Impartiality and fair play revisited

IF 2.9 1区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS Journal of Political Philosophy Pub Date : 2023-04-06 DOI:10.1111/jopp.12300
Brookes Brown
{"title":"Impartiality and fair play revisited","authors":"Brookes Brown","doi":"10.1111/jopp.12300","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>It is not fair to ask of others what you are not willing to do yourself.(Eleanor Roosevelt).</p><p>Something seems troubling about Miguel's behavior. Yet it is hard to say what he is doing wrong. He did not ask anyone to act for his benefit. He never agreed to any park-walking plan. Given the number of people involved in the watch (imagine it is a town with thousands of volunteers at the ready), he is not meaningfully adding to anyone's burden.</p><p>Put more precisely:</p><p>Much about this claim is controversial: does the mere receipt of benefits really trigger obligations? Does this hold if beneficiaries do not acquiesce? Must the relevant benefits track objective or subjective good? But my interest lies in a further puzzle, one that arises once we accept that something in this vein explains the wrongness of Miguel's actions.</p><p>Many scholars treat <i>Park</i> and <i>Snow</i> as different in kind. While the former is said to involve wrongful free-riding, the latter is viewed as a <i>predatory demand</i>. Consequently, while Miguel is said to have a duty to join in, Neda is thought to do nothing wrong if she refuses to pay the bill.</p><p>The problem is that the two scenarios look remarkably similar. In both situations, a group of people provide an unrequested benefit and take their doing so to trigger an obligation for beneficiaries to repay in a manner specified by their benefactors. My goal in this essay is to make sense of these competing intuitions by developing an account of what differentiates predatory demands from practices that properly generate duties of fair play. In fact, I will argue, cases like <i>Snow</i> and <i>Park</i> are even more similar than theories of fair play have acknowledged. Nonetheless, we can distinguish the two by properly situating fair play in the broader moral landscape. Doing so better grounds the duty and, more precisely, illuminates its scope—but it requires profoundly reimagining what fair play asks of us in a way that calls into question long-standing assumptions about civic ethics.</p><p>My argument proceeds as follows. In Section I, I detail an account of the moral motivation that underlies the duty of fair play. Building on recent work by Garrett Cullity and others, I argue that such obligations arise from a concern for fairness best understood as a demand for appropriate impartiality. Those who free-ride make unjustified exceptions by granting themselves a privilege that they would deny to others. In Section II, I raise a challenge to recent attempts by Isabella Trifan to flesh out the relevant notion of impartiality. We can, she suggests, distinguish cases of free-riding and predatory demands by looking to participants' attitudes. On her account, people are similarly situated such that non-contributions constitute violations of impartiality so long as they share a preference for receiving the same good without contributing to its production. But this approach, I show, fails to capture widespread and appealing beliefs about fairness.</p><p>In Section III, I propose an alternative. Fairness concerns arise whenever people are willing to accept others working to their good, but unwilling to return the favor. This approach, I show, makes better sense of our intuitions. However, as I reveal in Section IV, it suggests significant revisions to our understanding of fair play. Accepting it requires upending long-standing claims about our responsibility to vote, pay taxes, and undertake other civic acts. In Section V, I defend this view against objections. The <i>reciprocity approach</i>, I argue, provides a more parsimonious, grounded, and instructive account of fair play, one that better explains and distinguishes cases of wrongdoing and predatory demands.</p><p>Underlying defenses of fair play is a concern for fairness. Beneficiaries are said to treat benefactors <i>unfairly</i> when they fail to participate in the scheme from which they have benefited. Rawls, for example, writes, “We are not to gain from the cooperative labor of others without doing our fair share.”4 Klosko holds that non-cooperation is problematic because “th[e] situation is unfair.”5 Murphy regards lawbreakers as acting wrongly because they enjoy an “unfair profit.”6</p><p>Just what defines something as unfair, and the features in virtue of which an act qualifies as such, have remained largely unspecified in discussions of fair play. In recent scholarship, only Garrett Cullity and Isabella Trifan have sought to offer a systematic account.7 Fairness, they argue, is a matter of <i>appropriate impartiality</i>. A judge ought not to prefer one convicted felon over another in sentencing because of the former's religion, a professor should not grade her spouse, all the participants in a soccer game should be held to the same offside rule. Free-riders, they argue, act wrongly because they violate this standard. In refusing to repay the benefits that they have received, such actors permit themselves a privilege they would deny to others.</p><p>I think this focus on impartiality captures something important about transactional fairness. The request that others treat us <i>fairly</i> is importantly comparative. In this way it is distinct from the demand that we receive what we want or even otherwise merit. The worry is lest we be treated <i>differently</i> to our detriment. Of course, not all differential treatments fail this standard. If I enter the children's race, I will not be awarded a medal even if I run faster than my toddler opponent. The question is what qualifies an act as instantiating an unjustified privilege?</p><p>When these features are present, a person who avoids contributing unjustifiably exempts herself from rules that she would apply to others. But those who do so in cases that lack these desiderata exhibit no such bias: they would take <i>everyone</i> to have good reason to act in the same way.</p><p>This account, Cullity argues, succeeds in our aim: it distinguishes cases where fair play applies from those to which it does not, permitting us to identify wrongful demands. Situations like <i>Snow</i>, he suggests, violate the third requirement. To take Neda to have to pay the elves, “would mean holding everyone liable to pay for all unsolicited benefits that are worth their cost.” This, he contends, would be destructively inefficient.9</p><p>Here is the problem. <i>Park</i> can be read as having the same form as <i>Snow</i>: a group of people provide an unsolicited benefit and demand reasonable payment (in the former case, that Miguel join the patrol; in the latter that Neda pay the bill). If this behavior violates the generalization requirement in the latter case, why not in the former?</p><p>Like the neighborhood watch, the scientists provide a good (enhanced health) that improves everyone's lives. Framed this way, the case passes the test. Contributing both to this and to any similar future efforts would make each person better off. At the same time, the scientists did <i>precisely</i> what the elves were doing—providing drive-by benefits and hoping to get paid. According to Cullity, such behavior flunks the test. The account thus fails to provide conclusive guidance: which features should we treat as salient for the purposes of generalization?</p><p>They share this attitude, she holds, so long as—and only so long as—their preferences are ordered:</p><p>Trifan takes this view to provide the clarity we seek. On this reading both Miguel and the townsfolk act wrongly if they refuse to pay up. Each shares with their benefactors the right point of view: the desire that the park and the water supply be made safe without their having to contribute to the process of making it so (in the case of the scientists because—or so Trifan posits—they share in a duty to keep consumers healthy). In contrast, the elves are not interested in the benefit that they provide (or so we are to presume). What they want is not to have the sidewalk shoveled: it is <i>to be paid</i>.13 Consequently, Neda violates no rule of impartiality in failing to pay her bill.</p><p>This case violates the FRP as Trifan understood it. Mary does not desire the benefit of having you water the plants that she does not have. According to the shared preferences account, you thus have no obligation to repay her efforts. But that seems silly: there doesn't seem anything predatory if Mary expects you to return the favor with cat-sitting, cookies, a ride to the airport. Indeed, the stakes here precisely echo fair-play scholars' complaint: if you do nothing to Mary's benefit, you enjoy an unfair profit. You are better off and she worse off because of work that she did to your good. Far from being fair, if Mary were (for example) to ask you to check in on her cat while she was away, the declaration that “I owe you nothing because you don't have a garden” would ring almost bizarrely churlish.</p><p>If Cullity's explanation is unduly vague, Trifan's thus proves unduly narrow, cutting out cases that seem to generate real considerations of fairness. There is, however, a way to revise the view that avoids this mistake. We can capture the sense that Mary's efforts deserve reciprocation by recasting the FRP. As formulated, the approach presumes that persons are similarly situated only insofar as they share an interest in particular goods—watered flower garden, washed cars. This vastly limits the set of cases to which fair play applies. Our tastes and aims are diverse. You love dark chocolate; I hate it. You care about arias; I only like Norwegian death metal. But we need not view ourselves as operating in such distinct spheres. Despite our differing views on Zumba classes or DIY home renovation, there is something we share—a broader mutual concern for a world where people <i>provide benefits that enrich our lives</i>. My life goes better when you go out of your way to return my lost wallet; your life goes better when I refill the printer paper or drop off cookies in the breakroom. Each of us equally desires that others not take advantage of our own such efforts. You do not want your work on my behalf to go unreciprocated; I want the same for my efforts.</p><p>In this way, Mary and you find yourselves in the same position despite your divergent hobbies. Both of you have an interest in other people advancing your projects. While you need help with your faltering garden, Mary may find herself requiring assistance with her car or somebody to take in the mail before it is stolen. At a more general level, your preferences thus align precisely as Trifan would desire. Each of you share the preference ordering (for simplicity's sake, here and going forward, I will focus on the first two preferences, since Trifan takes them to encompass all the elements relevant for the FRP) that:</p><p>This view rescues our intuitions about fairness. If, given this preference ordering, you are willing to have Mary work on your behalf without doing the same, you do precisely that which Cullity and Trifan found to violate impartiality: make an unjustified exception of yourself by holding others to standards you would not yourself employ.</p><p>The challenge is that this formulation of the FRP no longer answers our original puzzle in what we took to be the right way. While <i>Garden</i>, <i>Enterprising Scientists</i>, and <i>Park</i> all qualify as demanding a return, so too does <i>Snow</i>. After all, the elves really do work for Neda's benefit at a cost that all-things-considered she is willing to pay.</p><p>The solution lies in further revising and refining the FRP. There are, I think, two improvements required: the first to the way the approach conceptualizes costs, the second to the way it conceptualizes benefits. Let's start with the former.</p><p>Recall that our aim is to identify the ways in which parties must be similarly situated for non-contributions to count as violations of impartiality. As currently formulated, the FRP takes parties to have this status so long as they both share a preference for receiving a benefit at the price of “bearing the benefits-producing costs,” though they would prefer to receive it for free. This focus on the cost of producing the benefit is, presumably, itself intended to reflect a concern for fairness. After all, the thing that is said to trigger the obligation is the fact that one party has taken on those very costs to the advantage of the other. To equalize the situation, we are to infer, the beneficiary should join the benefactor in paying the price <i>by joining in the production of the good from which they have benefited</i>.</p><p>It is worth noting that, although this repayment structure is baked into the FRP and often taken for granted by scholars of fair play, it is not, in fact, something that Trifan seems to accept, though she offers no explanation. After all, her view is not that having benefited from the work of the scientists, the townspeople are duty-bound to study water safety and take up a practice of roving do-gooding, but rather that they ought to pay the bill with which they have been presented. In light of this, there are two ways to read the FRP. On one reading, the cost that beneficiaries must be willing to bear involves joining the processes required to produce the relevant goods, as Hart and Rawls suggest. On another, beneficiaries are duty-bound to pay a reasonable price for the good that they have received, as determined by the benefactors.14 The two readings are linked, since benefactors presumably play some part in determining the structure of the benefits-producing practice.</p><p>For our purposes, selecting between these readings is irrelevant: both violate impartiality. In either case, benefactors reserve a privilege for themselves that they would deny to beneficiaries. The issue is this. Benefactors choose the good that they will provide <i>at their own discretion</i>. Your neighborhood watch, your city's road builders, your garden-watering neighbor do not—in many cases <i>cannot reasonably</i>—ask whether you would prefer they build park trails or lay new train lines. This is in part what distinguishes fair play from consent or contract. All that matters in generating the obligation is that the resulting good is genuinely beneficial and the cost not too high. By contrast, beneficiaries are said to enjoy no such freedom. They are required <i>either</i> (on the first reading) to contribute to the production of the good they received (selected at the benefactor's discretion) <i>or</i> (on the second) to pay the price (set by the benefactor). In this way the parties are <i>not</i> similarly situated: benefactors exercise discretion over how they advantage beneficiaries, beneficiaries lack this privilege.</p><p>According to the classic account of fair play reflected in the FRP, Jane acts wrongly. Despite her distaste for the smell, she would (we can imagine) prefer assisting in repainting to leaving the walls undone. She is thus said to possess the free-rider's mindset. <i>But,</i> Jane could say, <i>she is not making an exception of herself</i>. She is doing <i>precisely</i> what her benefactors are doing—contributing to their good at her own discretion. In this way her behavior is consistent and impartial: she would take <i>everyone</i> to have reason to act in the same manner.</p><p>Taking the wrongness of unfair play to consist in violations of impartiality thus supports a revised version of the FRP, one that takes a more open-ended approach to payment:</p><p>This version of the FRP maps more neatly onto the cases that we have explored, with greater explanatory power. On this reading, Jane acts appropriately in <i>Baking</i>, but behaves unfairly in <i>Inaction</i> when she does nothing to her neighbors' benefit. Miguel's neighbors equally have cause for complaint when he benefits from the neighborhood watch, but does nothing for them. Unlike <i>shared preferences,</i> this approach makes sense of the intuition that Mary's work watering your garden triggers a real concern for fairness. And unlike that account, it can sensibly explain what went wrong in <i>Snow</i>. The problem isn't that the elves didn't want sidewalks shoveled (perhaps they did!). Rather, the issue is that the elves <i>took themselves to have the right to dictate the terms of repayment</i>. Their error lay in <i>presenting a bill</i>. By doing so, they took themselves to have the right to impose obligations to act <i>in particular ways</i> over their beneficiaries—a right they did not take their beneficiaries in turn to have over their behavior. This violates impartiality.