WHENCE THE DEMAND FOR ETHICAL THEORY?

IF 0.8 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI:10.2307/48614001
Damian Cueni, M. Queloz
{"title":"WHENCE THE DEMAND FOR ETHICAL THEORY?","authors":"Damian Cueni, M. Queloz","doi":"10.2307/48614001","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Where does the impetus towards ethical theory come from? What drives humans to make values explicit, consistent, and discursively justi(able? This paper situates the demand for ethical theory in human life by identifying the practical needs that give rise to it. Such a practical derivation puts the demand in its place: while (nding a home for it in the public decisionmaking of modern societies, our account also imposes limitations on the demand by presenting it as scalable and contextsensitive. This differentiates strong forms of the demand calling for theory from weaker forms calling for less, and contexts where it has a place from contexts where it is out of place. In light of this, subjecting personal deliberation to the demand turns out to involve a tradeoff. systematization by exercising our judgment in a particular case; nor, according to Williams, does that authority derive from the idea that reason itself demands this kind of systematization. To think that systematization is required either by reason itself or by the need for rational con)ict resolution, Williams maintains, betrays an overly rationalistic conception of rationality.3 But even if we agree with Williams that neither the need to resolve con)icts as such nor reason itself pull us in the direction of ethical theory, it does not necessarily follow that there is no such pull. In “Why Practice Needs Ethical Theory,” Martha Nussbaum has argued that there is a practical demand for ethical theory. Williams, she wryly remarks, conveys the impression of thinking that “when we do away with theory we will be left with people like Bernard Williams”: energetically critical and selfcritical people, not captive to any other theory, and sensitive to distortions in their experience (2000, p. We (nd ourselves with a plurality of values which, even within one person, can con)ict in ways that are not resolvable without loss.1 The need to resolve these con)icts can seem to pull ethical thought in the direction of ethical theory and systematization, notably by demanding that values be made explicit in terms of stateable principles, that they be made consistent by using some of them to overturn others in systematic ways, and that they be rendered as far as possible discursively justi!able. It is this bundle of demands—which we shall call “the Demand” for short—that will be our central concern in this paper.2 Bernard Williams has argued that insofar as we yield to the Demand, there will be a question as to where the resulting regimentation of ethical thought derives its authority from. That authority cannot simply derive from the need to resolve con)icts of values, since we are perfectly capable of rationally resolving con)icts of values without such This content downloaded from 188.154.64.229 on Wed, 31 Mar 2021 10:20:34 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 136 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY 70). But ordinary life, Nussbaum notes, is not like a Henry James novel with liberal politics thrown in. It is teeming with crude and illconsidered theories regimenting people’s lives. In practice, therefore, we need good ethical theories to drive out the bad. Whatever our conception of rationality, there is a practical demand for ethical theory. In this paper, we show that Williams can agree with Nussbaum that the Demand has a place, notably in public life, and that it is indeed a practical demand; but precisely because it is a practical demand, it must be situated in the practical contexts from which it derives its point, and this means that it arises only in certain contexts, and that even then, it remains a demand for far less than a fullblown ethical theory. We thus propose to take what might be called a humanistic approach to ethical theory: an approach that seeks to situate philosophically vexing subject matters in human life by taking an agentcentered view of them and inquiring into the practical point in human affairs of thinking along these lines in the !rst place.4 Applied to ethical theory, such a humanistic approach invites us to try and make sense, in light of facts about us and our situation, of why we come to feel the impetus towards ethical theory in the !rst place. It encourages to ask such questions as: Who needs to subject ethical thought to the Demand? Do we all need to do it all of the time, or only some of us under certain circumstances? And do we really always need a fullblown systematic and coherent ethical theory, or does the pull towards ethical theory come in degrees? Answering these questions by situating the Demand in human life will reveal that it is not just a fetish, but is rooted in human needs, so that there is a vindicatory explanation for why the Demand arises. Yet it will also vindicate the Demand only up to a point, presenting it as overreaching itself if it is taken either to apply