗森对托马斯·霍布斯关于自然状态的描述的解读,都浮现在我的脑海中正如这些理论家和其他人所表明的那样,真理主张并不适用于所有时间和地点;相反,它们反映了它们所产生的社会的主导思想、价值观和结构。女权主义思想家的贡献——其中包括巴特勒本人——在这方面同样是无价的。7 .女权主义者通过质疑所谓人性的捏造,揭露了本体论的意识形态成分,并且批判了这些成分对现存社会不平等的自然化和合法化针对达尔文主义和生物决定论等明显案例的批评比比皆是。然而,当代哲学也复制了将社会关系自然化的趋势——尽管是以更微妙的方式。巴特勒的本体论,如本文所示,是这方面的一个重要例子。在将巴特勒的本体论置于历史唯物主义批判之下时,我们至少可以预见到三种主要的阻力。首先,巴特勒的早期作品开创了对身体自然主义概念的批判。因此,指责他们后来的作品复制了他们曾经强烈反对的趋势(例如,Butler, 1993),可能会被认为是一种公然的误读。然而,正如我将进一步讨论的那样,他们后来的工作显然采用了自然/社会二分法,正如他们的不稳定性/不稳定性区分所证明的那样(Lloyd, 2015)。其次,我们应该回顾巴特勒后来的工作旨在动员一种非传统的本体论,他们称之为“社会本体论”(巴特勒,2009)巴特勒认为,社会本体论并不是“对基本结构的描述”;相反,他们认为,它独特地将“身体的‘存在’”称为“暴露于社会工艺和形式之下”(第3页)。尽管巴特勒的社会本体论可能是复杂的,但它仍然是本体论。正如我们看到巴特勒自己所表达的那样,之所以如此,是因为社会本体论中的“社会”实际上只是指人类状况的一种基本结构:身体受影响和形成的内在能力。因此,社会本体论只是将本体论的他者——社会的、历史的或偶然的——并入本体论本身。事实上,正如我在这篇文章中,尤其是在第三节中所展示的那样,巴特勒本体论化的社会特征是他们自己社会的特征。因此,社会本体论,就像达尔文或霍布斯的自然主义一样,是那个时代的杰出代表。最后,还有一个常识性的反对我的论点:“但巴特勒不是完全正确吗?”人类一直是不稳定的、脆弱的和相互依赖的。那么,这些当然是我们本体论的一部分了。”本文的目的并不是要反驳这种观点。相反,我接下来的目的是要表明,在巴特勒的本体论中,社会是从后门进入的:在那里,资本主义社会的特征伪装成普遍的、本体论的真理。也就是说,尽管我承认所有人类社会都存在相互依赖、脆弱性和不稳定性,但我认为巴特勒没有把握住它们,因为他们把资本主义形式误认为是普遍存在的。然而,正如本文所揭示的那样,这一根本性的失误将巴特勒的理论困在了它试图批判的社会的范围内。巴特勒对新自由主义进行了本体论批判。他们反对不稳定的、相互依赖的主体的本体论条件,反对自主和独立个人的新自由主义概念,他们认为独立的个人是虚构的,并且否认平等和相互依赖的本体论条件。因此,正如本节所示,巴特勒从对不稳定性的本体论解释中得出了他们对新自由主义和平等主义政治的批判。对Butler来说,不稳定性指的是相互依赖、脆弱和身体暴露于社会经济和政治力量的本体论条件(Butler, 2009)。 巴特勒写道,不稳定性是人类状况不可避免的特征,因为它“与出生同时延伸”(第14页)。事实上,正如他们所写的那样,它遵循“我们作为肉体存在的社会存在,我们相互依赖住所和生计,因此,在不公正和不平等的政治条件下,我们面临无国籍、无家可归和贫困的风险”(巴特勒,2015)。巴特勒认为,在相互依赖的条件下,隐含着另一个本体论结构:平等。“相互依赖,”他们写道,“虽然考虑到独立和依赖的差异,但意味着社会平等:每个人都是依赖的,或者在依赖和被依赖的关系中形成和维持”(巴特勒,2021)。对巴特勒来说,我们都是平等的,因为没有人是完全独立的。因此,不稳定是一种自然平等相互依赖的状态。