</p><p>Critics might raise two objections to <i>mutual exchange</i>: that it is unjustifiably partial, and that it fails to reflect persons' actual shared preference-rankings. Let's consider each in turn.</p><p>First, detractors might deny that Jane and her neighbors occupy the same position in <i>Baking</i>. While the neighbors are bound to abide by the painting scheme, Jane has retained for herself the right to repay their efforts in whatever form she desires: cakes, plumbing, a communal garden. She thus enjoys a freedom that they lack. But, notice, if the neighbors are bound to the painting scheme, it is only because they <i>committed</i> to doing so.16 Like Jane, they had the freedom to choose a different path. Even if we were to treat this loss of freedom as a cost that must be included in our calculation, surely it too can be repaid by taking on additional burdens.17 Imagine that Jane builds her neighbors a new laundry room, plants a rose garden, and bakes them weekly treats. Something would seem very off if Jane's neighbors were to complain she acted unfairly, while happily eating her cakes among the flowers she laboriously nurtures.</p><p>Still, opponents might insist that <i>mutual exchange</i> fails to capture participants' and non-cooperators' <i>actual</i> preferences. Both, they might argue, prefer receiving goods at the cost of being bound to (depending on your preferred reading) adopt the same practices as those who benefited them or pay producers' reasonable demands. Consequently, a person like Jane who acts otherwise grants themselves an unjustified exception. As we will see in Section IV, I think the revised FRP can answer the real concern at the heart of this objection—the worry that we will not be able to work together to produce valued goods. Nonetheless, it is important to see that this concern is not foundational to our account of impartial action, as this critique would have us believe.</p><p>The idea that people wish to be <i>bound</i> to act as their benefactors demand is both unrealistic and utterly unappealing. Why would I take it to be a given that, simply because somebody has done <i>something</i> to my benefit, at their own discretion, they get to tell me exactly how to behave? The distastefulness of this notion is precisely what lends force to many famous objections to fair play.18 It seems <i>unfair</i> that one party could come in this manner to exercise such control over another—an intuition that makes sense only if this is not a realistic measure of the relevant shared preferences. Of course, I have reason to <i>consider</i> my benefactors' requests—I am well inclined towards those who benefit me—but that is quite different from being <i>obliged</i> to obey their dictates.</p><p>We can make better sense of the notion that people desire to be bound to replicate the benefit-producing behavior from which they have profited, especially in the kind of cases long favored by advocates of fair play—complex cooperative ventures such as those necessary to advance public health or safety. In such instances, participants and beneficiaries might each fear that others exercising discretion will vitiate the relevant benefit: too few people will show up for jury duty, vote, serve in the military. Consequently, they may prefer others to be bound to act as the scheme requires, even at the cost of being so required in turn and despite their lack of control over the initial selection of the relevant good or the precise manner of its provision.19</p><p>But the claim that this captures our preferences seems mistaken on several grounds. We have already seen one example. It is commonplace to feel we have moral reason to act on others' behalf differently from how they acted to our benefit: we rely on them when our car breaks down, they on us when they need to carry a couch up on the stairs. If these exchanges are subsumed into a single practice, the restrictions lose all relevant purpose—they do not hold people to advancing specific benefits. If they do not, then this approach either altogether rejects an ordinary feature of our moral experience or demands that we develop a distinct further theory to explain such cases.</p><p>But perhaps we can succeed at the latter. Critics might argue that this preference ordering applies to a very specific set of cases—large-scale interactions which lend themselves to free-riding, because we need <i>enough</i>—but not everyone—to undertake a task if we are to succeed at producing the relevant good. Such circumstances are routine: we need enough people to serve in the military, vote, go carbon neutral. However, it does not make sense to conclude on these grounds that all of us prefer that <i>everyone</i> be bound to take up the relevant task. Indeed, such a demand would be absurd. It would require that <i>everyone</i> be farmers, dentists, school-crossing guards, sewer-system experts.20 That isn't just unattractive—it is impossible.</p><p>What we really want is not for everyone to take up such roles, but for everyone to be attentive and responsive to whether enough people are doing the necessary work.21 What we would like even more is that those who do not themselves undertake the relevant acts (having satisfied themselves that sufficiently many are doing so) perform further valuable labor to our benefit. When they do so, we <i>each</i> end up both equally situated and better off—all have paid a price necessary to produce goods and all have benefited from such work. Fair play is not a leveling-down principle. The demand is not simply that others suffer. I don't <i>really</i> want other people to make their way to the polls when the right candidate's election is secured—I want them to do something actually productive to help bring about good social conditions. Miguel's neighbors don't really desire a 400th person on nightly patrol in the medium-sized park—what they want is <i>a sufficient number</i> of people at the job, and others promoting the good through further, more efficacious, means—improving the lighting on local streets, planting a flower garden.</p><p>The challenges of coordination give us a reason to be humble and careful in our assessments of where our participation is required, but not a reason to accept that we be duty bound to undertake innumerable actions that add no value. This is especially true because public goods are rarely one-shot deals. We receive regular feedback as to whether enough people are going on patrol or using solar panels.</p><p>Finally, this do-as-I-do approach overlooks an important worry for impartiality: the fact that persons are routinely <i>not</i> similarly situated. It is more costly for a single mother working two jobs to get to the polls than a tenured professor on sabbatical. It seems fundamentally unfair to ask they do the same task in anticipation of the same benefit when the burdens involved differ so dramatically. One person might reasonably balk at being asked to take on an unequal cost. Now, proponents might say that schemes with this feature fail the <i>morality</i> standard and thus do not activate concerns for fairness. Still, this would in practice apply to almost any realistic large-scale cooperative scheme. Such practices are slow-moving and often inattentive to individual circumstances in a way that makes it unlikely they will ever, in themselves, fully succeed at laying out rules that divide work in a genuinely equitable fashion. It is thus reasonable to conclude that people might share a preference for taking on a fair share of the labor of working to others' good, without being willing to undertake precisely the same acts as others, or bow to the dictates of the scheme in which they have participated.</p><p>Although these objections fail, they do reflect an important way in which <i>mutual exchange</i> proves discordant with our intuitions. Earlier, we treated <i>Park</i> and <i>Scientists</i> as clear instances of wrongful free-riding. Indeed, our central task was explaining what distinguished these cases from inappropriate demands like <i>Snow</i>. That is precisely what the FRP was intended to do. But our revised approach classifies both as predatory demands. Neither the participants in the watch nor the scientists have the right to specify the form in which their efforts are repaid. Both behave no better than the elves when they require the townsfolk to pay up, Miguel to show up.</p><p>There is a sense in which I think that this is correct. None of these benefactors has a right to specify the way beneficiaries' debts are satisfied. <i>Park</i>, <i>Scientists</i>, and <i>Snow</i> thus share the same moral mistake. Nonetheless, I think more can be said to explain our sense that the former cases generate concerns for fairness absent in the latter. I will say more to reconstruct <i>Park</i> in Section IV. For now, let us focus primarily on <i>Scientists</i>. Understanding how their claims differ from the elves' pushes us to further refine the FRP.</p><p>Earlier I suggested that each of us shares an interest in “others laboring on our behalf.” Read that way, the elves and the scientists have the same merit. Both work to others' benefit—in ways that we have reason to believe constitute a net gain to recipients. However, our interests are not <i>quite</i> so straightforward. To see this, we need to situate fair play in the broader moral landscape.</p><p>Freelance do-gooding is not the only way we seek to advance our projects or call on others to do the same. In many cases, institutions beyond others' kindness—the market, contract, consensual negotiation—better track our interests, are more effective and efficient means of benefit. They provide what we want at lower cost with greater control over our circumstances. Each of us thus shares an interest in the success of these institutions. Actions that undermine them are not to our benefit. Still, these institutions have their gaps and limits, in both ideal and non-ideal conditions. There are spaces where non-market actions do better at advancing what we care about, for any number of reasons. There is no company that notices my forgotten flower garden; markets do poorly at preventing pollution; in many places no affordable childcare services for the quite poor exist, nor reasonably priced green spaces. Fair play is suited to these interstitial gaps, to the spaces where other institutions and practices fail to best advance our interests. When people act to fill in these gaps, they provide a great benefit. Conversely, they threaten our well-being when they act to undermine institutions better suited to promoting the good, even when their immediate action technically provides a benefit.</p><p>This suggests a further revision to the FRP. Contributors and would-be free-riders are similarly situated insofar as they share the following attitudinal ordering:</p><p>Unlike <i>shared preferences</i> or <i>mutual exchange</i>, this approach successfully captures and explains our deeply held views about fairness in a way that makes sense of the felt difference between <i>Snow</i> and <i>Scientists</i>.</p><p>Consider the fact that discussions of fair play typically focus on public goods, benefits defined (among other things) by jointness in supply such that the provision of the good to one person entails furnishing it to all.22 The reciprocity account explains this emphasis. These goods are poorly suited to consent- or market-based approaches. It is simply too hard to negotiate terms, communicate agreement, or limit benefits to those who assent. The same is true of cases like <i>Garden</i>. Because Mary does not know where you are traveling, she would have a difficult time seeking consent to water your wilting plants. Many ordinary actions have this flavor: the return of lost keys, the carrying of printed papers from the copying room, the casual exchange of favors between friends are all for different reasons relatively poorly suited to the precise pre-negotiation and consent of formal market or contractual exchanges.</p><p>By contrast, in <i>Snow</i> we confront (or so we are told) an otherwise ordinary commercial case from which the usual avenues of consent and negotiation have been deliberately removed. Trifan herself says of a similar case, that it is, “a straightforward commercial transaction … more appropriately governed by explicit consent to receiving and paying for a benefit.”23 The would-be shovelers could easily have knocked on the door and asked if Neda was willing to pay their price (as someone did to me this morning). If Neda cared enough, we have every reason to believe that commercial shoveling services are readily on offer. Consequently, the elves are best read as acting <i>with the aim of getting a profit they might not be due in the efficient market system they would seek to prevent or disrupt</i>, rather than as <i>contributing to the well-being of others in a way that does not operate to upset otherwise beneficial practices</i>. Consequently, their behavior does not satisfy the reciprocity approach. As Cullity writes, “a commercial system that recognized this sort of liability would be so cripplingly inefficient that it would impoverish us.”24</p><p><i>Scientists</i> offers a more challenging case. The complication is not—as Trifan suggests—that the scientists share a moral obligation to provide clean water. Plenty of appropriately commercial transactions address issues of moral concern. The existence of a commercial pharmaceutical industry, for example, helps to protect the health of billions in good part <i>because of the informational, efficiency, and incentive-generating advantages of a market system</i>. Indeed, we could read the elves as sharing in a moral responsibility to clean the snow—I certainly take myself to have an ethical in addition to a legal responsibility to make my sidewalk safe for passersby.</p><p>Rather, what matters are the details Trifan inserts in the case. The scientists are “passing through,” not a permanent fixture in town. They implement the fix “overnight.” And, of course, they are scientists, not professional plumbers. We are given the impression of a one-off incident that required rare specialized expertise possessed by a group of people who had to act with little time, on an important issue, in conditions in which they could not realistically ask consent, and who do not seek to gain from the exercise; not a roving band of entrepreneurs attempting to set up a hit-and-run business model that subverts normal bid-and-contract procedures to acquire a profit they could not guarantee in an ordinary commercial transaction. The more this story rings true, the more the case seems to trigger genuine fair-play concerns, the less so, the more it seems a predatory demand—just as the reciprocity approach predicts.</p><p>The reciprocity approach thus achieves what we set out to do. It distinguishes predatory demands and actions that trigger fair play in a way that explains the distinction and grounds it in a broader systematic account of fairness. In doing so, however, the approach points to the need to quite radically revise our understanding of the resulting duty.</p><p>Our account challenges both these features. Let's begin with the cooperative scheme requirement. This attribute of fair play is oft-stated, but little defended. Instead, it is repeated like a mantra—though one that is (tellingly) violated in many famous examples, from Nozick's worry about book-pushing friends to Cullity's concern about shoe-repairing elves.26</p><p>The reciprocity approach rejects this requirement. Individuals do not need to receive benefits that result from collective schemes for the production of particular goods to trigger fairness concerns. Indeed, they need not even share an interest in the same goods. It is enough that one or more people do the right kind of work to others' profit. There is no moral distinction between our generous gardener Mary and the collection of neighbors who patrol Miguel's local park. Both reflect the same <i>duty of reciprocity,</i> an obligation to repay the burdensome labor others do to your benefit. Concerns for fairness thus arise equally in ordinary interpersonal exchanges and collective schemes.