across the board or necessarily to pull us all the way to ethical theory. This is because understanding the Demand as arising out of situated practical needs suggests that it is scalable and contextsensitive: it is scalable insofar as we can distinguish between a demand for a fullblown ethical theory and a weaker demand only for some degree of explication, systematization, and discursive justi!cation; and it is contextsensitive insofar as we can separate contexts in which the Demand has a point from contexts in which it is otiose or even harmful. Understanding these aspects of the Demand will help us put it in its proper place and think about how much ground—particularly in personal deliberation—we should cede to it. 1. Situating the Demand To situate the Demand in human life, we must understand what facts about human beings and their situation it grows out of and derives its point from. Williams goes some way towards doing this in a paper entitled “Con-icts of Values” (1981a), which complements Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. In this paper, Williams has surprisingly positive things to say about the impetus towards ethical theory. Contrary to the impression he gives in Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, he is not a sceptic about ethical theory across the board. While he denies that the Demand is a constitutive requirement of logic or rationality, he argues that it does have a practical basis in individual and social needs. In particular, he suggests that it is rooted in a requirement on agencies in a “public, large and impersonal forum” to be “governed by an explicable order which allows these agencies to be answerable” (1981a, p. 81). Taking our cue from Williams, we can try to place the Demand in human affairs by sketching, in barest outline, a prototypical situation in which the Demand arises in its most primitive form in response to human needs, thereby offering what might be called a practical derivation of the Demand. This This content downloaded from 188.154.64.229 on Wed, 31 Mar 2021 10:20:34 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ETHICAL THEORY / 137 way of proceeding is modeled on Williams’s vindicatory genealogy of the virtues of truth (2002), which is in turn modeled on E. J. Craig’s (1990) genealogy of the concept of knowledge. While Williams and Craig aim to derive the need for the virtues of truth and the concept of knowledge from very basic needs that human beings have anyway, however, we aim to show that the need for ethical theory derives from needs that are far more local—needs indexed to particular, restricted circumstances. But though the needs are more local, the method is the same: to determine what a conceptual practice does for us by identifying its natural home and the needs it answers to.5 We can start on this task with the uncontroversial idea that human beings with a plurality of values will get in each other’s way. Given a commitment to social coexistence, they will need some means of resolving con!icts in nonviolent ways, of attributing priority to certain values and determining how far they are to be realized at the expense of the realization of other values. This in itself could be achieved in many different ways—one could just about imagine it being achieved through some process that randomized over different outcomes. But if the decisions reached by any such con!ictresolver are to be effective in preventing con!ict, they also need to be enforced, and this will require some form of public power. If the exercise of this power is to be more than mere coercion—which, by breeding resentment and violence, threatens to be part of the problem rather than the solution—the decisionmaking needs to be authoritative. There needs to be some distinction between might and right, between brute power and power that is legitimated by some kind of legitimation story. In the course of history, such legitimation stories have taken very different forms, many of them transcendental. But in order to bring something like the need for ethical theory into view, we need to factor in two crucial facts about us and our situation that are far more local. The \"rst thing that we need to factor in is that we moderns in liberal democracies have particularly demanding standards for what counts as a legitimation of power. As Williams argues (2005a, p. 95), this is connected with the fact that many other legitimation stories, including notably transcendental ones, no longer carry enough conviction under conditions of modernity—we have less material available in terms of which to present decisions as authoritative. But one notable way in which, for us, decisionmaking can differ from purely arbitrary assertions of will by a Caligulan ruler is by being an impartial exercise of reasonable judgement (Williams 2005a, p. 94).6 The second thing to factor in is that we live in large societies. In suf\"ciently small and closeknit societies, it might be possible for a person to possess authority in the eyes of those concerned already in virtue of the relations of personal trust established through close acquaintance. The decisions ma","PeriodicalId":47459,"journal":{"name":"AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.8000,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"6","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.2307/48614001","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 6

