{"title":"The Poverty of Economic Reasoning about Climate Change","authors":"M. Sagoff","doi":"10.13021/G8PPPQ.302010.89","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"A New Yorker cartoon illustrates the intergenerational aspect of climate change. It shows an Eskimo mother, father, and young child as they wave a tearful farewell to an old man, presumably a grandparent, whom they have placed on an ice floe. The family itself stands on a floating piece of ice. Which generation is responsible for the plight of which? I want to argue that the intergenerational aspect of climate change makes economic reasoning about it more problematic than one might think. Economic analysis depends on the idea of trade or exchange. It is hard to see, therefore, how it applies to our relations to people in the further future. We cannot bargain with them or they with us. Since they do not yet exist, they cannot have property rights. If ability to pay is a prerequisite of willingness to pay (WTP), moreover, then future generations cannot be willing--because they are not able--to pay us anything. We have exhausted all possible \"benefits of trade\" with them. I shall argue that the passivity of future generations--their inability to exercise market or political power--makes economic analysis irrelevant not just to justifying the goals of climate policy but also to designing instruments to achieve those goals. Economists often recommend that an international authority \"cap\" global greenhouse gas (GHG) emissions but allow firms to trade \"allowances\" under that cap. I shall argue that such a regime cannot succeed because generations in the further future, who are its principal beneficiaries, are in no position to defend it. Trading in GHG \"allowances,\" as I shall argue, is more likely to reflect beliefs about the likelihood of enforcement--bets placed on election returns, for example--than to reveal the marginal cost of \"sustainable\" production or \"clean\" energy technology. [ILLUSTRATION OMITTED] A perfectly efficient or competitive market cannot respond to the need of future generations for a stable climate because future generations play no role as market actors. An efficient policy therefore cannot be a sustainable policy. This is an argument against efficiency, not against sustainability. That economic theory fails in this way suggests we must rely on other reasons and rationales to justify a response to the threat of climate change. Climate Change Is Not a Collective Action Problem According to Paul G. Harris, \"Climate change is a collective action problem par excellence.\" One can see the appeal of this analysis. In 1965, Mancur Olson in The Logic of Collective Action showed that when each individual acts on self-interest, for example, to \"free-ride\" on the more socially motivated action of others, public goods will not be produced. Olson defines a \"group\" as \"a number of individuals with a common interest.\" Olson wrote, \"Unless the number of individuals in a group is quite small, or unless there is coercion or some other special device to make individuals act in their common interest, rational, self-interested individuals will not act to achieve their common or group interests.\" A little reflection, however, suggests that the \"tragedy of the commons\" or the analysis of a collective action problem does not fit the challenge of climate change. In the typical collective action problem, such as managing an open-access commons or preventing defections in a \"prisoner's dilemma\" game, each person will gain if all cooperate and all will lose if each acts in his or her own individual self-interest. In the case of climate change, however, one group, that is, people alive today and through the next generation, will make significant sacrifices, for example, by forgoing the consumption of inexpensive fossil fuels. A completely different group, whom one might call \"posterity,\" will benefit. The coercion necessary to solve a collective action problem is justified by the mutual reciprocity of advantage, that is, the idea that each person gains more by the restriction of the freedom of others than he or she loses by accepting that same restriction. …","PeriodicalId":82464,"journal":{"name":"Report from the Institute for Philosophy & Public Policy","volume":"22 1","pages":"8-15"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2010-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"2","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Report from the Institute for Philosophy & Public Policy","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.13021/G8PPPQ.302010.89","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Abstract