</p><p>If anything, what the reciprocity approach tells us about the rules condition is even more revolutionary. It is typically taken to be a central feature of fair play that it requires beneficiaries to <i>abide by the rules of the practice from which they have benefited</i>. This purportedly fundamental aspect of the duty has been taken to explain why citizens are obliged to vote, obey the law, pay taxes, and so on. But the reciprocity account rejects this requirement as contravening fairness. For benefactors to take themselves to have the right to dictate the way in which beneficiaries return their efforts, while reserving for themselves the right to provide goods at their own discretion, violates impartiality. While beneficiaries are duty-bound to return the good that they have received to their benefactor(s), the precise form in which they do so is up to them.</p><p>This suggests a very different picture of our civic obligations, one where tax-avoiding non-voters may escape moral critique. Nonetheless, I will argue that it is not as radical as it might seem. What follows is less a sweeping revision of how we should <i>behave</i> than a profound rethinking of the <i>reasons</i> that guide our behavior. While the classic account holds that citizens must obey the law or vote, because fairness by nature requires that they abide by the rules of the practice from which they have benefited, the reciprocity approach is more practical. It holds that citizens must <i>often</i> behave in these ways, because doing so is in many cases the only workable way to provide a benefit to all those to whom a debt is owed.</p><p>Remember that while the reciprocity approach does not require that beneficiaries obey the dictates of their benefactors, it does demand that they work to advance benefactors' interests. In small-scale cases, the options for doing so are near endless: I know that my colleague is worried about getting her car started in time to get her kid to school, wants to become a better runner, needs comments on a paper. But in large-scale cases such efforts come up against two problems: reach and diversity. As a citizen, I owe the millions who have paid taxes and showed up at the polls to my benefit. These people are not only numerous—they are very far apart, and they have very different interests and needs. Sam loves brownies, Jim is gluten-intolerant. Mary wants her house repainted, Jenn lives in a yurt. Lauren's dog requires walking, Fred hates animals and wishes to avoid any contact with them. As one person, it is nearly impossible for me to reliably know—much less seek to satisfy—these needs.</p><p>There is, however, one set of goods that I know is valued by every person who has worked to my benefit—the very goods they themselves worked to advance. Whatever their other differences, Sam, Jim, Mary, Jenn, Lauren, Fred, and millions of others see benefit in public safety, health, environmental cleanliness, and the other goods that their compliance with the law or exertions at the ballot box are intended to promote.27 Efforts to advance these goods thus constitute a benefit to each person whose work to promote those very same good has put me in debt.</p><p>In itself, this does not explain why citizens have special reason to vote or pay taxes. After all, there are lots of things you might do to advance the relevant goods. Fixing the pothole in front of your house promotes transportation; donating to a local free clinic could improve public health. However, these responses fail to account for both the breadth and the complexity of the relevant goods. Many good-promoting works have a localized effect. Your pothole repair may benefit Lauren, who lives on your block, but will do nothing at all for Jim who lives on the other side of town and never drives your way. Other actions provide value only if they align properly with fellow citizens' efforts. Your brilliant education plan is of little value if nobody implements it.</p><p>Beneficiaries of large-scale civic goods can thus see themselves as repaying their benefactors only insofar as they act as part of a joint effort to provide the relevant goods to the entire population to whom they owe a debt. In small-scale cases, such collective action is easy to achieve. You and I can build a bookshelf with a brief chat about parts, or tango by keeping an eye on how the other moves. But such structure is far more challenging to achieve in large-scale cases. It is difficult to imagine sustaining an effective system of public safety or health without structured efforts at harmonization; the tens of thousands of actions that play a part are unlikely to align absent formal coordination. To commit to the success of these goods is thus to aim at advancing an organized plan for their achievement.</p><p>And here we can see the value of practice rules. The dictates of the applicable cooperative practice just are the central features of the shared plan. That people pay these taxes or follow these laws are the pathways by which we have chosen to together produce the relevant goods. That we might have arranged ourselves so as to generate these goods through other means does not detract from the fact that this is our plan. Consequently, those who do not abide by the rules cannot see themselves as advancing the arrangement and thus cannot take themselves to benefit their benefactors as the reciprocity account requires.</p><p>This gives each of us good reason to obey the rules of large-scale practices from which we benefit. In turn—to return to our earlier discussion—this explains why cases like <i>Park</i> feel different from <i>Snow</i>. It isn't just that the elves are providing the wrong kind of benefit. It also matters that Neda has a greater range of options easily available by which to return the elves' favor. By contrast, Miguel will find it challenging to benefit all the members of his neighborhood watch without taking his turn on patrol. Because his individual efforts to bake cakes or light the sidewalk will almost certainly lack sufficient breadth of interest, reach or alignment, he is likely to find that joining in is the only way that he can pay his debt.</p><p>Still, it is important that Miguel's reasons are <i>pragmatic</i>, not a fundamental feature of fair play. It follows that there can be exceptions. If Miguel manages to knit a warm sweater for every winter walker or fix the dangerous cracks on the park trails, he can genuinely say that he has repaid his debts. His helpful neighbors cannot complain that he gave himself an unjustified exception if he fails to show up, flashlight at the ready. This matters, because the rule of complex practices like those from which we benefit as citizens often have limitations, inadequacies, or incomplete features that open opportunities for us to pay our debts without participating as the practice demands.</p><p>Lawmakers, for example, often lack the knowledge, skill set, or attention span to provide an adequate blueprint for the production of goods like health or public safety.28 The successful production of these goods thus routinely depends on others undertaking legally discretionary actions to fill in the gaps—not taking advantage of legally available loopholes, taking lower-paid jobs to promote effective public policy, and so on. Those who do such work advance the scheme, even if they fail to otherwise participate by showing up for jury duty or taking a turn at the ballot box. The reciprocity approach thus demands a more precise and nuanced account of fair citizenship.</p><p>This account has many advantages. Most notably, it demonstrates greater and more parsimonious explanatory power. Though discussions of fair play focus on fairness, they have traditionally provided no systematic account of the nature of this value. The reciprocity approach does so, grounding our demands for fair play in a deeper concern for appropriate impartiality. In doing so, the approach provides a singular theory, one capable of speaking to both individual and collective exchanges, and of distinguishing in each instance between predatory demands and fairness-generating benefits. Unlike more recent attempts to draw such distinctions, the view can capture and explain what have long looked like conflicting intuitions about the nature of fairness and our duty to others, in a manner that begins to make clear the value of non-voluntarily acquired obligations.29</p><p>Both can be read as efforts to stave off the conclusion that we are subject to an endless array of demands from others' work on our behalf. The reciprocity account, opponents might worry, denies just these restraints, generating too weighty a moral obligation.</p><p>While fair-play advocates like Tosi and Dworkin succeed at limiting our obligations, they do so by drawing unexplained—and I think unjustifiable—boundaries. Why do we owe some people who provide us with non-requested benefits repayment for their work, but not others? No reason is provided. The reciprocity approach offers a more attractive response. There are no artificial limits. We <i>do</i> owe others for the benefits they provide, at least when they are consistent with our general good and come at a cost. But it does not follow that we are required to pay the price our benefactors demand or take up the same actions in turn. We are merely obliged to do <i>something</i> to their benefit, at our discretion, just as they did for us. That your life is made better by a street musician does not mean you must toss him a bill. But this is not because you owe him nothing. It is because you can pay your debt in any number of ways: Perhaps you support the arts, perhaps you lobby to allow busking in the subways, vote for politicians who want to expand music licensing, or join the musician's efforts to provide joy and beauty by contributing in your own way. All can satisfy your duty.</p><p>This answers Dworkin and Tosi's real concern: isn't the price of acknowledging that we owe others for the work they do our benefit too high? The cost, we can now see, is rarely extensive. We can pay our debts just as easily as we acquire them. My life is routinely made better by the work of others, in ways large or small. People help me salt the sidewalk, pick up their dog poop, cheer me on as I run a marathon, donate to the local food bank. In turn, I often pay them back almost without thinking: planting flowers on the local bike trail, lending out my snowblower, racing after a father whose child has let a mitten fall unnoticed to the ground, hanging cheerful holiday decorations.32 And, of course, in the event that the cost of repayment ever exceeds the value I gain, such actions cease to generate duties of return. The reciprocity approach thus manages to restrict the weight of our duties without drawing contrived and groundless boundaries.</p><p>Fair play, the claim suggests, does not concern itself with <i>fairness</i> between beneficiaries and benefactors, but instead consists in a fundamental obligation to sustain particular beneficial practices. The fact that the reciprocity account accurately captures our intuitions about fairness thus does not tell us what fair play requires.</p><p>We have already seen several problems with this reading. To begin with, it lacks anything in the way of deeper explanation or grounding. While the reciprocity account finds further justification for its claims—the parties act wrongly in making unjustified exceptions for themselves—this account simply stipulates that fair play is fundamentally concerned with the preservation of specific institutions (who says exchanges are meant to sustain such practices? And how does this meaning generate obligation?).</p><p>Perhaps just as tellingly, this reading is discordant with our intuitions. In many cases, we cannot make sense of our feelings about reciprocal exchange by understanding them as intended to sustain particular schemes rather than productive social life more broadly. Take the view that we ought to respond to helpful efforts like Mary's in <i>Garden</i>.34 This is a commonplace intuition: others give us rides, make us soup when we are sick, feed our pets, dog-sit. We ought, we think, to return their efforts—but not necessarily in kind. Instead, we should <i>work to make their lives better</i>.</p><p>Similarly, concerns about reciprocity typically persist even when exchanges cannot possibly sustain a particular advantageous relationship. I should pay my taxes even if I am moving out of town tomorrow; I should leave my hair-cutter a tip even if I intend to frequent a different salon in the future. Conversely, such obligations continue even when the preservation of a practice is guaranteed. The fact that a scholarship program from which I once received assistance has secured a massive donation that will ensure its survival does not assuage my duty to give back. Indeed, the idea that it would is confusing. After all, arguments from fair play are typically meant to explain why non-action is wrong, <i>even when the existence of the relevant practice is secured</i>. The reciprocity approach thus makes better sense of our intuitions.35</p><p>Finally, opponents might worry that the reciprocity approach elides important distinctions between the interpersonal and collective contexts. But they would then be on the hook for explaining just what, precisely these differences are. Surprisingly little is on offer; the existence and moral salience of this distinction is typically taken for granted. As we have seen, morally salient features are, of course, often present in the collective context—the scale and nature of large-scale schemes often make consent, promise, or contract a challenge: communication and negotiation are too difficult, public goods too challenging to limit to willing participants.</p><p>These issues, though, are merely pragmatic, not fundamental to fair play. Nor do they support a strict distinction. After all, versions of these traits can also be found in the interpersonal context. If your friend notices your cat is in need of care while you are traveling, she may not be able to contact you to ask permission. If your neighbor repairs the apartment building's squeaky front door, all residents will benefit. And, of course, some collectively produced goods avoid these concerns—public transit provides an opportunity for consent, a collectively constructed well constitutes a private good. These ways of drawing boundaries between types of obligations thus give us no reason to cling to the cooperative scheme requirement over a more nuanced approach.</p><p>Much about the reciprocity approach to fair play remains to be worked out. Are qualifying benefits defined by objective goodness, subjective goodness, or some combination of the two? What defines some effort as “equivalent labor?” capable of repaying others' efforts? Nonetheless, the approach offers a rich alternative to the classic account of fair play, one that manages to both better capture and better explain our intuitions about fairness. Unlike the traditional approach, or newer attempts at precision like those offered by Cullity and Trifan, the view grounds our concerns and provides the resources to differentiate fairness-generating benefits from predatory demands, in a way suited to provide guidance to the full array of relations we bear to the individuals and collectives who contribute to our good.</p><p>None relevant.</p><p>There are no potential conflicts of interest relevant to this article.</p><p>The author declares human ethics approval was not needed for this study.</p>","PeriodicalId":47624,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Political Philosophy","volume":"31 3","pages":"315-336"},"PeriodicalIF":2.9000,"publicationDate":"2023-04-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/jopp.12300","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Political Philosophy","FirstCategoryId":"98","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/jopp.12300","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"ETHICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