Abstract

Where does the impetus towards ethical theory come from? What drives humans to make values explicit, consistent, and discursively justi(able? This paper situates the demand for ethical theory in human life by identifying the practical needs that give rise to it. Such a practical derivation puts the demand in its place: while (nding a home for it in the public decisionmaking of modern societies, our account also imposes limitations on the demand by presenting it as scalable and contextsensitive. This differentiates strong forms of the demand calling for theory from weaker forms calling for less, and contexts where it has a place from contexts where it is out of place. In light of this, subjecting personal deliberation to the demand turns out to involve a tradeoff. systematization by exercising our judgment in a particular case; nor, according to Williams, does that authority derive from the idea that reason itself demands this kind of systematization. To think that systematization is required either by reason itself or by the need for rational con)ict resolution, Williams maintains, betrays an overly rationalistic conception of rationality.3 But even if we agree with Williams that neither the need to resolve con)icts as such nor reason itself pull us in the direction of ethical theory, it does not necessarily follow that there is no such pull. In “Why Practice Needs Ethical Theory,” Martha Nussbaum has argued that there is a practical demand for ethical theory. Williams, she wryly remarks, conveys the impression of thinking that “when we do away with theory we will be left with people like Bernard Williams”: energetically critical and selfcritical people, not captive to any other theory, and sensitive to distortions in their experience (2000, p. We (nd ourselves with a plurality of values which, even within one person, can con)ict in ways that are not resolvable without loss.1 The need to resolve these con)icts can seem to pull ethical thought in the direction of ethical theory and systematization, notably by demanding that values be made explicit in terms of stateable principles, that they be made consistent by using some of them to overturn others in systematic ways, and that they be rendered as far as possible discursively justi!able. It is this bundle of demands—which we shall call “the Demand” for short—that will be our central concern in this paper.2 Bernard Williams has argued that insofar as we yield to the Demand, there will be a question as to where the resulting regimentation of ethical thought derives its authority from. That authority cannot simply derive from the need to resolve con)icts of values, since we are perfectly capable of rationally resolving con)icts of values without such This content downloaded from 188.154.64.229 on Wed, 31 Mar 2021 10:20:34 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 136 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY 70). But ordinary life, Nussbaum notes, is not like a Henry James novel with liberal politics thrown in. It is teeming with crude and illconsidered theories regimenting people’s lives. In practice, therefore, we need good ethical theories to drive out the bad. Whatever our conception of rationality, there is a practical demand for ethical theory. In this paper, we show that Williams can agree with Nussbaum that the Demand has a place, notably in public life, and that it is indeed a practical demand; but precisely because it is a practical demand, it must be situated in the practical contexts from which it derives its point, and this means that it arises only in certain contexts, and that even then, it remains a demand for far less than a fullblown ethical theory. We thus propose to take what might be called a humanistic approach to ethical theory: an approach that seeks to situate philosophically vexing subject matters in human life by taking an agentcentered view of them and inquiring into the practical point in human affairs of thinking along these lines in the !rst place.4 Applied to ethical theory, such a humanistic approach invites us to try and make sense, in light of facts about us and our situation, of why we come to feel the impetus towards ethical theory in the !rst place. It encourages to ask such questions as: Who needs to subject ethical thought to the Demand? Do we all need to do it all of the time, or only some of us under certain circumstances? And do we really always need a fullblown systematic and coherent ethical theory, or does the pull towards ethical theory come in degrees? Answering these questions by situating the Demand in human life will reveal that it is not just a fetish, but is rooted in human needs, so that there is a vindicatory explanation for why the Demand arises. Yet it will also vindicate the Demand only up to a point, presenting it as overreaching itself if it is taken either to apply across the board or necessarily to pull