然而,巴特勒将不稳定的平等与我们社会状况的不平等进行了对比。他们强调,尽管脆弱性标志着每个人的存在,但特定人群的脆弱性是不同的(Butler, 2009)。为了捕捉这种不稳定性的不平等分配,Butler引入了“不稳定性”的概念(第3页,25-26页)。他们将不稳定性描述为“一个更具体的政治概念”(第3页),其中一个命名为“不稳定性最大化的政治诱导条件”(第26页)。具体来说,巴特勒认为,“不稳定性”是“不稳定性的差异分布”,其中“某些人群遭受失败的社会和经济支持网络,并变得不同地暴露于伤害,暴力和死亡”(第26页)。对巴特勒来说,不稳定性指的是我们在社会上未能实现平等相互依存的本体论条件。因此,它抓住了新自由主义政策、专制国家暴力、警察暴力、监禁、战争和种族灭绝如何使某些人群的不稳定性增加(第26、115、147页;2015,第11页)。不稳定和不稳定的姐妹概念是巴特勒政治的基础。正如莫亚·劳埃德(Moya Lloyd)所指出的那样,它们使巴特勒能够区分“主要的脆弱性,即所有人都分享给他人的本体论条件”和“某些人面临的不安全和责任的具体、特殊、历史条件”(巴特勒,2015)。这种区别使巴特勒能够批判不稳定性的各个方面,准不稳定性,同时肯定不稳定性,并将其作为一种新的责任伦理的基础。巴特勒认为,“对共同的不稳定性的认识,引入了强有力的平等的规范性承诺,并促使更强有力的权利普遍化,寻求解决人类对食物、住所和其他持续和繁荣条件的基本需求”(巴特勒,2009)。通过从共享的脆弱性和相互依赖的本体论条件中推导出伦理义务,巴特勒因此假设我们有义务保护他人的生命,因为我们无法独立生存(第113页)。更准确地说,由于不稳定性是不稳定性的差异分配,对巴特勒来说,伦理要求成为不稳定性的非差异或平等分配(第25页)。他们“呼吁平等宜居的生活”,“需要平等地分配公共物品”(2015年,第69页)。因此,巴特勒的政治是对平等分配的规范要求。然而,在这里,巴特勒的平等主义是建立在对平等的特殊理解之上的。因为他们的平均主义来源于本体论的相互依赖,Butler将平等描述为“非个人主义的”,或超越个人的平等(Butler, 2021)。巴特勒坚持认为,这种本体论上的平等“不能简化为赋予每个抽象的人相同价值的演算”(第16页)。因此,巴特勒告诉我们,本体论所隐含的平等形式并不是“单一而独特”的个体的自由平等;相反,它是奇点的平等,“通过它们的相互关系来定义和维持”(第16页)。在本体论上,我们在从未“完全个体化”的情况下是平等的(第46页)。巴特勒对本体论的非个人主义平等的描述是他们批判资本主义的基础。通过对比本体论平等与社会不平等,巴特勒将资本主义描绘为否认相互依赖和平等(巴特勒,2009年,2015年)。他们写道,在“当代条件下”,“存在着一场针对相互依赖观念的战争”和“试图将生命的不可居住性最小化的手的社会网络”(第67页)。此外,在Butler看来,自由主义和新自由主义的资本主义意识形态促进了独立和自给自足的个人的谬误(Butler, 2009, 2021)。资本主义及其新自由主义的个人主义幻觉掩盖、违反和否认全球相互依存,从而产生不稳定性(Butler, 2021)。 巴特勒声称,新自由主义的个人主义将不稳定性描绘成一种需要根除的威胁。这样一来,它就传播了生命可以得到保护的幻想,从而为助长不稳定的政府机制辩护。相比之下,巴特勒认为,旨在通过消除不稳定性来对抗不平等的政治是徒劳的,因为我们的本体论无法被消除。他们写道,伦理-政治任务“不是为了实现自给自足而克服依赖,而是接受相互依赖作为平等的条件”(第47页)。