It is not fair to ask of others what you are not willing to do yourself.(Eleanor Roosevelt).

Something seems troubling about Miguel's behavior. Yet it is hard to say what he is doing wrong. He did not ask anyone to act for his benefit. He never agreed to any park-walking plan. Given the number of people involved in the watch (imagine it is a town with thousands of volunteers at the ready), he is not meaningfully adding to anyone's burden.

Put more precisely:

Much about this claim is controversial: does the mere receipt of benefits really trigger obligations? Does this hold if beneficiaries do not acquiesce? Must the relevant benefits track objective or subjective good? But my interest lies in a further puzzle, one that arises once we accept that something in this vein explains the wrongness of Miguel's actions.

Many scholars treat Park and Snow as different in kind. While the former is said to involve wrongful free-riding, the latter is viewed as a predatory demand. Consequently, while Miguel is said to have a duty to join in, Neda is thought to do nothing wrong if she refuses to pay the bill.

The problem is that the two scenarios look remarkably similar. In both situations, a group of people provide an unrequested benefit and take their doing so to trigger an obligation for beneficiaries to repay in a manner specified by their benefactors. My goal in this essay is to make sense of these competing intuitions by developing an account of what differentiates predatory demands from practices that properly generate duties of fair play. In fact, I will argue, cases like Snow and Park are even more similar than theories of fair play have acknowledged. Nonetheless, we can distinguish the two by properly situating fair play in the broader moral landscape. Doing so better grounds the duty and, more precisely, illuminates its scope—but it requires profoundly reimagining what fair play asks of us in a way that calls into question long-standing assumptions about civic ethics.

My argument proceeds as follows. In Section I, I detail an account of the moral motivation that underlies the duty of fair play. Building on recent work by Garrett Cullity and others, I argue that such obligations arise from a concern for fairness best understood as a demand for appropriate impartiality. Those who free-ride make unjustified exceptions by granting themselves a privilege that they would deny to others. In Section II, I raise a challenge to recent attempts by Isabella Trifan to flesh out the relevant notion of impartiality. We can, she suggests, distinguish cases of free-riding and predatory demands by looking to participants' attitudes. On her account, people are similarly situated such that non-contributions constitute violations of impartiality so long as they share a preference for receiving the same good without contributing to its production. But this approach, I show, fails to capture widespread and appealing beliefs about fairness.

In Section III, I propose an alternative. Fairness concerns arise whenever people are willing to accept others working to their good, but unwilling to return the favor. This approach, I show, makes better sense of our intuitions. However, as I reveal in Section IV, it suggests significant revisions to our understanding of fair play. Accepting it requires upending long-standing claims about our responsibility to vote, pay taxes, and undertake other civic acts. In Section V, I defend this view against objections. The reciprocity approach, I argue, provides a more parsimonious, grounded, and instructive account of fair play, one that better explains and distinguishes cases of wrongdoing and predatory demands.

Underlying defenses of fair play is a concern for fairness. Beneficiaries are said to treat benefactors unfairly when they fail to participate in the scheme from which they have benefited. Rawls, for example, writes, “We are not to gain from the cooperative labor of others without doing our fair share.”4 Klosko holds that non-cooperation is problematic because “th[e] situation is unfair.”5 Murphy regards lawbreakers as acting wrongly because they enjoy an “unfair profit.”6

Just what defines something as unfair, and the features in virtue of which an act qualifies as such, have remained largely unspecified in discussions of fair play. In recent scholarship, only Garrett Cullity and Isabella Trifan have sought to offer a systematic account.7 Fairness, they argue, is a matter of appropriate impartiality. A judge ought not to prefer one convicted felon over another in sentencing because of the former's religion, a professor should not grade her spouse, all the participants in a soccer game should be held to the same offside rule. Free-riders, they argue, act wrongly because they violate this standard. In refusing to repay the benefits that they have received, such actors permit themselves a privilege they would deny to others.

I think this focus on impartiality captures something important about transactional fairness. The request that others treat us fairly is importantly comparative. In this way it is distinct from the demand that we receive what we want or even otherwise merit. The worry is lest we be treated differently to our detriment. Of course, not all differential treatments fail this standard. If I enter the children's race, I will not be awarded a medal even if I run faster than my toddler opponent. The question is what qualifies an act as instantiating an unjustified privilege?

When these features are present, a person who avoids contributing unjustifiably exempts herself from rules that she would apply to others. But those who do so in cases that lack these desiderata exhibit no such bias: they would take everyone to have good reason to act in the same way.

This account, Cullity argues, succeeds in our aim: it distinguishes cases where fair play applies from those to which it does not, permitting us to identify wrongful demands. Situations like Snow, he suggests, violate the third requirement. To take Neda to have to pay the elves, “would mean holding everyone liable to pay for all unsolicited benefits that are worth their cost.” This, he contends, would be destructively inefficient.9

Here is the problem. Park can be read as having the same form as Snow: a group of people provide an unsolicited benefit and demand reasonable payment (in the former case, that Miguel join the patrol; in the latter that Neda pay the bill). If this behavior violates the generalization requirement in the latter case, why not in the former?

Like the neighborhood watch, the scientists provide a good (enhanced health) that improves everyone's lives. Framed this way, the case passes the test. Contributing both to this and to any similar future efforts would make each person better off. At the same time, the scientists did precisely what the elves were doing—providing drive-by benefits and hoping to get paid. According to Cullity, such behavior flunks the test. The account thus fails to provide conclusive guidance: which features should we treat as salient for the purposes of generalization?

They share this attitude, she holds, so long as—and only so long as—their preferences are ordered:

Trifan takes this view to provide the clarity we seek. On this reading both Miguel and the townsfolk act wrongly if they refuse to pay up. Each shares with their benefactors the right point of view: the desire that the park and the water supply be made safe without their having to contribute to the process of making it so (in the case of the scientists because—or so Trifan posits—they share in a duty to keep consumers healthy). In contrast, the elves are not interested in the benefit that they provide (or so we are to presume). What they want is not to have the sidewalk shoveled: it is to be paid.13 Consequently, Neda violates no rule of impartiality in failing to pay her bill.

