核级联还是一成不变?为什么美利欧主义者可能是对的?对特洛克等人(2023)的评论

Etel Solingen
{"title":"核级联还是一成不变?为什么美利欧主义者可能是对的?对特洛克等人(2023)的评论","authors":"Etel Solingen","doi":"10.1002/ffo2.168","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Tetlock et al.'s balanced contribution to the debate over the possibility of long-range geopolitical forecasting provides a useful roadmap at a critical time. An especially challenging geopolitical juncture compels heightened attention to systematic efforts of this sort that both identify limits on expert judgment and offer ways to overcome them. The task may be extremely difficult—skeptics abound—but is nevertheless vital for a social science true to the mission of enhancing peace and security. Tetlock et al. report findings from a previous study suggesting that expertise in nuclear weapons improved accuracy in predicting long-range proliferation. In particular, they argue, experts did not cry wolf; they exhibited low False-Alarm rates. Meliorists could find some reassurance there. And yet this field of inquiry has also seen significant and repeated overestimation of the odds of nuclear proliferation cascades. In 1963 President Kennedy foresaw the potential of between 15 and 25 nuclear weapons states by 1975. Yet rather than actual proliferation cascades, it is only <i>predictions</i> of imminent cascades, chains, and dominoes that have proliferated since (Potter &amp; Mukhatzhanova, <span>2008</span>). Such predictions have failed to materialize thus far for well over 60 years, a significantly long range. Radical Skeptics might find this vindicating. Understanding the sources of over-predicted proliferation on the one hand, and of the more accurate tally in Tetlock et al.'s findings on the other, may shed light on these two distinctive (past) readings of the future. It may also further improve the Meliorist's case for long-range predictions.</p><p>Over-predictions of nuclear proliferation may run the epistemological-ontological gamut, but I focus here on one <i>systematic</i> source of bias leading to massive False Positives for over 60 years. This record is especially, though not uniquely, the domain of a brand of neorealist theory alluring for its simplicity—“it's all about systemic anarchy and balance of power.” Anarchy presumably renders all states insecure, compelling self-help while acquiring nuclear weapons provides security, helps balance power, delivers stability, and minimizes the chances of war (the classic and most impressive locus is Waltz, <span>1979</span>, <span>1981</span>). Yet this analytical foundation has proved fatally flawed in its predictive tally. The massive number of predicted False Positives and anomalies in neorealist studies include Ukraine, Poland, Germany, Japan, and many, many more cases.1 If one abides by the theory's core tenets, anarchy, uncertainty, and self-help should have led most if not all states to acquire nuclear weapons. Yet an overwhelming majority (191 states!) have renounced them while nine have acquired them. Even more modest predictions (Waltz, <span>1981</span>) of 18 to 30 nuclear weapons states have not materialized; and even acutely vulnerable states (e.g., Vietnam, Egypt, Taiwan, and many others) have not matched those theoretical priors.</p><p>Other empirical anomalies for the theory stand out. Offers of “hegemonic protection” had disparate effects, with some states renouncing nuclear weapons but not others. In line with the theory's core tenet, alliances cannot explain nuclear abstention in an anarchic context: self-help dominates, making alliances feeble by definition. Indeed, “nuclear weapons make alliances obsolete” (Waltz, <span>1979</span>, <span>1981</span>). The empirical record confirms that some allies abstained from acquiring them but not others, and that most states restrained their nuclear ambitions in the absence of superpower guarantees. Comparable structural conditions can (and have) lead to very different nuclear choices. Whereas the theory predicts that multipolarity leads to nuclearization, multipolarity has led to different outcomes across time and space (e.g., East Asia vs. the Middle East vs. Latin America). Predictive insolvency has thus manifested itself at all levels of aggregation—systemic, regional, bilateral, and individual cases—and for a large number of cumulative years that offered the opportunity to test the argument's validity. This record is especially odd for a theory operating at the heart—the inner sanctum—of states' security dilemmas, a predictive domain that loads the dice in its favor as the most auspicious terrain for corroborating its tenets. If the theory cannot make it here, some could wonder whether it can make it anywhere, borrowing from Levy's (<span>2022</span>, p. 442) “reverse Sinatra inference.”