Performance-Enhancing Technologies and the Values of Athletic Competition

D. Wasserman
{"title":"Performance-Enhancing Technologies and the Values of Athletic Competition","authors":"D. Wasserman","doi":"10.13021/G8PPPQ.282008.116","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"For decades, the American criminal justice system has been engaged in a \"war on drugs\" that critics say cannot be won. The enthusiasm for that war has been flagging for some time; a 1989 issue of the Quarterly (then called QQ) featured an article by Claudia Mills titled \"The War on Drugs: Is it Time to Surrender?\" In amateur and professional sports, however, the war on performance-enhancing drugs has been steadily escalating in recent years. Major doping scandals have roiled several sports, and drug testing has become ever more stringent. Yet at the time of the 2008 Beijing Olympics, where concerns about doping were pervasive, a few voices called for surrender. Some commentators argued that the war on doping was futile, since the technological sophistication of the dopers would always outstrip, if only for a few critical weeks or months, the capacity to detect their work. Others, however, argued that even if the war could be won, it wouldn't be worth fighting. As John Tierney wrote in the New York Times, \"We all know the body can be improved. We all know Olympic athletes have the highest-functioning bodies in the world. They can call themselves natural, just as they used to call themselves amateur, but at some point that claim may seem the most unnatural thing of all.\" To bolster his case, Tierney noted that the fans themselves include people \"with laser-corrected eyes, chemically whitened teeth and surgically enhanced anatomies. Not to mention the pharmacopeia coursing through our veins.\" These are still minority opinions. Just a year before the Olympics began, Barry Bonds broke Hank Aaron's lifetime home run record to a chorus of denunciation from sports pundits for his reported steroid use. Several months later, that chorus grew even more strident with the release of the Mitchell Report on doping in professional baseball, which gave Bonds lots of company and his detractors a surfeit of new targets. Along with cycling, the subject of frequent scandals involving widespread steroid use, baseball has now submitted itself to an intensive regime of drug testing and monitoring. But even in the unlikely event that anti-doping measures are successful in their narrow objective of deterring illegal drug use, they are ill-equipped to deal with a wider range of biotechnological interventions, which may bring far more significant changes in the performance capabilities of athletes. Unlike steroids, whose possession is illegal and whose use is widely regarded as unhealthy, these new technologies, genetic modification in particular, may at some point become legal and safe. Also unlike steroids, these technologies won't all be intended to confer a competitive advantage. Some, like the prosthetic limbs of runner Oscar Pistorius, will be designed to restore function lost to disease or disability; others, especially genetic modifications, will be intended for more general enhancement purposes. And in some cases, such as germline genetic engineering, the interventions will be undertaken not by the athletes themselves, but by their parents. To ban such technologies would be to ban whole classes of athletes, including some who would be incapable of compliance and others who would not be responsible for their enhancements. Moreover, a ban on biotechnological enhancement would be hard to justify or maintain without a ban on other technological enhancements, like the performance-boosting swimsuits that predominated at the Beijing Olympics, and whose cost is bankrupting many small high school and college teams. The attempt to distinguish forbidden from permitted modifications on the basis of their external or internal location, or their natural or artificial character, has proven a particularly futile exercise in casuistry. Rather than criticize recent efforts to make such distinctions, I will just observe that the continuing uncertainty about the grounds for distinguishing forbidden and permitted modifications is likely to undermine the moral authority and practical efficacy of any regulatory regime. …","PeriodicalId":82464,"journal":{"name":"Report from the Institute for Philosophy & Public Policy","volume":"28 1","pages":"22-27"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2008-06-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"2","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Report from the Institute for Philosophy & Public Policy","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.13021/G8PPPQ.282008.116","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2