This case violates the FRP as Trifan understood it. Mary does not desire the benefit of having you water the plants that she does not have. According to the shared preferences account, you thus have no obligation to repay her efforts. But that seems silly: there doesn't seem anything predatory if Mary expects you to return the favor with cat-sitting, cookies, a ride to the airport. Indeed, the stakes here precisely echo fair-play scholars' complaint: if you do nothing to Mary's benefit, you enjoy an unfair profit. You are better off and she worse off because of work that she did to your good. Far from being fair, if Mary were (for example) to ask you to check in on her cat while she was away, the declaration that “I owe you nothing because you don't have a garden” would ring almost bizarrely churlish.

If Cullity's explanation is unduly vague, Trifan's thus proves unduly narrow, cutting out cases that seem to generate real considerations of fairness. There is, however, a way to revise the view that avoids this mistake. We can capture the sense that Mary's efforts deserve reciprocation by recasting the FRP. As formulated, the approach presumes that persons are similarly situated only insofar as they share an interest in particular goods—watered flower garden, washed cars. This vastly limits the set of cases to which fair play applies. Our tastes and aims are diverse. You love dark chocolate; I hate it. You care about arias; I only like Norwegian death metal. But we need not view ourselves as operating in such distinct spheres. Despite our differing views on Zumba classes or DIY home renovation, there is something we share—a broader mutual concern for a world where people provide benefits that enrich our lives. My life goes better when you go out of your way to return my lost wallet; your life goes better when I refill the printer paper or drop off cookies in the breakroom. Each of us equally desires that others not take advantage of our own such efforts. You do not want your work on my behalf to go unreciprocated; I want the same for my efforts.

In this way, Mary and you find yourselves in the same position despite your divergent hobbies. Both of you have an interest in other people advancing your projects. While you need help with your faltering garden, Mary may find herself requiring assistance with her car or somebody to take in the mail before it is stolen. At a more general level, your preferences thus align precisely as Trifan would desire. Each of you share the preference ordering (for simplicity's sake, here and going forward, I will focus on the first two preferences, since Trifan takes them to encompass all the elements relevant for the FRP) that:

This view rescues our intuitions about fairness. If, given this preference ordering, you are willing to have Mary work on your behalf without doing the same, you do precisely that which Cullity and Trifan found to violate impartiality: make an unjustified exception of yourself by holding others to standards you would not yourself employ.

The challenge is that this formulation of the FRP no longer answers our original puzzle in what we took to be the right way. While Garden, Enterprising Scientists, and Park all qualify as demanding a return, so too does Snow. After all, the elves really do work for Neda's benefit at a cost that all-things-considered she is willing to pay.

The solution lies in further revising and refining the FRP. There are, I think, two improvements required: the first to the way the approach conceptualizes costs, the second to the way it conceptualizes benefits. Let's start with the former.

Recall that our aim is to identify the ways in which parties must be similarly situated for non-contributions to count as violations of impartiality. As currently formulated, the FRP takes parties to have this status so long as they both share a preference for receiving a benefit at the price of “bearing the benefits-producing costs,” though they would prefer to receive it for free. This focus on the cost of producing the benefit is, presumably, itself intended to reflect a concern for fairness. After all, the thing that is said to trigger the obligation is the fact that one party has taken on those very costs to the advantage of the other. To equalize the situation, we are to infer, the beneficiary should join the benefactor in paying the price by joining in the production of the good from which they have benefited.

It is worth noting that, although this repayment structure is baked into the FRP and often taken for granted by scholars of fair play, it is not, in fact, something that Trifan seems to accept, though she offers no explanation. After all, her view is not that having benefited from the work of the scientists, the townspeople are duty-bound to study water safety and take up a practice of roving do-gooding, but rather that they ought to pay the bill with which they have been presented. In light of this, there are two ways to read the FRP. On one reading, the cost that beneficiaries must be willing to bear involves joining the processes required to produce the relevant goods, as Hart and Rawls suggest. On another, beneficiaries are duty-bound to pay a reasonable price for the good that they have received, as determined by the benefactors.14 The two readings are linked, since benefactors presumably play some part in determining the structure of the benefits-producing practice.

For our purposes, selecting between these readings is irrelevant: both violate impartiality. In either case, benefactors reserve a privilege for themselves that they would deny to beneficiaries. The issue is this. Benefactors choose the good that they will provide at their own discretion. Your neighborhood watch, your city's road builders, your garden-watering neighbor do not—in many cases cannot reasonably—ask whether you would prefer they build park trails or lay new train lines. This is in part what distinguishes fair play from consent or contract. All that matters in generating the obligation is that the resulting good is genuinely beneficial and the cost not too high. By contrast, beneficiaries are said to enjoy no such freedom. They are required either (on the first reading) to contribute to the production of the good they received (selected at the benefactor's discretion) or (on the second) to pay the price (set by the benefactor). In this way the parties are not similarly situated: benefactors exercise discretion over how they advantage beneficiaries, beneficiaries lack this privilege.

According to the classic account of fair play reflected in the FRP, Jane acts wrongly. Despite her distaste for the smell, she would (we can imagine) prefer assisting in repainting to leaving the walls undone. She is thus said to possess the free-rider's mindset. But, Jane could say, she is not making an exception of herself. She is doing precisely what her benefactors are doing—contributing to their good at her own discretion. In this way her behavior is consistent and impartial: she would take everyone to have reason to act in the same manner.

Taking the wrongness of unfair play to consist in violations of impartiality thus supports a revised version of the FRP, one that takes a more open-ended approach to payment:

This version of the FRP maps more neatly onto the cases that we have explored, with greater explanatory power. On this reading, Jane acts appropriately in Baking, but behaves unfairly in Inaction when she does nothing to her neighbors' benefit. Miguel's neighbors equally have cause for complaint when he benefits from the neighborhood watch, but does nothing for them. Unlike shared preferences, this approach makes sense of the intuition that Mary's work watering your garden triggers a real concern for fairness. And unlike that account, it can sensibly explain what went wrong in Snow. The problem isn't that the elves didn't want sidewalks shoveled (perhaps they did!). Rather, the issue is that the elves took themselves to have the right to dictate the terms of repayment. Their error lay in presenting a bill. By doing so, they took themselves to have the right to impose obligations to act in particular ways over their beneficiaries—a right they did not take their beneficiaries in turn to have over their behavior. This violates impartiality.

Critics might raise two objections to mutual exchange: that it is unjustifiably partial, and that it fails to reflect persons' actual shared preference-rankings. Let's consider each in turn.

First, detractors might deny that Jane and her neighbors occupy the same position in Baking. While the neighbors are bound to abide by the painting scheme, Jane has retained for herself the right to repay their efforts in whatever form she desires: cakes, plumbing, a communal garden. She thus enjoys a freedom that they lack. But, notice, if the neighbors are bound to the painting scheme, it is only because they committed to doing so.16 Like Jane, they had the freedom to choose a different path. Even if we were to treat this loss of freedom as a cost that must be included in our calculation, surely it too can be repaid by taking on additional burdens.17 Imagine that Jane builds her neighbors a new laundry room, plants a rose garden, and bakes them weekly treats. Something would seem very off if Jane's neighbors were to complain she acted unfairly, while happily eating her cakes among the flowers she laboriously nurtures.

Still, opponents might insist that mutual exchange fails to capture participants' and non-cooperators' actual preferences. Both, they might argue, prefer receiving goods at the cost of being bound to (depending on your preferred reading) adopt the same practices as those who benefited them or pay producers' reasonable demands. Consequently, a person like Jane who acts otherwise grants themselves an unjustified exception. As we will see in Section IV, I think the revised FRP can answer the real concern at the heart of this objection—the worry that we will not be able to work together to produce valued goods. Nonetheless, it is important to see that this concern is not foundational to our account of impartial action, as this critique would have us believe.

The idea that people wish to be bound to act as their benefactors demand is both unrealistic and utterly unappealing. Why would I take it to be a given that, simply because somebody has done something to my benefit, at their own discretion, they get to tell me exactly how to behave? The distastefulness of this notion is precisely what lends force to many famous objections to fair play.18 It seems unfair that one party could come in this manner to exercise such control over another—an intuition that makes sense only if this is not a realistic measure of the relevant shared preferences. Of course, I have reason to consider my benefactors' requests—I am well inclined towards those who benefit me—but that is quite different from being obliged to obey their dictates.

We can make better sense of the notion that people desire to be bound to replicate the benefit-producing behavior from which they have profited, especially in the kind of cases long favored by advocates of fair play—complex cooperative ventures such as those necessary to advance public health or safety. In such instances, participants and beneficiaries might each fear that others exercising discretion will vitiate the relevant benefit: too few people will show up for jury duty, vote, serve in the military. Consequently, they may prefer others to be bound to act as the scheme requires, even at the cost of being so required in turn and despite their lack of control over the initial selection of the relevant good or the precise manner of its provision.19

But the claim that this captures our preferences seems mistaken on several grounds. We have already seen one example. It is commonplace to feel we have moral reason to act on others' behalf differently from how they acted to our benefit: we rely on them when our car breaks down, they on us when they need to carry a couch up on the stairs. If these exchanges are subsumed into a single practice, the restrictions lose all relevant purpose—they do not hold people to advancing specific benefits. If they do not, then this approach either altogether rejects an ordinary feature of our moral experience or demands that we develop a distinct further theory to explain such cases.

But perhaps we can succeed at the latter. Critics might argue that this preference ordering applies to a very specific set of cases—large-scale interactions which lend themselves to free-riding, because we need enough—but not everyone—to undertake a task if we are to succeed at producing the relevant good. Such circumstances are routine: we need enough people to serve in the military, vote, go carbon neutral. However, it does not make sense to conclude on these grounds that all of us prefer that everyone be bound to take up the relevant task. Indeed, such a demand would be absurd. It would require that everyone be farmers, dentists, school-crossing guards, sewer-system experts.20 That isn't just unattractive—it is impossible.

What we really want is not for everyone to take up such roles, but for everyone to be attentive and responsive to whether enough people are doing the necessary work.21 What we would like even more is that those who do not themselves undertake the relevant acts (having satisfied themselves that sufficiently many are doing so) perform further valuable labor to our benefit. When they do so, we each end up both equally situated and better off—all have paid a price necessary to produce goods and all have benefited from such work. Fair play is not a leveling-down principle. The demand is not simply that others suffer. I don't really want other people to make their way to the polls when the right candidate's election is secured—I want them to do something actually productive to help bring about good social conditions. Miguel's neighbors don't really desire a 400th person on nightly patrol in the medium-sized park—what they want is a sufficient number of people at the job, and others promoting the good through further, more efficacious, means—improving the lighting on local streets, planting a flower garden.

The challenges of coordination give us a reason to be humble and careful in our assessments of where our participation is required, but not a reason to accept that we be duty bound to undertake innumerable actions that add no value. This is especially true because public goods are rarely one-shot deals. We receive regular feedback as to whether enough people are going on patrol or using solar panels.