us all the way to ethical theory. This is because understanding the Demand as arising out of situated practical needs suggests that it is scalable and contextsensitive: it is scalable insofar as we can distinguish between a demand for a fullblown ethical theory and a weaker demand only for some degree of explication, systematization, and discursive justi!cation; and it is contextsensitive insofar as we can separate contexts in which the Demand has a point from contexts in which it is otiose or even harmful. Understanding these aspects of the Demand will help us put it in its proper place and think about how much ground—particularly in personal deliberation—we should cede to it. 1. Situating the Demand To situate the Demand in human life, we must understand what facts about human beings and their situation it grows out of and derives its point from. Williams goes some way towards doing this in a paper entitled “Con-icts of Values” (1981a), which complements Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. In this paper, Williams has surprisingly positive things to say about the impetus towards ethical theory. Contrary to the impression he gives in Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, he is not a sceptic about ethical theory across the board. While he denies that the Demand is a constitutive requirement of logic or rationality, he argues that it does have a practical basis in individual and social needs. In particular, he suggests that it is rooted in a requirement on agencies in a “public, large and impersonal forum” to be “governed by an explicable order which allows these agencies to be answerable” (1981a, p. 81). Taking our cue from Williams, we can try to place the Demand in human affairs by sketching, in barest outline, a prototypical situation in which the Demand arises in its most primitive form in response to human needs, thereby offering what might be called a practical derivation of the Demand. This This content downloaded from 188.154.64.229 on Wed, 31 Mar 2021 10:20:34 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ETHICAL THEORY / 137 way of proceeding is modeled on Williams’s vindicatory genealogy of the virtues of truth (2002), which is in turn modeled on E. J. Craig’s (1990) genealogy of the concept of knowledge. While Williams and Craig aim to derive the need for the virtues of truth and the concept of knowledge from very basic needs that human beings have anyway, however, we aim to show that the need for ethical theory derives from needs that are far more local—needs indexed to particular, restricted circumstances. But though the needs are more local, the method is the same: to determine what a conceptual practice does for us by identifying its natural home and the needs it answers to.5 We can start on this task with the uncontroversial idea that human beings with a plurality of values will get in each other’s way. Given a commitment to social coexistence, they will need some means of resolving con!icts in nonviolent ways, of attributing priority to certain values and determining how far they are to be realized at the expense of the realization of other values. This in itself could be achieved in many different ways—one could just about imagine it being achieved through some process that randomized over different outcomes. But if the decisions reached by any such con!ictresolver are to be effective in preventing con!ict, they also need to be enforced, and this will require some form of public power. If the exercise of this power is to be more than mere coercion—which, by breeding resentment and violence, threatens to be part of the problem rather than the solution—the decisionmaking needs to be authoritative. There needs to be some distinction between might and right, between brute power and power that is legitimated by some kind of legitimation story. In the course of history, such legitimation stories have taken very different forms, many of them transcendental. But in order to bring something like the need for ethical theory into view, we need to factor in two crucial facts about us and our situation that are far more local. The "rst thing that we need to factor in is that we moderns in liberal democracies have particularly demanding standards for what counts as a legitimation of power. As Williams argues (2005a, p. 95), this is connected with the fact that many other legitimation stories, including notably transcendental ones, no longer carry enough conviction under conditions of modernity—we have less material available in terms of which to present decisions as authoritative. But one notable way in which, for us, decisionmaking can differ from purely arbitrary assertions of will by a Caligulan ruler is by being an impartial exercise of reasonable judgement (Williams 2005a, p. 94).6 The second thing to factor in is that we live in large societies. In suf"ciently small and closeknit societies, it might be possible for a person to possess authority in the eyes of those concerned already in virtue of the relations of personal trust established through close acquaintance. The decisions ma
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
伦理理论的需求从何而来?