相比之下,他们认为,本体论通过提供“平等”作为“组织健康、食物、住所、就业、性生活和公民生活的社会组织的原则”,帮助我们对抗不稳定性(Butler, 2021)因此,Butler寻求在平等主义条件下建立平等的相互依存关系:通过平等地分配公共物品,最大限度地减少不稳定性,建立“平等宜居的生活”(Butler, 2015)。这样,巴特勒的平等政治将通过充分认识不稳定性来消除不稳定性。正如贾内尔·沃森(Janell Watson, 2012)所说,巴特勒对不平等强加的新自由主义不稳定性的平等主义解决方案是“所有人的不稳定性”。在反对新自由主义的不稳定性的同时,巴特勒认为个人独立只存在于小说中,我们被剥夺了平等相互依存的本体论状态。但是,独立的个人究竟是一种幻觉呢,还是它在现存社会中具有客观的现实性呢?相互依赖是一种隐蔽的、尚未实现的本体论条件,还是不同的社会以不同形式的相互依赖为特征?巴特勒,我将在下面说明,将资本主义描述为某种程度上缺乏或反对相互依赖的社会是不正确的。相反,资本主义的出现并不标志着从相互依赖的社会向个人主义社会的转变;它构成了从一种相互依赖形式到另一种相互依赖形式的过渡。在理论化这些变化的形式时,本节提供了一种相互依赖的非本体论解释。这一叙述反过来又揭示了巴特勒本体论的超历史特征。澄清一下,我提出这样一种说法,并不否认相互依存一直是每个社会的特征。然而,接受某些特征在不同的人类社会中持续存在,并不是立即从事超历史的理论化。例如,当马克思说迄今为止存在的所有社会都是阶级社会时,他的意思并不是说阶级是本体论的一个不可避免的特征——事实上,他的结论恰恰相反。恩格斯,[1848]2010)。此外,承认所谓“阶级”在历史上的特定形成,在方法论上阻止了我们把阶级当作“阶级本身”来对待。这就是说,在任何情况下,阶级的内容完全取决于它所处的社会。因此,马克思关于迄今为止存在的一切社会都是阶级社会的主张是一个历史的主张,而不是一个超历史的主张。在马克思的基础上,我对相互依存的历史解释阐明了它在其存在的不同社会中所采取的特定形式。这揭示了巴特勒的超历史主义:他们倾向于忽略历史的特殊性,从而将相互依存关系减少为一种静态的、不变的本体论特征,适用于所有时代和所有地方。要从历史上分析相互依存关系,我们可以从考察它在资本主义中的形态开始。在这里,考虑巴特勒关于资本主义及其新自由主义意识形态是独立和原子性个性的表达的说法,与其说是错误的,不如说是片面的。尽管巴特勒在本体论的相互依存和独立的社会幻想之间建立了一个二分法,但资本主义的相互依存必须与它的社会关系看起来像独立的事实联系起来理解。因此,把握资本主义相互依存的形式,就需要把资本主义与独立的辩证关系解释为资本主义的独特特征之一。马克思认识到,相互依存是资本主义社会的特征,而不是自然的相互依存和社会强加的独立。正如他在《政治政治批判大纲》中所论证的那样,资本主义的相互依赖标志着从固定的个人依赖关系向“建立在客观依赖基础上的个人独立”的过渡(马克思,1993)。马克思分析了资本主义的相互依赖与个人自由的关系,个人自由源于封建社会的个人依赖关系的解体,资本主义生产方式的出现,以及随之而来的社会关系。对马克思来说,资本主义社会构成了一个整体,在这个整体中,个人无论其社会角色如何,都是完全融合在一起的。 也就是说,为了作为独立生产者生存,所有个体都必须参与劳动分工这种整合形成了一个相互依赖的紧密网络,但它并不完全否定个人的个人独立性。更确切地说,资本主义的相互依赖构成了自我决定、自由和自主的个人与客观必然性领域之间的对立。因此,正如历史学家Moishe Postone所说的那样,它将个人自由描述为“一种更全面的不自由形式”,这种不自由形式根植于一系列历史特定条件,在这些条件下,“人们以一种支配和强迫他们的形式创造历史”(Postone, 2012)。