Finally, this do-as-I-do approach overlooks an important worry for impartiality: the fact that persons are routinely not similarly situated. It is more costly for a single mother working two jobs to get to the polls than a tenured professor on sabbatical. It seems fundamentally unfair to ask they do the same task in anticipation of the same benefit when the burdens involved differ so dramatically. One person might reasonably balk at being asked to take on an unequal cost. Now, proponents might say that schemes with this feature fail the morality standard and thus do not activate concerns for fairness. Still, this would in practice apply to almost any realistic large-scale cooperative scheme. Such practices are slow-moving and often inattentive to individual circumstances in a way that makes it unlikely they will ever, in themselves, fully succeed at laying out rules that divide work in a genuinely equitable fashion. It is thus reasonable to conclude that people might share a preference for taking on a fair share of the labor of working to others' good, without being willing to undertake precisely the same acts as others, or bow to the dictates of the scheme in which they have participated.

Although these objections fail, they do reflect an important way in which mutual exchange proves discordant with our intuitions. Earlier, we treated Park and Scientists as clear instances of wrongful free-riding. Indeed, our central task was explaining what distinguished these cases from inappropriate demands like Snow. That is precisely what the FRP was intended to do. But our revised approach classifies both as predatory demands. Neither the participants in the watch nor the scientists have the right to specify the form in which their efforts are repaid. Both behave no better than the elves when they require the townsfolk to pay up, Miguel to show up.

There is a sense in which I think that this is correct. None of these benefactors has a right to specify the way beneficiaries' debts are satisfied. Park, Scientists, and Snow thus share the same moral mistake. Nonetheless, I think more can be said to explain our sense that the former cases generate concerns for fairness absent in the latter. I will say more to reconstruct Park in Section IV. For now, let us focus primarily on Scientists. Understanding how their claims differ from the elves' pushes us to further refine the FRP.

Earlier I suggested that each of us shares an interest in “others laboring on our behalf.” Read that way, the elves and the scientists have the same merit. Both work to others' benefit—in ways that we have reason to believe constitute a net gain to recipients. However, our interests are not quite so straightforward. To see this, we need to situate fair play in the broader moral landscape.

Freelance do-gooding is not the only way we seek to advance our projects or call on others to do the same. In many cases, institutions beyond others' kindness—the market, contract, consensual negotiation—better track our interests, are more effective and efficient means of benefit. They provide what we want at lower cost with greater control over our circumstances. Each of us thus shares an interest in the success of these institutions. Actions that undermine them are not to our benefit. Still, these institutions have their gaps and limits, in both ideal and non-ideal conditions. There are spaces where non-market actions do better at advancing what we care about, for any number of reasons. There is no company that notices my forgotten flower garden; markets do poorly at preventing pollution; in many places no affordable childcare services for the quite poor exist, nor reasonably priced green spaces. Fair play is suited to these interstitial gaps, to the spaces where other institutions and practices fail to best advance our interests. When people act to fill in these gaps, they provide a great benefit. Conversely, they threaten our well-being when they act to undermine institutions better suited to promoting the good, even when their immediate action technically provides a benefit.

This suggests a further revision to the FRP. Contributors and would-be free-riders are similarly situated insofar as they share the following attitudinal ordering:

Unlike shared preferences or mutual exchange, this approach successfully captures and explains our deeply held views about fairness in a way that makes sense of the felt difference between Snow and Scientists.

Consider the fact that discussions of fair play typically focus on public goods, benefits defined (among other things) by jointness in supply such that the provision of the good to one person entails furnishing it to all.22 The reciprocity account explains this emphasis. These goods are poorly suited to consent- or market-based approaches. It is simply too hard to negotiate terms, communicate agreement, or limit benefits to those who assent. The same is true of cases like Garden. Because Mary does not know where you are traveling, she would have a difficult time seeking consent to water your wilting plants. Many ordinary actions have this flavor: the return of lost keys, the carrying of printed papers from the copying room, the casual exchange of favors between friends are all for different reasons relatively poorly suited to the precise pre-negotiation and consent of formal market or contractual exchanges.

By contrast, in Snow we confront (or so we are told) an otherwise ordinary commercial case from which the usual avenues of consent and negotiation have been deliberately removed. Trifan herself says of a similar case, that it is, “a straightforward commercial transaction … more appropriately governed by explicit consent to receiving and paying for a benefit.”23 The would-be shovelers could easily have knocked on the door and asked if Neda was willing to pay their price (as someone did to me this morning). If Neda cared enough, we have every reason to believe that commercial shoveling services are readily on offer. Consequently, the elves are best read as acting with the aim of getting a profit they might not be due in the efficient market system they would seek to prevent or disrupt, rather than as contributing to the well-being of others in a way that does not operate to upset otherwise beneficial practices. Consequently, their behavior does not satisfy the reciprocity approach. As Cullity writes, “a commercial system that recognized this sort of liability would be so cripplingly inefficient that it would impoverish us.”24

Scientists offers a more challenging case. The complication is not—as Trifan suggests—that the scientists share a moral obligation to provide clean water. Plenty of appropriately commercial transactions address issues of moral concern. The existence of a commercial pharmaceutical industry, for example, helps to protect the health of billions in good part because of the informational, efficiency, and incentive-generating advantages of a market system. Indeed, we could read the elves as sharing in a moral responsibility to clean the snow—I certainly take myself to have an ethical in addition to a legal responsibility to make my sidewalk safe for passersby.

Rather, what matters are the details Trifan inserts in the case. The scientists are “passing through,” not a permanent fixture in town. They implement the fix “overnight.” And, of course, they are scientists, not professional plumbers. We are given the impression of a one-off incident that required rare specialized expertise possessed by a group of people who had to act with little time, on an important issue, in conditions in which they could not realistically ask consent, and who do not seek to gain from the exercise; not a roving band of entrepreneurs attempting to set up a hit-and-run business model that subverts normal bid-and-contract procedures to acquire a profit they could not guarantee in an ordinary commercial transaction. The more this story rings true, the more the case seems to trigger genuine fair-play concerns, the less so, the more it seems a predatory demand—just as the reciprocity approach predicts.

The reciprocity approach thus achieves what we set out to do. It distinguishes predatory demands and actions that trigger fair play in a way that explains the distinction and grounds it in a broader systematic account of fairness. In doing so, however, the approach points to the need to quite radically revise our understanding of the resulting duty.

Our account challenges both these features. Let's begin with the cooperative scheme requirement. This attribute of fair play is oft-stated, but little defended. Instead, it is repeated like a mantra—though one that is (tellingly) violated in many famous examples, from Nozick's worry about book-pushing friends to Cullity's concern about shoe-repairing elves.26

The reciprocity approach rejects this requirement. Individuals do not need to receive benefits that result from collective schemes for the production of particular goods to trigger fairness concerns. Indeed, they need not even share an interest in the same goods. It is enough that one or more people do the right kind of work to others' profit. There is no moral distinction between our generous gardener Mary and the collection of neighbors who patrol Miguel's local park. Both reflect the same duty of reciprocity, an obligation to repay the burdensome labor others do to your benefit. Concerns for fairness thus arise equally in ordinary interpersonal exchanges and collective schemes.

If anything, what the reciprocity approach tells us about the rules condition is even more revolutionary. It is typically taken to be a central feature of fair play that it requires beneficiaries to abide by the rules of the practice from which they have benefited. This purportedly fundamental aspect of the duty has been taken to explain why citizens are obliged to vote, obey the law, pay taxes, and so on. But the reciprocity account rejects this requirement as contravening fairness. For benefactors to take themselves to have the right to dictate the way in which beneficiaries return their efforts, while reserving for themselves the right to provide goods at their own discretion, violates impartiality. While beneficiaries are duty-bound to return the good that they have received to their benefactor(s), the precise form in which they do so is up to them.

This suggests a very different picture of our civic obligations, one where tax-avoiding non-voters may escape moral critique. Nonetheless, I will argue that it is not as radical as it might seem. What follows is less a sweeping revision of how we should behave than a profound rethinking of the reasons that guide our behavior. While the classic account holds that citizens must obey the law or vote, because fairness by nature requires that they abide by the rules of the practice from which they have benefited, the reciprocity approach is more practical. It holds that citizens must often behave in these ways, because doing so is in many cases the only workable way to provide a benefit to all those to whom a debt is owed.

Remember that while the reciprocity approach does not require that beneficiaries obey the dictates of their benefactors, it does demand that they work to advance benefactors' interests. In small-scale cases, the options for doing so are near endless: I know that my colleague is worried about getting her car started in time to get her kid to school, wants to become a better runner, needs comments on a paper. But in large-scale cases such efforts come up against two problems: reach and diversity. As a citizen, I owe the millions who have paid taxes and showed up at the polls to my benefit. These people are not only numerous—they are very far apart, and they have very different interests and needs. Sam loves brownies, Jim is gluten-intolerant. Mary wants her house repainted, Jenn lives in a yurt. Lauren's dog requires walking, Fred hates animals and wishes to avoid any contact with them. As one person, it is nearly impossible for me to reliably know—much less seek to satisfy—these needs.

There is, however, one set of goods that I know is valued by every person who has worked to my benefit—the very goods they themselves worked to advance. Whatever their other differences, Sam, Jim, Mary, Jenn, Lauren, Fred, and millions of others see benefit in public safety, health, environmental cleanliness, and the other goods that their compliance with the law or exertions at the ballot box are intended to promote.27 Efforts to advance these goods thus constitute a benefit to each person whose work to promote those very same good has put me in debt.

In itself, this does not explain why citizens have special reason to vote or pay taxes. After all, there are lots of things you might do to advance the relevant goods. Fixing the pothole in front of your house promotes transportation; donating to a local free clinic could improve public health. However, these responses fail to account for both the breadth and the complexity of the relevant goods. Many good-promoting works have a localized effect. Your pothole repair may benefit Lauren, who lives on your block, but will do nothing at all for Jim who lives on the other side of town and never drives your way. Other actions provide value only if they align properly with fellow citizens' efforts. Your brilliant education plan is of little value if nobody implements it.

Beneficiaries of large-scale civic goods can thus see themselves as repaying their benefactors only insofar as they act as part of a joint effort to provide the relevant goods to the entire population to whom they owe a debt. In small-scale cases, such collective action is easy to achieve. You and I can build a bookshelf with a brief chat about parts, or tango by keeping an eye on how the other moves. But such structure is far more challenging to achieve in large-scale cases. It is difficult to imagine sustaining an effective system of public safety or health without structured efforts at harmonization; the tens of thousands of actions that play a part are unlikely to align absent formal coordination. To commit to the success of these goods is thus to aim at advancing an organized plan for their achievement.

And here we can see the value of practice rules. The dictates of the applicable cooperative practice just are the central features of the shared plan. That people pay these taxes or follow these laws are the pathways by which we have chosen to together produce the relevant goods. That we might have arranged ourselves so as to generate these goods through other means does not detract from the fact that this is our plan. Consequently, those who do not abide by the rules cannot see themselves as advancing the arrangement and thus cannot take themselves to benefit their benefactors as the reciprocity account requires.

This gives each of us good reason to obey the rules of large-scale practices from which we benefit. In turn—to return to our earlier discussion—this explains why cases like Park feel different from Snow. It isn't just that the elves are providing the wrong kind of benefit. It also matters that Neda has a greater range of options easily available by which to return the elves' favor. By contrast, Miguel will find it challenging to benefit all the members of his neighborhood watch without taking his turn on patrol. Because his individual efforts to bake cakes or light the sidewalk will almost certainly lack sufficient breadth of interest, reach or alignment, he is likely to find that joining in is the only way that he can pay his debt.

