Deliberative Democracy and Campaign Finance Reform

Q2 Social Sciences Law and Contemporary Problems Pub Date : 2002-06-22 DOI:10.2307/1192407
Neil J. Kinkopf
{"title":"Deliberative Democracy and Campaign Finance Reform","authors":"Neil J. Kinkopf","doi":"10.2307/1192407","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Professor Schroeder's paper sets out a compelling description of some intractable problems with deliberative theory. I have found nothing to criticize in his outstanding article. In this comment, I wish to expand upon Schroeder's critique. In particular, I wish to explore a tension that occasionally arises among the fundamental elements of the theory of deliberative democracy. I first invoke the privilege of symposium comment writers to free-ride on the work of the principal paper. Professor Schroeder has presented a lucid survey of deliberative theory. (1) While I do not intend to repeat an exercise so well accomplished, a few points bear emphasizing. Deliberative theory is concerned with the problem of dissensus and justification. Given a plurality of reasonable, opposing views and assuming that all citizens are free and equal, how can one group--even a majority--justify imposing its preferences on another? Put another way, how can we justify applying the coercive power of the state against reasonable dissenters? (2) The response of deliberativists is that the exercise of state power is justified through a process of public reasoning. (3) This deliberative process is modeled expressly on the example of judicial decision-making. (4) Those who make a claim regarding the application of state power must offer reasons to justify their claims, much as a judge offers an opinion to justi fy the holding in a case. (5) This process of deliberation has three hallmarks. First, deliberation must be status-insensitive. As Schroeder explained in his article, \"individuals should have no advantages in the process of public deliberation by virtue of their wealth, social status, ability to mobilize electoral assets, or capacity to provide rewards to other participants in the process.\" (6) Second, decisions are to be based on reasoned argument. (7) Third, arguments advanced must be sincere. \"An argument ... must be one that [a deliberating citizen] endorses and one that 'would figure prominently amongst [her] reasons for the proposal,' absent other considerations.\" (8) The operation of deliberative democracy focuses on the public justification for a position. Focusing on the ex post justification leads to significant problems because it ignores a distinct and prior stage--the actual formation of a position. (9) Perversely, this focus can lead deliberativists to discount the importance of reason and even to undermine the ability of reason to function at this prior stage. (10) Moreover, the requirement that public justification take the form of reasoned argument can conflict with the requirement of status insensitivity. The campaign finance reform debate illustrates this problem. Given the imperative of status-insensitivity, it is not surprising that deliberativists tend ardently to support campaign finance reform. (11) Large campaign contributions and expenditures have long been understood to yield significant inequalities among citizens in terms of ability to participate effectively in the political process. Those who are able to make large contributions and expenditures enjoy an elevated status in the political arena compared to other citizens. Redressing this inequality has been a fundamental motivation of every modern attempt at campaign finance reform. (12) The problem for deliberativists is that this remedy is at war with their vision of the deliberative process. The dominant model of campaign finance reform proposals is to equalize citizen participation opportunities by limiting the impact of money in elections. (13) Given the cost of access to the media necessary to participate fully and effectively in public discourse, however, this approach inevitably entails less speech. (14) Any determination by the government that some quantum of speech is too much or drowns out the speech of others represents a level of distrust of the capacity of reason to govern deliberation. …","PeriodicalId":39484,"journal":{"name":"Law and Contemporary Problems","volume":"7 1","pages":"151-154"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2002-06-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Law and Contemporary Problems","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.2307/1192407","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q2","JCRName":"Social Sciences","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Professor Schroeder's paper sets out a compelling description of some intractable problems with deliberative theory. I have found nothing to criticize in his outstanding article. In this comment, I wish to expand upon Schroeder's critique. In particular, I wish to explore a tension that occasionally arises among the fundamental elements of the theory of deliberative democracy. I first invoke the privilege of symposium comment writers to free-ride on the work of the principal paper. Professor Schroeder has presented a lucid survey of deliberative theory. (1) While I do not intend to repeat an exercise so well accomplished, a few points bear emphasizing. Deliberative theory is concerned with the problem of dissensus and justification. Given a plurality of reasonable, opposing views and assuming that all citizens are free and equal, how can one group--even a majority--justify imposing its preferences on another? Put another