换言之,资本主义生产方式打破了封建的相互依存形式,构成了一个以新的相互依存形式为特征的社会。具体来说,资本主义中产生相互依赖的原因是劳动来调解社会关系。在以前的社会中,劳动及其产品是按照各种传统规范和公开的权力和统治关系(如奴隶关系、封建关系、亲属关系或个人和直接服从他人)生产和分配的相反,在资本主义社会,人们不再消费自己生产的东西;相反,一个人的劳动及其产品是获得他人的产品以供消费和生存的手段。也就是说,仅仅生产是不够的;一个人也必须交换。在中介交换中,资本主义中的劳动带来了一种新的相互依赖形式,即每个人都依赖于其他所有人来生存。因此,劳动成为一切社会关系的中介,而不是像前资本主义社会那样被这些社会关系中介。资本主义中劳动的独特性质带来了一种特殊的相互依存形式。在资本主义社会中,每个人的劳动都以同样的社会中介方式发挥作用:每个人的具体劳动都是整体的一部分,作为抽象劳动,它是构成资本主义社会整体的同质、普遍、社会中介的一个环节(Postone, 1993)。在这里,劳动的专一性被抽象,而劳动及其物化成为单个个体获取他人产品的手段。通过这一过程,资本主义生产产生了其独特的相互依赖形式:每个人都依赖他人来维持生计,因为每个人的劳动都是所有社会关系的中介因此,与巴特勒的假设相反,资本主义并没有“就其本身”消解相互依赖;相反,它在消灭封建的相互依存的同时,也让位于一种新的相互依存形式。此外,使巴特勒的解释进一步复杂化的是,马克思的分析揭示了相互依存不是自然赋予的,而是社会强加的。在资本主义中,相互依赖不是一个脆弱的、需要保护的本体论条件,正如巴特勒所假定的那样,而是一种强制性的整合形式。在资本主义中,劳动不再是一种直接的生存手段,而是一种获取他人商品的手段(Postone, 2012)在交换关系的基础上,资本主义劳动迫使我们融入商品生产的过程。资本主义的强制性相互依赖最好理解为统治。到目前为止,社会关系的中介被描述为间接的、隐蔽的和抽象的,它产生了一种具有这些特征的统治形式。例如,与古代奴隶社会或封建社会相比,资本主义统治是独特的抽象。正如波斯顿所解释的那样,这种统治“不以任何人、阶级或机构为基础;它的最终轨迹是资本主义社会的社会形式的普遍结构,而资本主义社会的社会形式是由社会实践的确定形式构成的”(Postone, 1993)。也就是说,资本主义的统治不能追溯到特定群体或个人的代理;相反,它是所有为了生存而参与资本主义关系的个人活动的产物。相互依存的强制性同时也是它的统治形式。资本主义相互依存的抽象本质有助于我们解释为什么巴特勒得出资本主义的主要特征是个体独立性的结论。正如马克思所认识到的那样,正是因为资本主义相互依赖的客观形式是隐蔽的,所以它根本不会立即表现为一种相互依赖的形式(马克思,1993)。也就是说,与早期社会不同,资本主义社会的人们虽然相互依存,但看起来是独立的。马克思的异化概念有助于解释这种现象。众所周知,马克思的异化表达了人类被自己的生产活动及其产品——资本——所支配的过程。 虽然这个过程是个人之间的社会关系,但在他们看来,这是他们“从属于独立于他们而存在的关系,这些关系产生于相互冷漠的个人之间的冲突”(马克思,1993)。在这些社会关系中表现出来的个人的基本相互依赖,也就是说,被相互依赖的、然而又是异质的生产方式所掩盖。因此,马克思解释说:“活动和产品的一般交换,即他们的相互联系,已经成为每个人的生存条件,在这里却表现为与他们不相干的东西,表现为自主的东西,表现为物”(第157页)。因此,独立性的出现是从资本主义生产方式的异化条件中产生出来的。然而,马克思对异化的描述并没有否定资本主义中个人的形式独立性。相反,它保留了独立与相互依存的辩证关系。在马克思的历史分析中,个人从统治的人际关系中获得前所未有的独立的过程——通过传统社会关系的解体——与个人对统治的客观、抽象、非个人的经济关系的日益依赖是同步的(第158页)。