Still, it is important that Miguel's reasons are pragmatic, not a fundamental feature of fair play. It follows that there can be exceptions. If Miguel manages to knit a warm sweater for every winter walker or fix the dangerous cracks on the park trails, he can genuinely say that he has repaid his debts. His helpful neighbors cannot complain that he gave himself an unjustified exception if he fails to show up, flashlight at the ready. This matters, because the rule of complex practices like those from which we benefit as citizens often have limitations, inadequacies, or incomplete features that open opportunities for us to pay our debts without participating as the practice demands.

Lawmakers, for example, often lack the knowledge, skill set, or attention span to provide an adequate blueprint for the production of goods like health or public safety.28 The successful production of these goods thus routinely depends on others undertaking legally discretionary actions to fill in the gaps—not taking advantage of legally available loopholes, taking lower-paid jobs to promote effective public policy, and so on. Those who do such work advance the scheme, even if they fail to otherwise participate by showing up for jury duty or taking a turn at the ballot box. The reciprocity approach thus demands a more precise and nuanced account of fair citizenship.

This account has many advantages. Most notably, it demonstrates greater and more parsimonious explanatory power. Though discussions of fair play focus on fairness, they have traditionally provided no systematic account of the nature of this value. The reciprocity approach does so, grounding our demands for fair play in a deeper concern for appropriate impartiality. In doing so, the approach provides a singular theory, one capable of speaking to both individual and collective exchanges, and of distinguishing in each instance between predatory demands and fairness-generating benefits. Unlike more recent attempts to draw such distinctions, the view can capture and explain what have long looked like conflicting intuitions about the nature of fairness and our duty to others, in a manner that begins to make clear the value of non-voluntarily acquired obligations.29

Both can be read as efforts to stave off the conclusion that we are subject to an endless array of demands from others' work on our behalf. The reciprocity account, opponents might worry, denies just these restraints, generating too weighty a moral obligation.

While fair-play advocates like Tosi and Dworkin succeed at limiting our obligations, they do so by drawing unexplained—and I think unjustifiable—boundaries. Why do we owe some people who provide us with non-requested benefits repayment for their work, but not others? No reason is provided. The reciprocity approach offers a more attractive response. There are no artificial limits. We do owe others for the benefits they provide, at least when they are consistent with our general good and come at a cost. But it does not follow that we are required to pay the price our benefactors demand or take up the same actions in turn. We are merely obliged to do something to their benefit, at our discretion, just as they did for us. That your life is made better by a street musician does not mean you must toss him a bill. But this is not because you owe him nothing. It is because you can pay your debt in any number of ways: Perhaps you support the arts, perhaps you lobby to allow busking in the subways, vote for politicians who want to expand music licensing, or join the musician's efforts to provide joy and beauty by contributing in your own way. All can satisfy your duty.

This answers Dworkin and Tosi's real concern: isn't the price of acknowledging that we owe others for the work they do our benefit too high? The cost, we can now see, is rarely extensive. We can pay our debts just as easily as we acquire them. My life is routinely made better by the work of others, in ways large or small. People help me salt the sidewalk, pick up their dog poop, cheer me on as I run a marathon, donate to the local food bank. In turn, I often pay them back almost without thinking: planting flowers on the local bike trail, lending out my snowblower, racing after a father whose child has let a mitten fall unnoticed to the ground, hanging cheerful holiday decorations.32 And, of course, in the event that the cost of repayment ever exceeds the value I gain, such actions cease to generate duties of return. The reciprocity approach thus manages to restrict the weight of our duties without drawing contrived and groundless boundaries.

Fair play, the claim suggests, does not concern itself with fairness between beneficiaries and benefactors, but instead consists in a fundamental obligation to sustain particular beneficial practices. The fact that the reciprocity account accurately captures our intuitions about fairness thus does not tell us what fair play requires.

We have already seen several problems with this reading. To begin with, it lacks anything in the way of deeper explanation or grounding. While the reciprocity account finds further justification for its claims—the parties act wrongly in making unjustified exceptions for themselves—this account simply stipulates that fair play is fundamentally concerned with the preservation of specific institutions (who says exchanges are meant to sustain such practices? And how does this meaning generate obligation?).

Perhaps just as tellingly, this reading is discordant with our intuitions. In many cases, we cannot make sense of our feelings about reciprocal exchange by understanding them as intended to sustain particular schemes rather than productive social life more broadly. Take the view that we ought to respond to helpful efforts like Mary's in Garden.34 This is a commonplace intuition: others give us rides, make us soup when we are sick, feed our pets, dog-sit. We ought, we think, to return their efforts—but not necessarily in kind. Instead, we should work to make their lives better.

Similarly, concerns about reciprocity typically persist even when exchanges cannot possibly sustain a particular advantageous relationship. I should pay my taxes even if I am moving out of town tomorrow; I should leave my hair-cutter a tip even if I intend to frequent a different salon in the future. Conversely, such obligations continue even when the preservation of a practice is guaranteed. The fact that a scholarship program from which I once received assistance has secured a massive donation that will ensure its survival does not assuage my duty to give back. Indeed, the idea that it would is confusing. After all, arguments from fair play are typically meant to explain why non-action is wrong, even when the existence of the relevant practice is secured. The reciprocity approach thus makes better sense of our intuitions.35

Finally, opponents might worry that the reciprocity approach elides important distinctions between the interpersonal and collective contexts. But they would then be on the hook for explaining just what, precisely these differences are. Surprisingly little is on offer; the existence and moral salience of this distinction is typically taken for granted. As we have seen, morally salient features are, of course, often present in the collective context—the scale and nature of large-scale schemes often make consent, promise, or contract a challenge: communication and negotiation are too difficult, public goods too challenging to limit to willing participants.

These issues, though, are merely pragmatic, not fundamental to fair play. Nor do they support a strict distinction. After all, versions of these traits can also be found in the interpersonal context. If your friend notices your cat is in need of care while you are traveling, she may not be able to contact you to ask permission. If your neighbor repairs the apartment building's squeaky front door, all residents will benefit. And, of course, some collectively produced goods avoid these concerns—public transit provides an opportunity for consent, a collectively constructed well constitutes a private good. These ways of drawing boundaries between types of obligations thus give us no reason to cling to the cooperative scheme requirement over a more nuanced approach.

Much about the reciprocity approach to fair play remains to be worked out. Are qualifying benefits defined by objective goodness, subjective goodness, or some combination of the two? What defines some effort as “equivalent labor?” capable of repaying others' efforts? Nonetheless, the approach offers a rich alternative to the classic account of fair play, one that manages to both better capture and better explain our intuitions about fairness. Unlike the traditional approach, or newer attempts at precision like those offered by Cullity and Trifan, the view grounds our concerns and provides the resources to differentiate fairness-generating benefits from predatory demands, in a way suited to provide guidance to the full array of relations we bear to the individuals and collectives who contribute to our good.

None relevant.

There are no potential conflicts of interest relevant to this article.

The author declares human ethics approval was not needed for this study.