伦理理论的动力来自哪里?是什么驱使人类使价值观变得明确、一致、可论证?本文通过识别产生伦理理论的现实需要,将伦理理论的需求置于人类生活的位置。这样一个实际的推导把需求放在了合适的位置:虽然在现代社会的公共决策中为它找到了一个家,但我们的解释也通过将其呈现为可扩展和上下文敏感而对需求施加了限制。这区分了要求理论的强烈形式和要求较少的较弱形式,以及它有一席之地的环境和不合适的环境。有鉴于此,将个人考虑置于需求之下就涉及到一种权衡。通过在特定情况下行使我们的判断来系统化;根据威廉姆斯的观点,这种权威也不是来自于理性本身要求这种系统化的观点。威廉斯认为,认为系统化是理性本身或理性冲突解决的需要所必需的,背叛了一种过度理性主义的理性概念但是,即使我们同意威廉姆斯的观点,即解决冲突的需要和理性本身都没有把我们拉向伦理理论的方向,这也不一定意味着没有这种拉。在《为什么实践需要伦理理论》一书中,玛莎·努斯鲍姆(Martha Nussbaum)认为,存在着对伦理理论的实践需求。她讽刺地说,威廉姆斯传达了这样一种印象,即“当我们抛弃理论时,我们将留下像伯纳德·威廉姆斯这样的人”:积极批判和自我批判的人,不受任何其他理论的束缚,对他们经验中的扭曲很敏感(2000,p.)。我们(发现自己有多种价值观,即使在一个人身上,也可能以不受损失的方式冲突解决这些冲突的需要似乎会把伦理思想拉向伦理理论和系统化的方向,特别是要求价值观以可陈述的原则来明确,通过用一些原则以系统的方式推翻另一些原则来保持一致,并且尽可能地使它们在论述上是合理的。这一系列需求——我们将简称其为“需求”——将是我们在本文中主要关注的问题伯纳德·威廉姆斯(Bernard Williams)认为,只要我们屈服于这种要求,就会出现一个问题,即由此产生的伦理思想的管制从何而来。这种权威不能简单地来自于解决价值观冲突的需要,因为我们完全有能力在没有这种需求的情况下理性地解决价值观冲突。此内容下载自188.154.64.229(星期三,2021年3月31日10:20:34 UTC)所有使用均受https://about.jstor.org/terms 136 /美国哲学季刊70)。但努斯鲍姆指出,普通人的生活并不像亨利·詹姆斯(Henry James)的小说中加入了自由主义政治。它充斥着粗糙和欠考虑的理论,控制着人们的生活。因此,在实践中,我们需要好的伦理理论来驱逐坏的。无论我们对理性的概念是什么,都有对伦理理论的实际需求。在本文中,我们表明威廉姆斯可以同意努斯鲍姆的观点,即需求有一席之地,特别是在公共生活中,而且它确实是一种现实的需求;但是,正因为它是一种实践的要求,它就必须被置于它的论点所根据的实践的语境中,这就是说,它只在某些语境中产生,而且即使在这种语境中,它仍然是一种远不完全是完备的伦理理论的要求。因此,我们建议对伦理理论采取一种可能被称为人文主义的方法:这种方法试图通过采取以主体为中心的观点来定位人类生活中哲学上令人烦恼的主题问题,并首先探讨沿着这些路线思考的人类事务中的实践点应用于伦理理论,这种人文主义的方法邀请我们尝试和理解,根据关于我们和我们的情况的事实,为什么我们开始感受到对伦理理论的推动。它鼓励人们提出这样的问题:谁需要将伦理思想置于需求之下?我们所有人都需要一直这样做吗,还是只有在某些情况下才需要?我们真的总是需要一个完整的、系统的、连贯的伦理理论吗?还是伦理理论的吸引力是分程度的?通过将需求置于人类生活中来回答这些问题,将揭示它不仅仅是一种恋物癖,而是根植于人类的需求,因此对需求产生的原因有一个证明性的解释。然而,它也只能在一定程度上证明需求是正确的,如果它被认为是全面适用的,或者必然会把我们一直拉到伦理理论,那么它就会显得过于夸大。 伦理理论的动力来自哪里?是什么驱使人类使价值观变得明确、一致、可论证?本文通过识别产生伦理理论的现实需要,将伦理理论的需求置于人类生活的位置。这样一个实际的推导把需求放在了合适的位置:虽然在现代社会的公共决策中为它找到了一个家,但我们的解释也通过将其呈现为可扩展和上下文敏感而对需求施加了限制。这区分了要求理论的强烈形式和要求较少的较弱形式,以及它有一席之地的环境和不合适的环境。有鉴于此,将个人考虑置于需求之下就涉及到一种权衡。