因此,他将资本主义中独立个体的出现解释为一种现象,这种现象只存在于主导资本主义的相互依存关系中。这样做,马克思的描述破坏了巴特勒强加的独立个体和相互依赖之间的二分法。马克思的分析表明,这种辩证法表达了资本主义相互依赖本身的核心。正如马克思在《政治经济学批判大纲》中所解释的那样,相互依存作为一种客观的纽带,作为人类活动的历史产物而存在,属于个人发展的特定阶段(第162页)。这种相互依存关系在资本主义中采取了一种异质的客观形式,这只能证明个人“仍然参与创造他们的社会生活条件”(第162页)。马克思认为,资本主义中的个体性以“以交换价值为先决条件的生产”为前提(第162页)。换句话说,资本主义的相互依赖与作为独立生产者和交换者的个人密切相关,这是资本主义生产所特有的社会角色。资本主义相互依存的历史特殊性突出了巴特勒的叙述的超历史主义。巴特勒对资本主义相互依存的归化可以用这样一个事实来解释:相互依存既是资本主义社会特有的特征,也是所有人类存在的必要特征。在巴特勒看来,这种必要性与其在资本主义中历史决定的形式相结合,表现为人类状况的一种表达:一个人的生存依赖于他人(巴特勒,2015)正如引言中所提到的,马克思(1992)对政治经济学家表现出同样的倾向进行了著名的批评,揭示了亚当·斯密分析的失败,因为它将历史形成视为人类的先天特征。在将资本主义的特征呈现为永恒和自然的过程中,巴特勒的描述保留了这种倾向,因此未能分析资本主义的生产方式及其社会关系。在将相互依赖视为一种自然事实的过程中,巴特勒的社会本体论除了相互依赖随时间而变化这一真理之外,没有传达任何东西。因此,社会本体论忽略了实现它的目的:它不是分析形成个体的社会力量,而是将它们稀释和扁平化为人类状况的一般特征。相比之下,在资本主义中捕捉对身体产生影响的过程,需要对这些过程进行历史描述。在指出这种描述的样子时,前面的描述揭示了相互依赖是资本主义统治的主要模式。区分历史上截然不同的相互依赖形式,揭示了巴特勒描述的一个关键事实:他们的理论本体论的相互依赖形式是资本主义的。事实上,对资本主义的历史特征进行本体论化的倾向是巴特勒理论的运作方式。这在他们的本体论平等理论中表现得最为明显。回想一下,对于巴特勒来说,本体论的平等不是独立个体的平等,而是指“存在”的平等,其特征是“独特性”和“通过其相互关系来定义和维持”(2020,第16页)。这个本体论条件包含两个关键特征:非个体奇点和平等。在研究这些特征时,本节认为每个特征都是资本主义社会所独有的。 反过来,这一分析表明,巴特勒关于人类自然状态的理论是资本主义社会特有的一种状态的本体论:平等的相互依存。巴特勒的超历史主义和本体论的政治含义在于割断了资本主义中平等与暴力的关系。巴特勒作品中的一个重要论点是平等和暴力是相互排斥的,因此平等可以对抗暴力事实上,他们坚定地认为“大多数形式的暴力都致力于不平等,无论这种承诺是否明确地主题化”(Butler, 2021)。暴力表达和加剧社会不平等的观点导致他们主张“激进的平等”(第142页)。这种承诺建立在双重监督的基础上:首先是资本主义的平等,其次是大规模灭绝的激进平等。只有忽略了平等的这两种社会历史表现,巴特勒才能将其呈现为一种有待实现的本体论善。巴特勒指出,作为我们本体论特征的激进平等的社会实现必然挑战新自由主义的不稳定性,从而清除了暴力平等。然而,正如托克维尔(Tocqueville)、阿伦特(Arendt)和马克思(Marx)等理论家所警告的那样,平等并不能防范暴力。特别是,阿多诺将对平等的分析扩展到种族灭绝,认为种族灭绝与资本主义通过平等化来整合的倾向密不可分(阿多诺,2007)。