查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
重新审视公正和公平竞争
即使我明天要搬离城镇,我也应该纳税;即使我打算以后经常去另一家沙龙,我也应该给我的理发师小费。相反,即使一种做法的保全得到保证,这种义务仍然存在。事实上,我曾经获得过资助的一个奖学金项目获得了大量捐款,这将确保它的生存,但这并不能减轻我的回报义务。事实上,这种想法令人困惑。毕竟,公平竞争的论点通常是为了解释为什么不采取行动是错误的,即使相关做法的存在是有保障的。因此,互惠方法可以更好地理解我们的直觉。35最后,反对者可能担心互惠方法会忽略人际和集体环境之间的重要区别。但他们将不得不解释这些差异到底是什么。令人惊讶的是,报价很少;这种区别的存在和道德重要性通常被认为是理所当然的。正如我们所看到的,道德上的显著特征当然经常出现在集体背景下——大规模计划的规模和性质往往使同意、承诺或合同成为一种挑战:沟通和谈判太困难,公共产品太具有挑战性,无法仅限于有意愿的参与者。然而,这些问题仅仅是务实的,而不是公平竞争的根本。他们也不支持严格的区分。毕竟,这些特质的版本也可以在人际关系中找到。如果你的朋友在你旅行时注意到你的猫需要照顾,她可能无法联系你请求许可。如果你的邻居修理公寓楼吱吱作响的前门,所有居民都会受益。当然,一些集体生产的商品也避免了这些担忧——公共交通提供了获得同意的机会,集体建造的井构成了私人商品。因此,这些划分义务类型界限的方式使我们没有理由坚持合作计划的要求,而不是采取更微妙的方法。公平竞争的互惠方式还有很多问题有待解决。合格利益是由客观善、主观善还是两者的结合来定义的?什么将一些努力定义为“同等劳动”?能够回报他人的努力?尽管如此,这种方法为公平竞争的经典描述提供了一个丰富的替代方案,它能够更好地捕捉和解释我们对公平的直觉。与传统方法或Cullity和Trifan提供的新的精确尝试不同,这种观点为我们的担忧奠定了基础,并提供了资源来区分产生公平的利益和掠夺性需求,以一种适合指导我们与为我们的利益做出贡献的个人和集体之间的各种关系的方式。无相关。本条不存在潜在的利益冲突。作者宣称这项研究不需要人类伦理的批准。 我认为这种对公正性的关注体现了交易公正性的一些重要内容。要求他人公平对待我们的要求具有重要的可比性。通过这种方式,它与我们得到我们想要的东西甚至其他优点的要求不同。我们担心的是,我们会受到不同的对待,从而对我们不利。当然,并不是所有的差异治疗都不符合这个标准。如果我参加儿童比赛,即使我跑得比我蹒跚学步的对手快,我也不会获得奖牌。问题是,什么能将一种行为定性为实例化了一种不合理的特权?当这些特征出现时,一个不合理地避免贡献的人就不受她将适用于他人的规则的约束。但那些在缺乏这些渴望的情况下这样做的人并没有表现出这样的偏见:他们认为每个人都有充分的理由以同样的方式行事。Cullity认为,这种说法成功地实现了我们的目标:它区分了公平竞争适用的案件和不适用的案件,使我们能够识别错误的要求。他认为,像斯诺这样的情况违反了第三个要求。让Neda不得不支付精灵的费用,“意味着让每个人都有责任支付所有值得他们付出的主动福利。”他认为,这将是破坏性的低效。9问题是这样的。Park可以被解读为与Snow有着相同的形式:一群人主动提供福利,并要求合理的付款(在前者中,Miguel加入巡逻队;在后者中,Neda支付账单)。如果在后一种情况下这种行为违反了泛化要求,为什么在前一种情况中不呢?就像邻里守望一样,科学家们提供了一种良好的(增强的健康),改善了每个人的生活。通过这种方式构建,该案例通过了测试。为这一点和未来任何类似的努力做出贡献都会让每个人都过得更好。与此同时,科学家们所做的正是精灵们正在做的事情——提供免下车福利,并希望获得报酬。据Cullity说,这种行为不合格。因此,该说明未能提供结论性指导:为了概括的目的,我们应该将哪些特征视为突出特征?她认为,只要——而且只有——他们的偏好是有序的,他们都有这种态度:Trifan认为这种观点是为了提供我们所寻求的清晰度。在这篇文章中,如果米格尔和镇上的人拒绝付款,他们的行为都是错误的。每个人都与他们的捐助者分享了正确的观点:希望公园和供水安全,而不必为这一过程做出贡献(就科学家而言,因为——或者Trifan认为——他们有责任保持消费者的健康)。相比之下,精灵们对他们提供的利益不感兴趣(或者我们可以推测)。他们想要的不是铲人行道,而是要付钱。13因此,内达不付账没有违反公正原则。这起案件违反了Trifan所理解的FRP。Mary不希望你给她没有的植物浇水。根据共享偏好账户,因此您没有义务回报她的努力。但这似乎很愚蠢:如果玛丽希望你用坐猫猫、饼干、乘车去机场来回报你,那似乎就没有什么掠夺性的东西。事实上,这里的利害关系恰恰呼应了公平竞争学者的抱怨:如果你对玛丽没有任何好处,你就会享受不公平的利润。你过得更好,她过得更糟,因为她为你做了有益的工作。如果玛丽(例如)让你在她不在的时候去看她的猫,那么“我什么都不欠你,因为你没有花园”的声明听起来几乎是奇怪的无礼。如果Cullity的解释过于模糊,那么Trifan的解释就显得过于狭隘,剔除了似乎产生真正公平考虑的案例。然而,有一种方法可以修正这种观点,从而避免这种错误。我们可以通过重塑FRP来捕捉玛丽的努力值得回报的感觉。根据公式,该方法假设,只有当人们对特定商品——浇水的花园、洗过的汽车——有共同兴趣时,他们的处境才会相似。这极大地限制了公平竞争适用的一系列案例。我们的口味和目标各不相同。你喜欢黑巧克力;我讨厌它。你关心咏叹调;我只喜欢挪威的死亡金属。但我们不必把自己看作是在这样不同的领域中运作。尽管我们对尊巴课程或DIY家居装修有不同的看法,但我们有一些共同点——对一个人们提供丰富我们生活的福利的世界有着更广泛的共同关注。当你想方设法把我丢失的钱包还回来时,我的生活会变得更好;当我把打印纸重新装满或把饼干放在休息室时,你的生活会更好。我们每个人都同样希望别人不要利用我们自己的这种努力。 劳伦的狗需要散步,弗雷德讨厌动物,希望避免与它们接触。作为一个人,我几乎不可能可靠地知道——更不用说寻求满足——这些需求了。然而,我知道有一套商品是每个为我工作过的人都看重的——正是他们自己努力推销的商品。无论他们的其他差异如何,Sam、Jim、Mary、Jenn、Lauren、Fred和数百万其他人都看到了公共安全、健康、环境清洁方面的好处,以及他们遵守法律或在投票箱中努力推广的其他商品。27因此,推广这些商品的努力对每个人来说都是一种好处,因为他们为推广这些商品所做的工作让我负债累累。这本身并不能解释为什么公民有特殊的理由投票或纳税。毕竟,你可以做很多事情来预付相关商品。修复你家门前的坑洞可以促进交通;向当地的免费诊所捐款可以改善公众健康。然而,这些答复没有考虑到相关货物的广度和复杂性。许多好的宣传作品都具有本地化效果。你的坑洞修复可能会让住在你街区的劳伦受益,但对住在城市另一边、从不开车的吉姆毫无帮助。其他行动只有在与其他公民的努力保持适当一致的情况下才有价值。如果没有人实施,你出色的教育计划就没有什么价值。因此,大规模公民产品的受益者只能认为自己在偿还捐助者的债务,只要他们共同努力向他们欠下债务的全体人民提供相关产品。在小规模的情况下,这种集体行动很容易实现。你和我可以建立一个书架,简单地聊一聊零件,或者通过关注对方的动作来跳探戈。但在大规模案例中,要实现这样的结构要困难得多。如果不进行有组织的协调努力,很难想象维持一个有效的公共安全或卫生系统;在没有正式协调的情况下,数万起作用的行动不太可能协调一致。因此,致力于这些商品的成功就是为了推进一个有组织的计划来实现它们。在这里我们可以看到实践规则的价值。适用的合作实践的规定正是共享计划的核心特征。人们缴纳这些税或遵守这些法律是我们选择共同生产相关商品的途径。我们可能已经安排好通过其他方式生产这些商品,但这并没有削弱我们的计划。因此,那些不遵守规则的人不能认为自己在推动这一安排,因此不能像互惠账户所要求的那样,认为自己有利于捐助者。这给了我们每个人遵守大规模实践规则的充分理由,我们从中受益。反过来——回到我们之前的讨论——这解释了为什么像Park这样的案例感觉与Snow不同。不仅仅是精灵提供了错误的福利。同样重要的是,内达有更多的选择,可以很容易地回报精灵的青睐。相比之下,Miguel会发现,在不轮流巡逻的情况下,让他所在社区的所有成员都受益是一项挑战。因为他个人烤蛋糕或照亮人行道的努力几乎肯定会缺乏足够的兴趣、影响力或一致性,他可能会发现加入是他偿还债务的唯一途径。尽管如此,重要的是米格尔的理由是务实的,而不是公平竞争的基本特征。由此可见,也有例外。如果Miguel能为每一个冬天的步行者织一件保暖的毛衣,或者修复公园小径上危险的裂缝,他可以真诚地说他已经偿还了债务。他乐于助人的邻居不会抱怨,如果他不出现,随时准备用手电筒,他会给自己一个不合理的例外。这一点很重要,因为像我们作为公民从中受益的复杂实践规则往往具有局限性、不足之处或不完整的特征,为我们提供了在不按实践要求参与的情况下偿还债务的机会。例如,立法者往往缺乏知识、技能或注意力,无法为健康或公共安全等商品的生产提供足够的蓝图。28因此,这些商品的成功生产通常取决于其他人采取法律上自由裁量的行动来填补空白——而不是利用法律上可用的漏洞,从事低薪工作以促进有效的公共政策等等。从事这些工作的人推动了这项计划,即使他们没有以其他方式参与陪审团职责或投票。 因此,互惠方法要求对公平公民身份有更精确、更细致的描述。这个账户有很多优点。最值得注意的是,它展示了更大、更节俭的解释力。尽管关于公平竞争的讨论侧重于公平,但传统上没有系统地说明这种价值观的性质。互惠的做法做到了这一点,使我们对公平竞争的要求更加关注适当的公正性。在这样做的过程中,这种方法提供了一种独特的理论,能够对个人和集体的交流进行阐述,并在每种情况下区分掠夺性需求和公平产生的利益。与最近试图做出这种区分不同,这种观点可以捕捉并解释长期以来关于公平的本质和我们对他人的责任的相互矛盾的直觉,以一种开始表明非自愿获得的义务的价值的方式。29这可以被解读为努力避免得出这样的结论,即我们受到他人代表我们工作的无尽要求的影响。反对者可能会担心,互惠账户否认了这些限制,产生了过于沉重的道德义务。虽然托西和德沃金这样的公平竞争倡导者成功地限制了我们的义务,但他们这样做是通过划定无法解释的——我认为是不合理的——界限。为什么我们欠一些为我们提供非要求福利的人工作补偿,而不欠其他人?没有提供任何理由。互惠方式提供了更具吸引力的回应。没有人为的限制。我们确实欠别人他们提供的好处,至少当这些好处与我们的总体利益一致并且是有代价的时候。但这并不意味着我们必须付出捐助者要求的代价,或者反过来采取同样的行动。我们只是有义务做一些有利于他们的事情,就像他们为我们做的那样。一个街头音乐家让你的生活变得更好,并不意味着你必须向他扔账单。但这并不是因为你什么都不欠他。这是因为你可以通过多种方式偿还债务:也许你支持艺术,也许你游说允许在地铁里街头表演,投票给希望扩大音乐许可的政客,或者加入音乐家的行列,通过自己的方式贡献自己的力量来提供欢乐和美丽。一切都能满足你的职责。这回答了德沃金和托西真正关心的问题:承认我们欠别人的工作的代价不是太高了吗?我们现在可以看到,成本很少是巨大的。我们可以像获得债务一样轻松地偿还债务。我的生活经常因为别人的工作而变得更好,无论大小。人们帮我在人行道上撒盐,捡他们的狗粪,在我跑马拉松时为我加油,向当地的食品银行捐款。反过来,我经常不假思索地还钱:在当地的自行车道上种花,借出我的吹雪机,追着一个孩子把手套掉在地上的父亲比赛,挂上欢快的节日装饰。32当然,如果还款成本超过了我获得的价值,这种行为就不再产生回报义务。因此,互惠办法设法限制了我们的职责,而没有人为和毫无根据的界限。该主张表明,公平竞争并不涉及受益人和捐助者之间的公平,而是包括维持特定有益做法的基本义务。互惠账户准确地捕捉了我们对公平的直觉,这一事实并不能告诉我们公平竞争需要什么。我们已经看到了这个阅读的几个问题。首先,它缺乏任何更深层次的解释或基础。虽然互惠账户为其主张找到了进一步的理由——各方为自己做出不合理的例外是错误的——但该账户只是简单地规定,公平竞争从根本上与维护特定机构有关(谁说交易所是为了维持这种做法?这一含义如何产生义务?),这种解读与我们的直觉不一致。在许多情况下,我们无法理解我们对互惠交换的感受,因为我们将其理解为旨在维持特定的计划,而不是更广泛的生产性社会生活。认为我们应该对像《花园里的玛丽》这样的有益努力做出回应。34这是一种常见的直觉:别人载我们上车,在我们生病时给我们做汤,喂我们的宠物,坐狗。我们认为,我们应该回报他们的努力,但不一定是实物。相反,我们应该努力让他们的生活变得更好。同样,即使交换不可能维持一种特殊的有利关系,对互惠的担忧通常也会持续存在。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
4.10
自引率
5.60%
发文量
17
期刊介绍: The Journal of Political Philosophy is an international journal devoted to the study of theoretical issues arising out of moral, legal and political life. It welcomes, and hopes to foster, work cutting across a variety of disciplinary concerns, among them philosophy, sociology, history, economics and political science. The journal encourages new approaches, including (but not limited to): feminism; environmentalism; critical theory, post-modernism and analytical Marxism; social and public choice theory; law and economics, critical legal studies and critical race studies; and game theoretic, socio-biological and anthropological approaches to politics. It also welcomes work in the history of political thought which builds to a larger philosophical point and work in the philosophy of the social sciences and applied ethics with broader political implications. Featuring a distinguished editorial board from major centres of thought from around the globe, the journal draws equally upon the work of non-philosophers and philosophers and provides a forum of debate between disparate factions who usually keep to their own separate journals.
期刊最新文献
Evaluating International Agreements: The Voluntarist Reply and Its Limits Issue Information The Journal of Political Philosophy Index, Volume 31 (2023) The challenge of policing minorities in a liberal society Noncompliance and the Demands of Public Reason
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1