{"title":"Well-being as a Primary Good: Towards Legitimate Well-being Policy","authors":"Sam Wren-Lewis","doi":"10.13021/G8PPPQ.312013.135","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"The use of well-being research in assessing and creating public policy is gaining popularity. The UK's Office of National Statistics has developed its National Well-being Index to do exactly that, and several other nations have followed suit. This sway in political will, however, can make the use of well-being research in public policy seem less controversial than it is. Much of the rhetoric around the move toward well-being measures in evaluating policy has centered either on the idea that well-being is what \"ultimately matters\" or that it is at least \"something we all care about.\" In this essay, I will argue that such claims are illegitimate from the perspective of political liberalism. The former kind of claim is illegitimate insofar as liberal societies should not base policy on comprehensive religious, moral, or philosophical doctrines that many reasonable citizens may not accept. The latter kind of claim is illegitimate insofar as some people care significantly more than others about well-being or the ingredients of well-being. Thus, the use of well-being research to evaluate public policy cannot be justified on either of these grounds. Does this mean that there are no justifiable grounds for well-being-based policy? Not necessarily. In this essay, I explore the possibility that the psychological aspects of well-being can be viewed as a \"primary good.\" That is, the preservation and promotion of well-being can be justified as instrumentally valuable for most people. Well-being is instrumentally valuable for most people regardless of their particular intrinsic values. In John Rawls's terms, well-being can be viewed as an all-purpose good that people are assumed to want whatever their plans. The reason for this is that the psychological aspects of well-being, the kinds of things subjective well-being research typically measures, tend to be cognitively and motivationally necessary for agency. Without being able to appreciate one's life emotionally and cognitively, one cannot sufficiently pursue one's own conception of the good. Thus, well-being tends to be necessary for leading a good life regardless of one's conception of in what a good life consists. Even if it is the case, however, that well-being can be viewed as a primary good in this way, it is not necessarily the case that the state should promote it as a matter of justice. The state should promote only primary goods that share certain important features. First, a given primary good must be distributable and objectively comparable if the state is to promote it in a just manner. In addition, the state must be in the best position to promote a given primary good. That is, the primary good must require institutional support: public policies related to its existence and continuation. Moreover, the primary good must be non-fungible. That is, it must not be commonly obtainable through substitutes--things other than the goods and services provided by the state. I will argue that the psychological aspects of well-being share each of these features. Thus, according to political liberalism, governments can legitimately provide the social goods necessary for the preservation and promotion of the psychological aspects of well-being. However, I end with a word of caution. The extent to which public policy should promote well-being is not obvious. It may be that only the basic psychological aspects of well-being tend to be necessary for agency. Indeed, it may be that only the absence of the psychological aspects of ill-being (such as chronic depression) is a primary good. This may make a difference to the kind of policies that governments should enact to preserve and promote well-being. Well-being and Political Liberalism Much of the talk about the use of well-being research in public policy has focused on either (a) the general validity or particular implications of well-being research, or (b) the value of well-being and related concepts (such as happiness, life satisfaction, quality of life, and so on). …","PeriodicalId":82464,"journal":{"name":"Report from the Institute for Philosophy & Public Policy","volume":"31 1","pages":"2-9"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2013-08-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"11","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Report from the Institute for Philosophy & Public Policy","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.13021/G8PPPQ.312013.135","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 11
Abstract
