Whose Truth? Objective and Subjective Perspectives on Truthfulness in Advocacy

W. Wendel
{"title":"Whose Truth? Objective and Subjective Perspectives on Truthfulness in Advocacy","authors":"W. Wendel","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2563767","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"A lawyer confronts many features of the world that are given, inflexible, and must simply be dealt with; at the same time she has latitude for creativity, for the exercise of skill and judgment toward the realization of the client’s ends. Although in law school it may seem that the law that is open-textured, manipulable, and the wellspring of creative lawyering, in practice the facts do not come pre-packaged and accepted as true for the purposes of an appellate court’s review, but are highly contingent and the product of the interaction between a lawyer and witnesses, documents, and other sources of information. It is exactly in this respect, however, that the theory of legal ethics is relatively under-developed. In recent years, legal ethics scholarship has changed its emphasis from ordinary first-order morality to a consideration of issues in democratic theory and legal philosophy. Focusing on the legitimacy of norms established through democratic political processes has yielded a robust theory of ethics with respect to the content of law: Ethical lawyering requires understanding the content of legal rules not from the Holmesian bad man perspective of “what can I get away with,” but from the point of view of the law as it would be understood by an impartial member of an interpretive community. The question to be considered in this paper is, if one believes that being an ethical lawyer has something to do with democratic legitimacy and the authority of law, what practical stance must a lawyer take with respect to facts? The answer to this question depends on the perspective one takes on the relationship between the role of lawyers as advocate and the contribution made by advocacy to legal legitimacy. Almost every scholar who has considered the problem of connecting ethical prescriptions for lawyers with considerations of political legitimacy, including Geoffrey Hazard and Dana Remus, Daniel Markovits, William Simon, and David Luban, has argued for a subjective perspective, so that the most important criterion for legitimacy is whether the legal system has taken into account the story the client wishes to tell. Using several case studies, I argue in this paper for the unpopular, unloved objective perspective, with the central criterion of legal legitimacy being what is the case, based on both law and facts – i.e. whether the client does or does not have a legal entitlement to do what is in her interests. Political legitimacy depends on adhering to ideals of truthfulness in politics. The alternative, subjective perspective on the relationship between legitimacy and advocacy, although emphasizing the extremely important value of human dignity, ultimately leads to a cynical, bullshitty (in Harry Frankfurt’s sense ) style of advocacy that undermines its own claim to political legitimacy.My argument is not that lawyers have a direct obligation to seek the truth. Our adversarial system of litigation presupposes that each party and her advocate will have their own perspective on the truth and be permitted to argue for it, and introduce evidence in support of it, at trial. The general theoretical orientation of the adversarial system toward partisan perspectives on the truth has, however, tended to make lawyers forget that they have some responsibility with respect to the truthfulness of litigated matters. Following Bernard Williams, I distinguish between truth with respect to some belief (“it is true that P,” where P would be something like “the defendant robbed the victim,” or “the plaintiff was standing right here when the accident occurred”) and truthfulness as an ideal that may apply to a process or institution of government. This emphasis on truth as a propositional matter has obscured the ethical analysis that should apply to practices, such as evidence gathering, the conduct of civil discovery, witness preparation, and the examination of witnesses at trial. The legitimacy of the civil justice system depends on its being a process of reason-giving, which in turn depends on the reasons having something to do with what actually is the case, as a matter of fact.","PeriodicalId":90770,"journal":{"name":"Yale journal of law & the humanities","volume":"28 1","pages":"3"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2015-02-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Yale journal of law & the humanities","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2563767","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