正如我们前面看到的,一体化是一个趋同的过程,表达了资本主义的平等。因此,阿多诺没有否认或质疑各种形式的超级不平等及其暴力,而是展示了暴力本身如何能成为平等的一种表现,即把所有人都还原为相同。“[G]enocide是绝对的整合。无论人类在哪里被消灭——德国军方称之为“被消灭”——它都在前进,直到人们从字面上消灭他们,因为他们偏离了他们完全无用的概念。对阿多诺来说,特殊性的清算是一种可交换性的表现——使不相同的事物变得可通约性——因此是平等的表现(第362页)。阿多诺通过可替代性进一步理论化了个人在整体整合中的消解(第362页)。阿多诺写道:“如果不忽视活着的人,就不可能有交换。”(第354页)。对阿多诺来说,使个体交换成为可能,作为可替代性可能性条件的漠视,就是平等。特别是,在资本主义交换中表现出来的平等,在劳改营中达到了激进的表现(第146页)。但是,正是由于这个原因,对阿多诺来说,奥斯维辛的意义超越了集中营。对他来说,后者正是现代性倒退趋势的最极端表现,两者都通过平等原则发挥作用,使人类与死亡平等(Adorno, 2005)。换句话说,奥斯维辛集中营的出现标志着现代文明成就被用于系统性的大规模屠杀。平等原则在种族灭绝中得以实现。如果说平等是一种种族灭绝的原则,那么巴特勒的“激进平等”本身可以表现为绝对整合、完全交换和冗余。考察一下他们对种族灭绝的理解,就会发现他们平等政治的缺陷。在批评阿伦特对艾希曼的分析时,巴特勒认为艾希曼的反人类罪最终是由于他无法认识到本体论的不稳定性,从而无法认识到据称对他提出的规范性要求,从而推断了他们对种族灭绝的理解(巴特勒,2015)。在他们的阅读中,巴特勒抛弃了阿伦特对种族灭绝与过剩密切相关的理解(Birmingham, 2018)。然而,请注意,阿伦特的多余不是超越历史的,而是植根于资本主义和帝国主义试图使人类同样多余的企图。阿伦特将这种倾向根植于资本主义法律本身,将种族灭绝理解为资本主义倾向于将所有人都归为同一人的一种表现。也就是说,与巴特勒相反,种族灭绝不是一个人对本体论无知的产物;正是资本的均等化运动产生了过剩和种族灭绝。巴特勒对种族灭绝的理想主义解决方案阐明了他们的框架的危险。巴特勒将阿伦特对艾希曼的批评与她对资本主义的批评分离开来,他认为,如果艾希曼的态度不同,他的行为本来是可以避免的。正如伯明翰所说:“他似乎认为,如果艾希曼理解了不稳定的共同条件,他可能不会那么容易受到主导规范的影响,这些规范的生活是可悲的,可以从地球表面根除”(2018)。换句话说,种族灭绝这一复杂问题被赋予了改变观点的简单理想主义解决方案。 巴特勒对艾希曼的解读和对种族灭绝的描述是他们本体论的直接结果。他们不能把种族灭绝看作是一种完全的融合——一种历史上对可交换性的表达——因为他们明白,平等和相互依赖本质上是反对资本主义的。因此,他们的框架忽略了资本主义最恶劣的暴力形式。最后,我想提出巴特勒的超历史和本体论倾向排除了解放理论和实践的可能性。这个缺点可以在巴特勒的范畴中找到,我认为,这些范畴不是解放的,因为它们终止于现有社会,而不是超越它。与巴特勒的分析相反,资本主义并不是一种先验的、本体论状态的不平等分配,而是社会劳动对支离破碎的个人的统治,这种统治产生了历史上前所未有的相互依赖。因此,我们发现自己被锁在其中的相互依赖,并不是一种被叠加的资本主义关系所掩盖的田园诗般的本体论条件,而是我们被自己的产品——资本——所支配。由于缺乏对资本主义相互依存的分析,巴特勒混淆了资本主义相互依存的暴力历史形成与对共享世界的本体论主张。因此,他们不仅把历史关系当作自然事实来掩盖,而且把现存关系当作有待实现的本体论来对待。虽然乍一看,巴特勒的抱负令人钦佩,但仔细研究巴特勒的政治,正如本文试图提供的那样,揭示了它向资本主义现状投降。