通过在特定情况下行使我们的判断来系统化;根据威廉姆斯的观点,这种权威也不是来自于理性本身要求这种系统化的观点。威廉斯认为,认为系统化是理性本身或理性冲突解决的需要所必需的,背叛了一种过度理性主义的理性概念但是,即使我们同意威廉姆斯的观点,即解决冲突的需要和理性本身都没有把我们拉向伦理理论的方向,这也不一定意味着没有这种拉。在《为什么实践需要伦理理论》一书中,玛莎·努斯鲍姆(Martha Nussbaum)认为,存在着对伦理理论的实践需求。她讽刺地说,威廉姆斯传达了这样一种印象,即“当我们抛弃理论时,我们将留下像伯纳德·威廉姆斯这样的人”:积极批判和自我批判的人,不受任何其他理论的束缚,对他们经验中的扭曲很敏感(2000,p.)。我们(发现自己有多种价值观,即使在一个人身上,也可能以不受损失的方式冲突解决这些冲突的需要似乎会把伦理思想拉向伦理理论和系统化的方向,特别是要求价值观以可陈述的原则来明确,通过用一些原则以系统的方式推翻另一些原则来保持一致,并且尽可能地使它们在论述上是合理的。这一系列需求——我们将简称其为“需求”——将是我们在本文中主要关注的问题伯纳德·威廉姆斯(Bernard Williams)认为,只要我们屈服于这种要求,就会出现一个问题,即由此产生的伦理思想的管制从何而来。这种权威不能简单地来自于解决价值观冲突的需要,因为我们完全有能力在没有这种需求的情况下理性地解决价值观冲突。此内容下载自188.154.64.229(星期三,2021年3月31日10:20:34 UTC)所有使用均受https://about.jstor.org/terms 136 /美国哲学季刊70)。但努斯鲍姆指出,普通人的生活并不像亨利·詹姆斯(Henry James)的小说中加入了自由主义政治。它充斥着粗糙和欠考虑的理论,控制着人们的生活。因此,在实践中,我们需要好的伦理理论来驱逐坏的。无论我们对理性的概念是什么,都有对伦理理论的实际需求。在本文中,我们表明威廉姆斯可以同意努斯鲍姆的观点,即需求有一席之地,特别是在公共生活中,而且它确实是一种现实的需求;但是,正因为它是一种实践的要求,它就必须被置于它的论点所根据的实践的语境中,这就是说,它只在某些语境中产生,而且即使在这种语境中,它仍然是一种远不完全是完备的伦理理论的要求。因此,我们建议对伦理理论采取一种可能被称为人文主义的方法:这种方法试图通过采取以主体为中心的观点来定位人类生活中哲学上令人烦恼的主题问题,并首先探讨沿着这些路线思考的人类事务中的实践点应用于伦理理论,这种人文主义的方法邀请我们尝试和理解,根据关于我们和我们的情况的事实,为什么我们开始感受到对伦理理论的推动。它鼓励人们提出这样的问题:谁需要将伦理思想置于需求之下?我们所有人都需要一直这样做吗,还是只有在某些情况下才需要?我们真的总是需要一个完整的、系统的、连贯的伦理理论吗?还是伦理理论的吸引力是分程度的?通过将需求置于人类生活中来回答这些问题,将揭示它不仅仅是一种恋物癖,而是根植于人类的需求,因此对需求产生的原因有一个证明性的解释。然而,它也只能在一定程度上证明需求是正确的,如果它被认为是全面适用的,或者必然会把我们一直拉到伦理理论,那么它就会显得过于夸大。 这是因为将需求理解为产生于情境中的实际需求,表明它是可扩展的和上下文敏感的:它是可扩展的,因为我们可以区分对完整的伦理理论的需求和对某种程度的解释、系统化和话语正当化的较弱需求;它是上下文敏感的,因为我们可以将需求有观点的上下文与无用甚至有害的上下文区分开来。理解“需求”的这些方面将有助于我们把它放在合适的位置上,并思考我们应该向它让步多少——尤其是在个人审议方面。1. 要将需求定位在人类生活中,我们必须了解关于人类及其处境的哪些事实是需求的来源和出发点。威廉姆斯在一篇题为“价值观的冲突”(1981)的论文中对此做了一些尝试,这篇论文补充了《伦理学和哲学的局限性》。在这篇论文中,威廉姆斯对伦理理论的发展有着令人惊讶的积极看法。与他在《伦理学与哲学的局限》中给人的印象相反,他并不是一个对伦理理论持怀疑态度的人。虽然他否认需求是逻辑或理性的构成要求,但他认为需求在个人和社会需求中确实有实践基础。