A lawyer confronts many features of the world that are given, inflexible, and must simply be dealt with; at the same time she has latitude for creativity, for the exercise of skill and judgment toward the realization of the client’s ends. Although in law school it may seem that the law that is open-textured, manipulable, and the wellspring of creative lawyering, in practice the facts do not come pre-packaged and accepted as true for the purposes of an appellate court’s review, but are highly contingent and the product of the interaction between a lawyer and witnesses, documents, and other sources of information. It is exactly in this respect, however, that the theory of legal ethics is relatively under-developed. In recent years, legal ethics scholarship has changed its emphasis from ordinary first-order morality to a consideration of issues in democratic theory and legal philosophy. Focusing on the legitimacy of norms established through democratic political processes has yielded a robust theory of ethics with respect to the content of law: Ethical lawyering requires understanding the content of legal rules not from the Holmesian bad man perspective of “what can I get away with,” but from the point of view of the law as it would be understood by an impartial member of an interpretive community. The question to be considered in this paper is, if one believes that being an ethical lawyer has something to do with democratic legitimacy and the authority of law, what practical stance must a lawyer take with respect to facts? The answer to this question depends on the perspective one takes on the relationship between the role of lawyers as advocate and the contribution made by advocacy to legal legitimacy. Almost every scholar who has considered the problem of connecting ethical prescriptions for lawyers with considerations of political legitimacy, including Geoffrey Hazard and Dana Remus, Daniel Markovits, William Simon, and David Luban, has argued for a subjective perspective, so that the most important criterion for legitimacy is whether the legal system has taken into account the story the client wishes to tell. Using several case studies, I argue in this paper for the unpopular, unloved objective perspective, with the central criterion of legal legitimacy being what is the case, based on both law and facts – i.e. whether the client does or does not have a legal entitlement to do what is in her interests. Political legitimacy depends on adhering to ideals of truthfulness in politics. The alternative, subjective perspective on the relationship between legitimacy and advocacy, although emphasizing the extremely important value of human dignity, ultimately leads to a cynical, bullshitty (in Harry Frankfurt’s sense ) style of advocacy that undermines its own claim to political legitimacy.My argument is not that lawyers have a direct obligation to seek the truth. Our adversarial system of litigation presupposes that each party and her advocate will have their own perspective on the truth and be permitted to argue for it, and introduce evidence in support of it, at trial. The general theoretical orientation of the adversarial system toward partisan perspectives on the truth has, however, tended to make lawyers forget that they have some responsibility with respect to the truthfulness of litigated matters. Following Bernard Williams, I distinguish between truth with respect to some belief (“it is true that P,” where P would be something like “the defendant robbed the victim,” or “the plaintiff was standing right here when the accident occurred”) and truthfulness as an ideal that may apply to a process or institution of government. This emphasis on truth as a propositional matter has obscured the ethical analysis that should apply to practices, such as evidence gathering, the conduct of civil discovery, witness preparation, and the examination of witnesses at trial. The legitimacy of the civil justice system depends on its being a process of reason-giving, which in turn depends on the reasons having something to do with what actually is the case, as a matter of fact.
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
谁的真理?倡导中真实性的客观与主观透视
律师面对世界上许多既定的、不可改变的、必须简单处理的特征;同时,她也有发挥创造力的空间,可以运用技巧和判断力来实现客户的目标。虽然在法学院,法律似乎是开放的、可操纵的,是创造性律师的源泉,但在实践中,事实并不是预先包装好的,也不是为了上诉法院的审查而被接受为真实的,而是高度偶然的,是律师与证人、文件和其他信息来源之间相互作用的产物。然而,正是在这方面,法律伦理理论相对欠发达。近年来,法律伦理研究的重点从普通的一阶道德转向对民主理论和法哲学问题的思考。关注通过民主政治过程建立的规范的合法性,已经产生了一个关于法律内容的强有力的伦理理论:伦理律师要求理解法律规则的内容,不是从“我能逃脱什么”的福尔摩斯坏人的角度,而是从法律的角度,因为它将被一个解释团体的公正成员所理解。本文要考虑的问题是,如果一个人认为作为一名道德律师与民主合法性和法律权威有关,那么律师在面对事实时必须采取什么样的实践立场?这个问题的答案取决于我们如何看待律师作为辩护人的角色与辩护人对法律正当性的贡献之间的关系。几乎每一位学者,包括杰弗里·哈扎德和达纳·雷姆斯、丹尼尔·马科维茨、威廉·西蒙和大卫·鲁班,都考虑过将律师的伦理处方与政治合法性的考虑联系起来的问题,他们都主张从主观角度出发,因此,合法性的最重要标准是法律体系是否考虑到了当事人希望讲述的故事。通过几个案例研究,我在本文中论证了不受欢迎的、不受欢迎的客观观点,法律合法性的核心标准是基于法律和事实的情况,即客户是否有合法权利做符合她利益的事情。政治合法性取决于对政治真实理想的坚持。另一种关于合法性和主张之间关系的主观视角,虽然强调了人类尊严的极其重要的价值,但最终导致了一种愤世嫉俗的、胡扯的(在哈利·法兰克福的意义上)主张风格,破坏了其自身对政治合法性的主张。我的观点并不是说律师有寻求真相的直接义务。我们的对抗性诉讼制度的前提是,每一方及其辩护人都有自己对真相的看法,并被允许在审判中为自己的观点辩护,并引入证据来支持自己的观点。然而,对抗性制度的一般理论倾向于对真相的党派观点,这往往使律师忘记了他们对诉讼事项的真实性负有一定的责任。按照伯纳德·威廉姆斯(Bernard Williams)的说法,我区分了关于某种信念的真理(“P是真的”,其中P可能类似于“被告抢劫了受害者”或“事故发生时原告就站在这里”)和作为一种可能适用于一个过程或政府机构的理想的真理。这种对真理作为命题问题的强调掩盖了应该适用于实践的伦理分析,例如证据收集、民事发现的实施、证人准备和审判时对证人的审查。民事司法制度的合法性取决于它是一个给出理由的过程,而给出理由的过程又取决于这些理由实际上与案件的实际情况有关。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
期刊最新文献
Taking Law Seriously How to Realize the Value of Stare Decisis: Options for following Precedent Jerome Frank, Lon Fuller, and a Romantic Pragmatism The Concept of "Religion The Riddle of Ruth Bryan Owen
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1