</p><p>Speaking of such inferences, a neorealist argument consistent with its tenets must easily place Japan among “most likely” cases for acquiring nuclear weapons. Japan has endured repeated and long-lasting cumulative shocks: not one, not two, but three of its rabid neighbors have acquired nuclear weapons (Soviet Union/Russia, China, and North Korea). Yet, in an astonishing blow to neorealist predictions (i.e., countries putatively go nuclear when adversarial neighbors do so) the perfect candidate for reactive nuclearization failed to acquire its own deterrent <i>for 70 years</i> (and counting). This is a very long-term predictive horizon indeed, no matter what happens next (Deacon &amp; Solingen, <span>2023</span>). Too many presumed thresholds have already been crossed and even a broken clock is right twice a day. As argued, invoking the US alliance to salvage predictive failure constitutes a major logical departure from first neorealist principles, where alliances can never be trusted and are clearly theorized to lack heft anyway.</p><p>Why so many empirical failures of prediction, quantitative and qualitative? First, Tetlock et al. find that the more bias-resistant and logically coherent the forecasting agents, the more accurate their predictions. Alas, neorealism suffers variously from explanatory inconsistency, logical incoherence, or unfalsifiable predictions. Many outcomes can be made to fit vague ad-hoc notions of security maximization (a posteriori). At best the approach is under-determining and its corollaries are inconclusive and open-ended: Japan should acquire nuclear weapons; not acquire them; substitute for them conventionally; not substitute; rely on the alliance; not rely; and so on, all in the name of <i>the same</i> first principles of security maximization under anarchy. There isn't a singular structural logic at play: acquiring nuclear weapons can effectively lead to higher <i>in</i>security and vulnerability. Second, neorealist arguments are time-invariant, stemming from a putatively inexorable, ahistorical “balance of power” untouched by evolving world-time. Third, as an invisible hand, “balance of power” is surely among the most invisible of them all, under-defined, unmeasurable, and unquantifiable; a wobbly, vague concept with low intersubjective reliability. Fourth, Tetlock et al. also expect that “accuracy will fall off more slowly for experts who demonstrate a command of predictively useful knowledge in the early periods.” This intuition is borne out by the fact that neorealist accounts typically hinge less on deep knowledge of any cases than on simplified “Occam razor”-style assumptions. This theoretical penchant for extreme parsimony leads to information asymmetry between neorealist-based predictions and those relying on richer knowledge of cases. Coming to term with these shortcomings, in recent decades studies began challenging previously unquestioned confidence in this theory as <i>the</i> driving force of all nuclear decisions (Ogilvie-White, <span>1996</span>; Solingen, <span>1994a</span>, <span>1994b</span>).</p><p>Having identified a key intellectual culprit of over-predictions, I turn to alternative approaches that may account for the superior predictive tally reported in Tetlock et al.'s study. Meliorists can rejoice in their initial findings that experts leaning on tolerance of ambiguity and dissonance, scope-sensitivity, bounded claims, and self-criticism may generate predictions that have proven better endowed to withstand the test of time. To the extent that these approaches avoided False Alarms of proliferation cascades, they already bring an epistemic edge to the table. The list of hypotheses under this rubric is diverse and more extensively discussed in Solingen (<span>1994a</span>, <span>2018a</span>). In this brief essay, I confine myself to an argument I developed in International Security (1994a), later elaborated in <i>Nuclear Logics</i> (Solingen, <span>1994a</span>, <span>1994b</span>, <span>2007</span>). An influential meta-study on failed proliferation chains by Potter and Mukhatzhanova (<span>2008</span>) wielded it as an example that obviated over-predicted cascades. Another study (Sil &amp; Katzenstein, <span>2010</span>) considered <i>Nuclear Logics'</i> core argument to have been <i>the</i> most undertheorized in this field hitherto as well as an analytically eclectic—yet clearly formulated—framework for estimating nuclear scenarios.</p><p>At its core, this framework highlighted that conceptions of security threats were not simple derivatives of abstract, elusive balances of power but were, instead, highly influenced by domestic models of political survival. These models hinged on competing orientations to the global political economy and offered important clues for estimating nuclear choices since the inception of the Nonproliferation Treaty in 1968. Internationalizing models were predicted to <i>lower the likelihood</i> of nuclear weapons' acquisition based on identified causal mechanisms upholding that relationship. Indeed, for over 50 years every decision to renounce nuclear weapons by states that had previously entertained them was nested in broader shifts toward internationalizing models. By contrast, most defiant nuclear courses since 1968 unfolded under inward-looking models hostile to integration in the global political economy. This pattern found support across different regional security contexts and diverse associations with hegemons and alliances. That it does so in a theoretically unfriendly terrain is especially suggestive; nuclear choices are arguably a “least likely” arena for corroborating the explanatory and predictive heft of domestic political economy models. And yet, despite the regularities the approach uncovered, it had been omitted from the canonical causal repertoire. That omission led to an overestimation of other presumed causal variables, especially neorealist ones.