他特别指出,其根源在于对“公共、大型和非个人论坛”中的机构的要求,即“由一种可解释的秩序来管理,这种秩序允许这些机构负责”(1981a,第81页)。从威廉姆斯那里得到启示,我们可以尝试将需求置于人类事务中,以最简单的轮廓描绘出一种典型的情况,在这种情况下,需求以其最原始的形式出现,以回应人类的需要,从而提供一种可能被称为需求的实际推导。此内容下载自188.154.64.229,周三,2021年3月31日10:20:34 UTC所有使用均须遵守https://about.jstor.org/terms伦理理论/ 137程序的方式是模仿威廉姆斯的真理美德的辩护谱系(2002),这反过来是模仿E. J.克雷格(1990)的知识概念谱系。虽然威廉姆斯和克雷格的目标是从人类无论如何都具有的非常基本的需求中推导出对真理美德和知识概念的需求,然而,我们的目标是表明,对伦理理论的需求来自更局部的需求——与特定的、受限制的环境相关联的需求。但是,尽管需求更本地化,方法是相同的:通过识别其自然家园和它所满足的需求来确定概念实践为我们做了什么我们可以从一个毫无争议的观点开始这项任务,即具有多种价值观的人类会互相妨碍。鉴于对社会共存的承诺,他们将需要一些解决欺诈的手段!以非暴力的方式,赋予某些价值优先权,并以牺牲其他价值的实现为代价,决定这些价值的实现程度。这本身可以通过许多不同的方式来实现——人们可以想象它是通过一些随机化的过程来实现的。但如果做出这样的决定!解决方案是有效地防止欺诈!在信息和通信技术方面,它们也需要强制执行,这将需要某种形式的公共权力。如果要让这种权力的行使不仅仅是强制,而强制会滋生怨恨和暴力,可能会成为问题的一部分而不是解决问题的办法,那么决策就需要具有权威性。强权和权利之间,蛮力和权力之间需要有一些区别,这是通过某种合法化故事来合法化的。在历史的进程中,这种合法化的故事采取了非常不同的形式,其中许多是先验的。但是为了让人们认识到伦理理论的必要性,我们需要考虑两个关于我们和我们的处境的关键事实,这两个事实更具有地方性。“我们需要考虑的另一件事是,我们这些自由民主国家的现代人对什么是权力的合法性有着特别苛刻的标准。正如威廉姆斯所说(2005,第95页),这与许多其他合法化故事,包括显著的先验故事,在现代性条件下不再具有足够的说服力这一事实有关——我们有更少的可用材料来将决定呈现为权威。但是,对我们来说,一个值得注意的方式是,决策可以不同于卡利古兰统治者的纯粹武断的意志断言,这是一种公正的合理判断(Williams 2005a, p. 94)第二个要考虑的因素是,我们生活在一个大社会中。 这是因为将需求理解为产生于情境中的实际需求,表明它是可扩展的和上下文敏感的:它是可扩展的,因为我们可以区分对完整的伦理理论的需求和对某种程度的解释、系统化和话语正当化的较弱需求;它是上下文敏感的,因为我们可以将需求有观点的上下文与无用甚至有害的上下文区分开来。理解“需求”的这些方面将有助于我们把它放在合适的位置上,并思考我们应该向它让步多少——尤其是在个人审议方面。1. 要将需求定位在人类生活中,我们必须了解关于人类及其处境的哪些事实是需求的来源和出发点。威廉姆斯在一篇题为“价值观的冲突”(1981)的论文中对此做了一些尝试,这篇论文补充了《伦理学和哲学的局限性》。在这篇论文中,威廉姆斯对伦理理论的发展有着令人惊讶的积极看法。与他在《伦理学与哲学的局限》中给人的印象相反,他并不是一个对伦理理论持怀疑态度的人。虽然他否认需求是逻辑或理性的构成要求,但他认为需求在个人和社会需求中确实有实践基础。他特别指出,其根源在于对“公共、大型和非个人论坛”中的机构的要求,即“由一种可解释的秩序来管理,这种秩序允许这些机构负责”(1981a,第81页)。从威廉姆斯那里得到启示,我们可以尝试将需求置于人类事务中,以最简单的轮廓描绘出一种典型的情况,在这种情况下,需求以其最原始的形式出现,以回应人类的需要,从而提供一种可能被称为需求的实际推导。此内容下载自188.154.64.229,周三,2021年3月31日10:20:34 UTC所有使用均须遵守https://about.jstor.org/terms伦理理论/ 137程序的方式是模仿威廉姆斯的真理美德的辩护谱系(2002),这反过来是模仿E. J.