The use of well-being research in assessing and creating public policy is gaining popularity. The UK's Office of National Statistics has developed its National Well-being Index to do exactly that, and several other nations have followed suit. This sway in political will, however, can make the use of well-being research in public policy seem less controversial than it is. Much of the rhetoric around the move toward well-being measures in evaluating policy has centered either on the idea that well-being is what "ultimately matters" or that it is at least "something we all care about." In this essay, I will argue that such claims are illegitimate from the perspective of political liberalism. The former kind of claim is illegitimate insofar as liberal societies should not base policy on comprehensive religious, moral, or philosophical doctrines that many reasonable citizens may not accept. The latter kind of claim is illegitimate insofar as some people care significantly more than others about well-being or the ingredients of well-being. Thus, the use of well-being research to evaluate public policy cannot be justified on either of these grounds. Does this mean that there are no justifiable grounds for well-being-based policy? Not necessarily. In this essay, I explore the possibility that the psychological aspects of well-being can be viewed as a "primary good." That is, the preservation and promotion of well-being can be justified as instrumentally valuable for most people. Well-being is instrumentally valuable for most people regardless of their particular intrinsic values. In John Rawls's terms, well-being can be viewed as an all-purpose good that people are assumed to want whatever their plans. The reason for this is that the psychological aspects of well-being, the kinds of things subjective well-being research typically measures, tend to be cognitively and motivationally necessary for agency. Without being able to appreciate one's life emotionally and cognitively, one cannot sufficiently pursue one's own conception of the good. Thus, well-being tends to be necessary for leading a good life regardless of one's conception of in what a good life consists. Even if it is the case, however, that well-being can be viewed as a primary good in this way, it is not necessarily the case that the state should promote it as a matter of justice. The state should promote only primary goods that share certain important features. First, a given primary good must be distributable and objectively comparable if the state is to promote it in a just manner. In addition, the state must be in the best position to promote a given primary good. That is, the primary good must require institutional support: public policies related to its existence and continuation. Moreover, the primary good must be non-fungible. That is, it must not be commonly obtainable through substitutes--things other than the goods and services provided by the state. I will argue that the psychological aspects of well-being share each of these features. Thus, according to political liberalism, governments can legitimately provide the social goods necessary for the preservation and promotion of the psychological aspects of well-being. However, I end with a word of caution. The extent to which public policy should promote well-being is not obvious. It may be that only the basic psychological aspects of well-being tend to be necessary for agency. Indeed, it may be that only the absence of the psychological aspects of ill-being (such as chronic depression) is a primary good. This may make a difference to the kind of policies that governments should enact to preserve and promote well-being. Well-being and Political Liberalism Much of the talk about the use of well-being research in public policy has focused on either (a) the general validity or particular implications of well-being research, or (b) the value of well-being and related concepts (such as happiness, life satisfaction, quality of life, and so on). …
福祉研究在评估和制定公共政策方面的应用越来越受欢迎。英国国家统计局(Office of National Statistics)为此制定了国民幸福指数(National Well-being Index),其他几个国家也纷纷效仿。然而,这种政治意愿的摇摆可以使福祉研究在公共政策中的应用看起来没有那么有争议。围绕在政策评估中采用幸福指标的说法,要么集中在幸福是“最终重要的”,要么至少是“我们都关心的东西”这一观点上。在本文中,我将从政治自由主义的角度论证这些主张是不合法的。前一种主张是不合理的,因为自由社会不应该把政策建立在许多理性公民可能不接受的全面的宗教、道德或哲学教义之上。后一种说法是不合理的,因为有些人比其他人更关心幸福或幸福的成分。因此,利用福祉研究来评估公共政策,在上述任何一个理由上都是不合理的。这是否意味着基于福祉的政策没有正当理由?不一定。在这篇文章中,我探讨了幸福感的心理方面可以被视为“主要利益”的可能性。也就是说,对大多数人来说,维护和促进幸福是有价值的。幸福对大多数人来说是有工具价值的,不管他们的内在价值如何。用约翰·罗尔斯的话说,幸福可以被看作是一种万能的好东西,人们被假设无论他们有什么计划都想要它。原因在于,幸福感的心理方面,即主观幸福感研究通常衡量的东西,往往是行为在认知和动机上所必需的。一个人如果不能从情感上和认知上欣赏自己的生活,就无法充分追求自己对美好的理解。因此,幸福往往是过上美好生活的必要条件,而不管一个人对美好生活的概念是什么。然而,即使是这样,幸福可以被视为一种主要的好,也不一定是国家应该把它作为一种正义的问题来促进。国家应该只促进具有某些重要特征的初级产品。首先,如果国家要以公正的方式促进一种特定的初级商品,它必须是可分配的和客观上可比较的。此外,国家必须处于促进特定初级商品的最佳位置。也就是说,首要利益必须需要体制支持:与它的存在和延续有关的公共政策。此外,首要商品必须是不可替代的。也就是说,它不能通过替代品——除了国家提供的商品和服务之外的东西——普遍获得。我认为幸福的心理方面都有这些特征。因此,根据政治自由主义,政府可以合法地提供必要的社会产品,以维护和促进心理方面的福祉。然而,最后我要提醒大家一句。公共政策应该在多大程度上促进福祉并不明显。也许只有幸福的基本心理方面才是能动性所必需的。事实上,也许只有不存在疾病的心理方面(如慢性抑郁症)才是一件主要的好事。这可能会对政府为维护和促进福祉而制定的政策产生影响。关于福祉研究在公共政策中的应用的许多讨论都集中在(a)福祉研究的一般有效性或特定含义,或(b)福祉和相关概念(如幸福,生活满意度,生活质量等)的价值。...