</p><p>Models of political survival explain both synchronic variation in nuclear preferences across states and overtime variation within the same state; varying state compliance with nonproliferation commitments; varying readings of security dilemmas as more (or less) intractable; variance in ranking alliances higher than self-reliance or vice versa; variance in relative receptivity to external sanctions and inducements; why and when external coercion and inducements may be effective; and why nuclear ambitions were renounced where one might have expected them. And yet, as Sil and Katzenstein note, domestic models were not portrayed as a holy grail that displaces other perspectives; the title “Nuclear Logics”—in the plural—made clear that, while making a compelling case, this argument is not the only game in town. Sil and Katzenstein deem it a pragmatic, self-conscious effort to avoid the trap of becoming so deeply embedded in a single paradigm that makes it impossible to “look at the world with fresh eyes.” Instead, the proposed models provide a useful prism that helps weigh and re-order the relative relevance of other drivers, including structural power, interests, norms, and institutions. The models refract, interpret, and filter external stimuli, offering a nimble analytical category to accommodate the reality of multiple causation. The very definition of security is endogenous to these models rather than an independent variable, as neorealism would have it.</p><p>Furthermore, the framework identified important caveats and scope conditions, making the association between models and nuclear choices neither deterministic nor inevitable but probabilistic and eminently falsifiable. One temporal scope condition was that the post-NPT “world-time” or “second nuclear age” posed different systemic constraints than those preceding it and possibly superseding it. Temporal sequencing also matters: nuclear reversals might be much harder when nuclear weapons acquisition precedes the inception of internationalizing models (e.g., China, India, Israel). Abandoning nuclear weapons once they already exist is more costly politically than ending a program before fruition, as prospect theory would submit. Another scope condition stipulated that the relative incidence of internationalizing versus inward-looking models at the regional level would inhibit or exacerbate domestic preferences regarding nuclear weapons in either direction. The framework also specified that the choice for or against alliances (which might/might not substitute for an indigenous deterrent) was also endogenous to domestic models. Sensitive to the fact that hegemony has its limits, this take is in notable agreement with Waltz's (<span>1981</span>) who rightfully argued that “in the past half-century, no country has been able to prevent other countries from going nuclear if they were determined to do so.” But this assertion evokes, once again, a conundrum for neorealist logic: Why were most countries <i>not</i> determined to do so in the first place in a world of anarchy, insecurity, and zero-sumness?</p><p>Political survival models are a dynamic category, entailing no linear or irreversible trajectory in either direction. Its predictive scenarios specified the logical conditions under which scenarios might obtain, the kind of evidence that would question or validate expectations, and the outcomes that would corroborate or falsify the theory. Even where past predictive performance over a relatively extended temporal range may have been reassuring, much to our dismay social theories don't typically work for eternity and may be less useful henceforth. Tetlock et al. acknowledge that easy questions posed during a placid period of history (slow-motion variables with low base rates of change) may help the case for Meliorism and long-range predictability. This suggests that the world-time under which a predictive study is conducted (e.g., the heart of the Cold War vs. the zenith of globalization or “end of history”) may affect aggregate forecasts by experts and nonexperts alike. Net predictability hinges not only on the skill or bias of forecasters but also on historical world-time. Alas, the contemporary geopolitical landscape may alter the relative stability of the last 30–40 years. Global and domestic shocks have rendered too many political, economic, technological, and other variables highly uncertain. Russia's attack on Ukraine compounded those shocks inducing nearly chaotic perturbation of significant relevance to nuclear futures. Ukraine had renounced the nuclear weapons it possessed in exchange of security guarantees from major powers including Russia (another anomaly for neorealism?). Putin proceeded to invade Ukraine in 2014 and 2022 and shower nuclear threats on several targets in and beyond Ukraine. Finally, a putative “third nuclear age” driven by artificial intelligence ambitions might return the “cascade” scenario forecasted by President Kennedy and so many others since the 1960s. But in line with the cautionary advice in Tetlock et al., one must also consider the distinct possibility that the emerging world time might retain some of the basic underlying conditions that obviated cascades in the past. Path dependence can persist. It may be premature to proclaim a wholesale <i>Zeitenwende</i> in nuclear forecasting. Even so, discontinuities and inefficient history (March &amp; Olsen, <span>1998</span>) could burden longer-range predictions under the current geopolitical juncture, pregnant with the highest levels of uncertainty in decades.</p><p>An enduring allegiance to failed epistemologies and ontologies is a sure path to fuel Radical Skeptics' convictions. Similar errors stemming from reductionist conceptualization have led to repeated falsified predictions of NATO's demise for over 70 years and much more. To be sure, neorealism is not the only source of prediction error. A related approach associated with technological determinism also exhibits a substantial number of “most likely cases” that renounced nuclear weapons and “least likely cases” that pursued them (Miller, <span>2017</span>). As Lewis (<span>2016</span>) argued, whether or not states decide not to acquire nuclear weapons has often far more to do with restraint than with technological barriers, given a 65-year-old technology. As the sheer size of failed predictions became evident, new studies pledging neorealist roots sought to rectify some of the noted deficiencies. In so doing, that work departs from first neorealist principles in several ways: it suddenly endows alliances with colossal analytical heft and attaches a large number of contingencies that throw “Occam razor” out the window (Debs &amp; Monteiro, <span>2016</span>). That is a commendable step that could enhance the potential for “adversarial collaborations” and improved predictions. Retaining other first (neorealist) principles, however, may also retain logical inconsistency. A consistent focus on the logic of anarchy trumps the idea that states can substitute self-help for external protection. Furthermore, continued reliance on fuzzy, elastic, and highly subjective definitions of balance of power, self-help, insecurity, and power itself make predictions even more elusive and possibly unfalsifiable. Scenarios hinging on external threats—not a figment of neorealist imagination—could do better when considering the domestic political landscapes that heighten or dampen pressures to respond to threats with nuclear weapons' acquisition. Important work along the lines of classical and neoclassical realism (Wohlforth, <span>1993</span>) does just that.</p><p>Adversarial collaborations proposed by Tetlock et al. would have to overcome deep cleavages in this field of inquiry, including methodological ones, that may have hindered progress hitherto. Such collaborations could, however, facilitate the crafting of “coherence hypotheses” that bear on the connections between the empirical accuracy of forecasts and the logical rigor with which forecasters make cumulative-risk judgments. “Viewpoint-variable” hypotheses can consider systematic bias stemming from the connections among ideology, forecasts, and forecasting accuracy. Other rules of thumb for converging on adversarial collaborations include greater attention to complex systemic effects, replacing analytically impoverished and grossly deficient—if parsimonious—forecasts. Hypotheses must be cast in falsifiable terms, with greater precision and better specification of threshold and boundary conditions; avoid circularity and ex-post-facto rationalizations; stipulate the kind of evidence that would challenge or corroborate their expectations; assess findings against competing theoretical claims; consider ways to discover, dissect, and assess indirect causal pathways, even if they are more difficult to work with; and devote attention to temporality and world time, or historical context. Above all, heightened tolerance for fallibility—especially for longer haul predictions—will remain forecasting's best friend, all the more so under current conditions of intensive and extensive domestic and systemic geopolitical uncertainty.