克雷格(1990)的知识概念谱系。虽然威廉姆斯和克雷格的目标是从人类无论如何都具有的非常基本的需求中推导出对真理美德和知识概念的需求,然而,我们的目标是表明,对伦理理论的需求来自更局部的需求——与特定的、受限制的环境相关联的需求。但是,尽管需求更本地化,方法是相同的:通过识别其自然家园和它所满足的需求来确定概念实践为我们做了什么我们可以从一个毫无争议的观点开始这项任务,即具有多种价值观的人类会互相妨碍。鉴于对社会共存的承诺,他们将需要一些解决欺诈的手段!以非暴力的方式,赋予某些价值优先权,并以牺牲其他价值的实现为代价,决定这些价值的实现程度。这本身可以通过许多不同的方式来实现——人们可以想象它是通过一些随机化的过程来实现的。但如果做出这样的决定!解决方案是有效地防止欺诈!在信息和通信技术方面,它们也需要强制执行,这将需要某种形式的公共权力。如果要让这种权力的行使不仅仅是强制,而强制会滋生怨恨和暴力,可能会成为问题的一部分而不是解决问题的办法,那么决策就需要具有权威性。强权和权利之间,蛮力和权力之间需要有一些区别,这是通过某种合法化故事来合法化的。在历史的进程中,这种合法化的故事采取了非常不同的形式,其中许多是先验的。但是为了让人们认识到伦理理论的必要性,我们需要考虑两个关于我们和我们的处境的关键事实,这两个事实更具有地方性。“我们需要考虑的另一件事是,我们这些自由民主国家的现代人对什么是权力的合法性有着特别苛刻的标准。正如威廉姆斯所说(2005,第95页),这与许多其他合法化故事,包括显著的先验故事,在现代性条件下不再具有足够的说服力这一事实有关——我们有更少的可用材料来将决定呈现为权威。但是,对我们来说,一个值得注意的方式是,决策可以不同于卡利古兰统治者的纯粹武断的意志断言,这是一种公正的合理判断(Williams 2005a, p. 94)第二个要考虑的因素是,我们生活在一个大社会中。 在足够小而紧密联系的社会中,一个人有可能凭借通过亲密的熟人建立起来的个人信任关系,在相关的人眼中拥有权威。这些决定很重要。 在足够小而紧密联系的社会中,一个人有可能凭借通过亲密的熟人建立起来的个人信任关系,在相关的人眼中拥有权威。这些决定很重要。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
1.50
自引率
0.00%
发文量
22
期刊介绍: Since its inauguration in 1964, the American Philosophical Quarterly (APQ) has established itself as one of the principal English vehicles for the publication of scholarly work in philosophy. The whole of each issue—printed in a large-page, double-column format—is given to substantial articles; from time to time there are also "state of the art" surveys of recent work on particular topics. The editorial policy is to publish work of high quality, regardless of the school of thought from which it derives.
期刊最新文献
Race and Class Together Virtue Ethics in Social Theory Structural Racism Within Reason What Does it Mean to Say “The Criminal Justice System is Racist”? Anti-Asian Racism
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1