A New Yorker cartoon illustrates the intergenerational aspect of climate change. It shows an Eskimo mother, father, and young child as they wave a tearful farewell to an old man, presumably a grandparent, whom they have placed on an ice floe. The family itself stands on a floating piece of ice. Which generation is responsible for the plight of which? I want to argue that the intergenerational aspect of climate change makes economic reasoning about it more problematic than one might think. Economic analysis depends on the idea of trade or exchange. It is hard to see, therefore, how it applies to our relations to people in the further future. We cannot bargain with them or they with us. Since they do not yet exist, they cannot have property rights. If ability to pay is a prerequisite of willingness to pay (WTP), moreover, then future generations cannot be willing--because they are not able--to pay us anything. We have exhausted all possible "benefits of trade" with them. I shall argue that the passivity of future generations--their inability to exercise market or political power--makes economic analysis irrelevant not just to justifying the goals of climate policy but also to designing instruments to achieve those goals. Economists often recommend that an international authority "cap" global greenhouse gas (GHG) emissions but allow firms to trade "allowances" under that cap. I shall argue that such a regime cannot succeed because generations in the further future, who are its principal beneficiaries, are in no position to defend it. Trading in GHG "allowances," as I shall argue, is more likely to reflect beliefs about the likelihood of enforcement--bets placed on election returns, for example--than to reveal the marginal cost of "sustainable" production or "clean" energy technology. [ILLUSTRATION OMITTED] A perfectly efficient or competitive market cannot respond to the need of future generations for a stable climate because future generations play no role as market actors. An efficient policy therefore cannot be a sustainable policy. This is an argument against efficiency, not against sustainability. That economic theory fails in this way suggests we must rely on other reasons and rationales to justify a response to the threat of climate change. Climate Change Is Not a Collective Action Problem According to Paul G. Harris, "Climate change is a collective action problem par excellence." One can see the appeal of this analysis. In 1965, Mancur Olson in The Logic of Collective Action showed that when each individual acts on self-interest, for example, to "free-ride" on the more socially motivated action of others, public goods will not be produced. Olson defines a "group" as "a number of individuals with a common interest." Olson wrote, "Unless the number of individuals in a group is quite small, or unless there is coercion or some other special device to make individuals act in their common interest, rational, self-interested individuals will not act to achieve their common or group interests." A little reflection, however, suggests that the "tragedy of the commons" or the analysis of a collective action problem does not fit the challenge of climate change. In the typical collective action problem, such as managing an open-access commons or preventing defections in a "prisoner's dilemma" game, each person will gain if all cooperate and all will lose if each acts in his or her own individual self-interest. In the case of climate change, however, one group, that is, people alive today and through the next generation, will make significant sacrifices, for example, by forgoing the consumption of inexpensive fossil fuels. A completely different group, whom one might call "posterity," will benefit. The coercion necessary to solve a collective action problem is justified by the mutual reciprocity of advantage, that is, the idea that each person gains more by the restriction of the freedom of others than he or she loses by accepting that same restriction. …
《纽约客》的一幅漫画说明了气候变化的代际方面。画中,爱斯基摩人的母亲、父亲和年幼的孩子含泪向一位老人挥手告别,这位老人可能是他们的祖父母,他们把老人放在一块浮冰上。这家人站在一块浮冰上。哪一代人应该为哪一代人的困境负责?我想说的是,气候变化的代际性使得对它的经济推理比人们想象的更有问题。经济分析依赖于贸易或交换的概念。因此,我们很难看到,这将如何适用于未来的两国人民关系。我们不能和他们讨价还价,他们也不能和我们讨价还价。因为他们还不存在,他们不可能拥有产权。此外,如果支付能力是支付意愿(WTP)的先决条件,那么后代就不可能愿意——因为他们没有能力——支付给我们任何东西。我们已经用尽了所有可能的“贸易利益”。我认为,后代的被动性——他们无法行使市场或政治权力——使得经济分析不仅对证明气候政策目标的合理性无关紧要,而且对设计实现这些目标的工具也无关紧要。经济学家经常建议国际权威机构“限制”全球温室气体(GHG)排放,但允许企业在这一上限下进行“配额”交易。我认为,这种制度不可能成功,因为未来的几代人,作为其主要受益者,没有能力为其辩护。我将指出,温室气体“配额”交易更有可能反映出对执行可能性的信念——比如对选举结果的押注——而不是揭示“可持续”生产或“清洁”能源技术的边际成本。一个完全有效或竞争的市场不能满足子孙后代对稳定气候的需求,因为子孙后代不扮演市场参与者的角色。因此,有效的政策不可能是可持续的政策。这是一个反对效率的论点,而不是反对可持续性的论点。经济理论在这方面的失败表明,我们必须依靠其他理由和理由来证明应对气候变化威胁的合理性。根据Paul G. Harris的说法,“气候变化是一个集体行动的问题。”我们可以看到这种分析的吸引力。1965年,Mancur Olson在《集体行动的逻辑》(The Logic of Collective Action)中指出,当每个个体都按照自身利益行事时,例如,“搭便车”他人更具社会动机的行动,就不会产生公共产品。奥尔森将“团体”定义为“一群有共同兴趣的人”。奥尔森写道:“除非一个群体中的个人数量很少,或者除非有强制或其他特殊手段使个人按照他们的共同利益行事,理性的、自利的个人不会为实现他们的共同利益或群体利益而行动。”然而,稍加反思就会发现,“公地悲剧”或对集体行动问题的分析并不适合气候变化的挑战。在典型的集体行动问题中,例如在“囚徒困境”博弈中管理开放的公共资源或防止叛逃,如果所有人都合作,每个人都会受益;如果每个人都以自己的个人利益为目的,所有人都会失败。然而,在气候变化的情况下,有一个群体,即今天和下一代的人,将做出重大牺牲,例如,放弃消费廉价的化石燃料。一个完全不同的群体,我们可以称之为“后代”,将从中受益。解决集体行动问题所必需的强制被互惠利益所证明,也就是说,每个人通过限制他人的自由而获得的收益大于他或她接受同样的限制而失去的收益。…