way, how can we justify applying the coercive power of the state against reasonable dissenters? (2) The response of deliberativists is that the exercise of state power is justified through a process of public reasoning. (3) This deliberative process is modeled expressly on the example of judicial decision-making. (4) Those who make a claim regarding the application of state power must offer reasons to justify their claims, much as a judge offers an opinion to justi fy the holding in a case. (5) This process of deliberation has three hallmarks. First, deliberation must be status-insensitive. As Schroeder explained in his article, "individuals should have no advantages in the process of public deliberation by virtue of their wealth, social status, ability to mobilize electoral assets, or capacity to provide rewards to other participants in the process." (6) Second, decisions are to be based on reasoned argument. (7) Third, arguments advanced must be sincere. "An argument ... must be one that [a deliberating citizen] endorses and one that 'would figure prominently amongst [her] reasons for the proposal,' absent other considerations." (8) The operation of deliberative democracy focuses on the public justification for a position. Focusing on the ex post justification leads to significant problems because it ignores a distinct and prior stage--the actual formation of a position. (9) Perversely, this focus can lead deliberativists to discount the importance of reason and even to undermine the ability of reason to function at this prior stage. (10) Moreover, the requirement that public justification take the form of reasoned argument can conflict with the requirement of status insensitivity. The campaign finance reform debate illustrates this problem. Given the imperative of status-insensitivity, it is not surprising that deliberativists tend ardently to support campaign finance reform. (11) Large campaign contributions and expenditures have long been understood to yield significant inequalities among citizens in terms of ability to participate effectively in the political process. Those who are able to make large contributions and expenditures enjoy an elevated status in the political arena compared to other citizens. Redressing this inequality has been a fundamental motivation of every modern attempt at campaign finance reform. (12) The problem for deliberativists is that this remedy is at war with their vision of the deliberative process. The dominant model of campaign finance reform proposals is to equalize citizen participation opportunities by limiting the impact of money in elections. (13) Given the cost of access to the media necessary to participate fully and effectively in public discourse, however, this approach inevitably entails less speech. (14) Any determination by the government that some quantum of speech is too much or drowns out the speech of others represents a level of distrust of the capacity of reason to govern deliberation. …
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
协商民主与竞选财政改革
施罗德教授的论文对审议理论中一些棘手的问题进行了令人信服的描述。我在他那篇出色的文章中找不到什么可批评的。在这篇评论中,我希望扩展施罗德的批评。特别是,我希望探讨在协商民主理论的基本要素之间偶尔出现的紧张关系。我首先援引专题讨论会评论作者的特权,免费利用主要论文的工作成果。施罗德教授对审议理论作了一个清晰的概述。虽然我不打算重复一项完成得如此出色的工作,但有几点需要强调。协商理论关注的是异议和正当性问题。考虑到存在多种合理的对立观点,并假设所有公民都是自由平等的,一个群体——甚至是多数群体——怎么能证明将自己的偏好强加给另一个群体是正当的呢?换句话说,我们如何证明运用国家的强制权力来对付合理的异议者是正当的?(2)协商主义者的回应是,国家权力的行使是通过公共推理的过程来证明的。(3)这一审议过程明确以司法决策为例。那些对国家权力的运用提出要求的人必须提供理由来证明他们的要求是正当的,就像法官提供意见来证明一个案件的判决是正当的一样。(5)审议过程有三个特点。首先,审议必须对地位不敏感。正如施罗德在他的文章中所解释的那样,“个人在公共审议过程中不应凭借其财富、社会地位、动员选举资产的能力或向过程中的其他参与者提供奖励的能力而享有优势。”第二,决策要基于合理的论证。第三,提出的论点必须是真诚的。“争论……必须是一个[审慎的公民]认可的,并且在不考虑其他因素的情况下,“将成为[她]提出建议的主要原因”。(8)协商民主的运作重点是公众对一个立场的正当理由。专注于事后辩护会导致严重的问题,因为它忽略了一个明显的前期阶段——立场的实际形成。(9)反常的是,这种关注可能导致商议主义者低估理性的重要性,甚至破坏理性在这一先前阶段发挥作用的能力。(10)此外,公开辩护采取理性论证形式的要求可能与地位不敏感的要求相冲突。关于竞选资金改革的辩论说明了这个问题。考虑到地位不敏感的必要性,商议主义者倾向于热烈支持竞选资金改革也就不足为奇了。(11)长期以来,人们一直认为,巨额竞选捐款和支出在公民有效参与政治进程的能力方面造成了严重的不平等。那些有能力提供大笔捐款和支出的人在政治舞台上的地位比其他公民高。纠正这种不平等一直是现代每一次竞选资金改革尝试的根本动机。(12)协商主义者面临的问题是,这种补救办法与他们对协商过程的看法相抵触。竞选资金改革提案的主要模式是通过限制金钱对选举的影响来平等公民参与机会。(13)但是,考虑到充分和有效地参与公共讨论所必需的使用媒介的费用,这种做法必然导致较少的言论。(14)如果政府认定某种言论量过多或淹没了其他人的言论,就表示一定程度上对理性支配审议的能力的不信任。...
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
Law and Contemporary Problems
Law and Contemporary Problems Social Sciences-Law
CiteScore
2.00
自引率
0.00%
发文量
1
期刊介绍: Law and Contemporary Problems was founded in 1933 and is the oldest journal published at Duke Law School. It is a quarterly, interdisciplinary, faculty-edited publication of Duke Law School. L&CP recognizes that many fields in the sciences, social sciences, and humanities can enhance the development and understanding of law. It is our purpose to seek out these areas of overlap and to publish balanced symposia that enlighten not just legal readers, but readers from these other disciplines as well. L&CP uses a symposium format, generally publishing one symposium per issue on a topic of contemporary concern. Authors and articles are selected to ensure that each issue collectively creates a unified presentation of the contemporary problem under consideration. L&CP hosts an annual conference at Duke Law School featuring the authors of one of the year’s four symposia.
期刊最新文献
The Influence of Re-Selection on Independent Decision Making in State Supreme Courts Voting Rights and the “Statutory Constitution” Challenging Gender in Single-Sex Spaces: Lessons from a Feminist Softball League Treaties and Human Rights: The Role of Long-Term Trends Correcting Federalism Mistakes in Statutory Interpretation: The Supreme Court and the Federal Arbitration Act
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1