Abstract

For decades, the American criminal justice system has been engaged in a "war on drugs" that critics say cannot be won. The enthusiasm for that war has been flagging for some time; a 1989 issue of the Quarterly (then called QQ) featured an article by Claudia Mills titled "The War on Drugs: Is it Time to Surrender?" In amateur and professional sports, however, the war on performance-enhancing drugs has been steadily escalating in recent years. Major doping scandals have roiled several sports, and drug testing has become ever more stringent. Yet at the time of the 2008 Beijing Olympics, where concerns about doping were pervasive, a few voices called for surrender. Some commentators argued that the war on doping was futile, since the technological sophistication of the dopers would always outstrip, if only for a few critical weeks or months, the capacity to detect their work. Others, however, argued that even if the war could be won, it wouldn't be worth fighting. As John Tierney wrote in the New York Times, "We all know the body can be improved. We all know Olympic athletes have the highest-functioning bodies in the world. They can call themselves natural, just as they used to call themselves amateur, but at some point that claim may seem the most unnatural thing of all." To bolster his case, Tierney noted that the fans themselves include people "with laser-corrected eyes, chemically whitened teeth and surgically enhanced anatomies. Not to mention the pharmacopeia coursing through our veins." These are still minority opinions. Just a year before the Olympics began, Barry Bonds broke Hank Aaron's lifetime home run record to a chorus of denunciation from sports pundits for his reported steroid use. Several months later, that chorus grew even more strident with the release of the Mitchell Report on doping in professional baseball, which gave Bonds lots of company and his detractors a surfeit of new targets. Along with cycling, the subject of frequent scandals involving widespread steroid use, baseball has now submitted itself to an intensive regime of drug testing and monitoring. But even in the unlikely event that anti-doping measures are successful in their narrow objective of deterring illegal drug use, they are ill-equipped to deal with a wider range of biotechnological interventions, which may bring far more significant changes in the performance capabilities of athletes. Unlike steroids, whose possession is illegal and whose use is widely regarded as unhealthy, these new technologies, genetic modification in particular, may at some point become legal and safe. Also unlike steroids, these technologies won't all be intended to confer a competitive advantage. Some, like the prosthetic limbs of runner Oscar Pistorius, will be designed to restore function lost to disease or disability; others, especially genetic modifications, will be intended for more general enhancement purposes. And in some cases, such as germline genetic engineering, the interventions will be undertaken not by the athletes themselves, but by their parents. To ban such technologies would be to ban whole classes of athletes, including some who would be incapable of compliance and others who would not be responsible for their enhancements. Moreover, a ban on biotechnological enhancement would be hard to justify or maintain without a ban on other technological enhancements, like the performance-boosting swimsuits that predominated at the Beijing Olympics, and whose cost is bankrupting many small high school and college teams. The attempt to distinguish forbidden from permitted modifications on the basis of their external or internal location, or their natural or artificial character, has proven a particularly futile exercise in casuistry. Rather than criticize recent efforts to make such distinctions, I will just observe that the continuing uncertainty about the grounds for distinguishing forbidden and permitted modifications is likely to undermine the moral authority and practical efficacy of any regulatory regime. …
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
提高成绩的技术和体育竞赛的价值
几十年来,美国刑事司法系统一直在进行一场“毒品战争”,批评人士称这场战争不可能获胜。一段时间以来,人们对这场战争的热情一直在减弱;1989年的《季刊》(当时还叫《QQ》)刊登了克劳迪娅·米尔斯的一篇文章,题为《禁毒战争:是投降的时候了吗?》然而,在业余和职业体育运动中,近年来,针对提高成绩药物的战争一直在稳步升级。重大的兴奋剂丑闻已经搅乱了几项运动,药物检测也变得越来越严格。然而,在2008年北京奥运会期间,对兴奋剂的担忧普遍存在,一些声音呼吁投降。一些评论人士认为,反兴奋剂战争是徒劳的,因为服用兴奋剂者的技术水平总是会超过检测他们行为的能力,哪怕只是在关键的几周或几个月里。然而,另一些人则认为,即使能打赢这场战争,也不值得打。正如约翰·蒂尔尼在《纽约时报》上所写的,“我们都知道身体是可以改善的。我们都知道奥运会运动员的身体是世界上功能最好的。他们可以称自己为自然爱好者,就像他们过去称自己为业余爱好者一样,但在某种程度上,这种说法似乎是最不自然的。”为了支持他的观点,蒂尔尼指出,粉丝本身包括那些“用激光矫正眼睛、化学美白牙齿和通过手术增强解剖结构的人”。更不用说我们血管里流淌的药典了。”这些仍然是少数人的意见。就在奥运会开幕前一年,巴里·邦兹打破了汉克·亚伦的本垒打纪录,引起了体育权威人士对他使用类固醇的一致谴责。几个月后,关于职业棒球运动员服用兴奋剂的米切尔报告(Mitchell Report)发布后,这种合唱变得更加尖锐,这给邦兹带来了许多同伴,也给他的批评者提供了过多的新目标。与自行车运动一样,棒球运动现在也接受了严格的药物检测和监控。自行车运动经常出现涉及广泛使用类固醇的丑闻。但是,即使反兴奋剂措施在阻止非法药物使用的狭隘目标上取得了成功(这种可能性不大),它们也无法应对更广泛的生物技术干预措施,而这些干预措施可能会给运动员的表现能力带来更大的变化。类固醇的持有是非法的,其使用被广泛认为是不健康的,而这些新技术,特别是基因改造技术,可能在某一时刻变得合法和安全。与类固醇不同的是,这些技术并不都是为了获得竞争优势。有些假肢,比如跑步运动员奥斯卡·皮斯托瑞斯(Oscar Pistorius)的假肢,将用于恢复因疾病或残疾而丧失的功能;其他的,尤其是基因改造,将用于更普遍的增强目的。在某些情况下,比如生殖系基因工程,干预将不是由运动员自己进行,而是由他们的父母进行。禁止这种技术将会禁止整个运动员阶层,包括一些无法遵守规定的运动员和其他不需要对他们的增强负责的运动员。此外,如果不禁止其他技术增强,禁止生物技术增强将很难站得住或维持下去,比如在北京奥运会上占主导地位的提高成绩的泳装,其成本使许多小型高中和大学运动队破产。试图根据其外部或内部位置,或其自然或人为特征来区分禁止和允许的修改,已被证明是诡辩中特别徒劳的练习。与其批评最近做出的区分,我只想指出,区分被禁止和被允许的修改的依据的持续不确定性,可能会破坏任何监管制度的道德权威和实际效力。…
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
期刊最新文献
Objectivity and Subjectivity in Theories of Well-Being Political Leadership and the Social Value of Privacy Some Scalar Issues in Climate Ethics Defining Scientific Integrity The Role of Non-Governmental Organizations in the Repatriation of Refugees
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1