把资本主义关系伪装成本体论的真理,使巴特勒能够要求实现一个已经存在的条件。当然,我并不是说我们生活在一个平等和相互依存的社会;相反,我努力要表明的是,正是巴特勒将资本主义中平等和相互依存的形式呈现为社会实现的本体论条件。因此,巴特勒的平等政治只不过是资产阶级平均主义的一个隐蔽版本。如果非个人共享的平等状态是资本主义的核心特征,是人类堕落最残酷的表现之一,那么它就不能像巴特勒所说的那样挑战新自由主义意识形态。巴特勒的理论证明了一个事实,即一个人无法逃避自己社会的决定。事实上,他们这样做的企图只会导致社会特征潜入并渗透到他们的理论中,从而使他们无法逃避或批评他们。因此,他们试图克服的自由主义在他们的理论中被复制,导致他们与资产阶级思想家的悠久传统一起呼吁平等。巴特勒运用的范畴——从相互依赖到非个体的独特性,以及平等——不是否定而是再生产现存的社会。诚然,它们的范畴在现存的社会中不能不终止;毕竟,它们是借来的。因此,巴特勒的理论不能超越现在。因此,他们既不能批判也不能内在地阐明资本主义社会形态内在的历史动态——比如相互依存和平等——这些必然指向自身之外。他们把资本主义相互依存的关系本体论化了之后,就被困在其中,被迫坚持认为没有出路。因此,他们认为政治的任务是“接受相互依赖作为平等的条件”(Butler, 2021)。在这个框架中,解放的条件不是消除不稳定性,而是实现不稳定性的不受阻碍的、平等的分配。换句话说,巴特勒认为解放是在不稳定中解放而不是从不稳定中解放。但是,如果不稳定性本身,正如我们所看到的,主要是资本主义结构的本体论化,那么巴特勒所寻求的解放就严格地存在于资本主义内部。批判巴特勒理论的必要性在于,它阐明了本体论衍生的政治中潜在的危险。根植于本体论的政治理论的问题不仅仅在于它们的意识形态功能是为社会现象提供自然主义的解释;他们还试图根据他们声称要解释的社会现象来塑造人性。同时,揭露这些理论的意识形态成分,就是为社会的变革而斗争。因此,与巴特勒的观点相反,对相互依赖的历史描述是将解放作为从资本主义中解放的表述的起点。我在这里的论点为未来的工作开辟了许多途径,这将更充分地发展对现有本体论的意识形态批判,这些本体论为当代政治哲学和伦理学提供了很多信息。 从我们作为资本主义社会的具体结构和决定出发的社会批判理论,可以揭示压迫、暴力和统治的抽象形式。从我们社会的历史特殊性中产生的批评。从资本主义生产的角度来看,允许我们思考从资本主义中解放出来。为此,对相互依存的历史描述是必不可少的,这不仅是为了历史的准确性,也是为了揭示资本主义暴力的根源和克服它们所必需的实践。因为,正如我所说,资本主义统治是通过相互依赖和平等发挥作用的,而不是反对相互依赖和平等,今天对暴力的谴责必须同时谴责资本主义社会中相互依赖和平等的形式。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
52
期刊最新文献
Issue Information Issue Information Issue Information Fear of Black Consciousness By Lewis R. Gordon. Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2022 Deparochializing Political Theory By Melissa S. Williams, New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 2020
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1