</p>","PeriodicalId":100567,"journal":{"name":"FUTURES & FORESIGHT SCIENCE","volume":"6 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2023-08-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1002/ffo2.168","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Nuclear cascades or more of the same? Why meliorists may have gotten it right: A commentary on Tetlock et al. (2023)\",\"authors\":\"Etel Solingen\",\"doi\":\"10.1002/ffo2.168\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>Tetlock et al.'s balanced contribution to the debate over the possibility of long-range geopolitical forecasting provides a useful roadmap at a critical time. An especially challenging geopolitical juncture compels heightened attention to systematic efforts of this sort that both identify limits on expert judgment and offer ways to overcome them. The task may be extremely difficult—skeptics abound—but is nevertheless vital for a social science true to the mission of enhancing peace and security. Tetlock et al. report findings from a previous study suggesting that expertise in nuclear weapons improved accuracy in predicting long-range proliferation. In particular, they argue, experts did not cry wolf; they exhibited low False-Alarm rates. Meliorists could find some reassurance there. And yet this field of inquiry has also seen significant and repeated overestimation of the odds of nuclear proliferation cascades. In 1963 President Kennedy foresaw the potential of between 15 and 25 nuclear weapons states by 1975. Yet rather than actual proliferation cascades, it is only <i>predictions</i> of imminent cascades, chains, and dominoes that have proliferated since (Potter &amp; Mukhatzhanova, <span>2008</span>). Such predictions have failed to materialize thus far for well over 60 years, a significantly long range. Radical Skeptics might find this vindicating. Understanding the sources of over-predicted proliferation on the one hand, and of the more accurate tally in Tetlock et al.'s findings on the other, may shed light on these two distinctive (past) readings of the future. It may also further improve the Meliorist's case for long-range predictions.</p><p>Over-predictions of nuclear proliferation may run the epistemological-ontological gamut, but I focus here on one <i>systematic</i> source of bias leading to massive False Positives for over 60 years. This record is especially, though not uniquely, the domain of a brand of neorealist theory alluring for its simplicity—“it's all about systemic anarchy and balance of power.” Anarchy presumably renders all states insecure, compelling self-help while acquiring nuclear weapons provides security, helps balance power, delivers stability, and minimizes the chances of war (the classic and most impressive locus is Waltz, <span>1979</span>, <span>1981</span>). Yet this analytical foundation has proved fatally flawed in its predictive tally. The massive number of predicted False Positives and anomalies in neorealist studies include Ukraine, Poland, Germany, Japan, and many, many more cases.1 If one abides by the theory's core tenets, anarchy, uncertainty, and self-help should have led most if not all states to acquire nuclear weapons. Yet an overwhelming majority (191 states!) have renounced them while nine have acquired them. Even more modest predictions (Waltz, <span>1981</span>) of 18 to 30 nuclear weapons states have not materialized; and even acutely vulnerable states (e.g., Vietnam, Egypt, Taiwan, and many others) have not matched those theoretical priors.</p><p>Other empirical anomalies for the theory stand out. Offers of “hegemonic protection” had disparate effects, with some states renouncing nuclear weapons but not others. In line with the theory's core tenet, alliances cannot explain nuclear abstention in an anarchic context: self-help dominates, making alliances feeble by definition. Indeed, “nuclear weapons make alliances obsolete” (Waltz, <span>1979</span>, <span>1981</span>). The empirical record confirms that some allies abstained from acquiring them but not others, and that most states restrained their nuclear ambitions in the absence of superpower guarantees. Comparable structural conditions can (and have) lead to very different nuclear choices. Whereas the theory predicts that multipolarity leads to nuclearization, multipolarity has led to different outcomes across time and space (e.g., East Asia vs. the Middle East vs. Latin America). Predictive insolvency has thus manifested itself at all levels of aggregation—systemic, regional, bilateral, and individual cases—and for a large number of cumulative years that offered the opportunity to test the argument's validity. This record is especially odd for a theory operating at the heart—the inner sanctum—of states' security dilemmas, a predictive domain that loads the dice in its favor as the most auspicious terrain for corroborating its tenets. If the theory cannot make it here, some could wonder whether it can make it anywhere, borrowing from Levy's (<span>2022</span>, p. 442) “reverse Sinatra inference.”</p><p>Speaking of such inferences, a neorealist argument consistent with its tenets must easily place Japan among “most likely” cases for acquiring nuclear weapons. Japan has endured repeated and long-lasting cumulative shocks: not one, not two, but three of its rabid neighbors have acquired nuclear weapons (Soviet Union/Russia, China, and North Korea). Yet, in an astonishing blow to neorealist predictions (i.e., countries putatively go nuclear when adversarial neighbors do so) the perfect candidate for reactive nuclearization failed to acquire its own deterrent <i>for 70 years</i> (and counting). This is a very long-term predictive horizon indeed, no matter what happens next (Deacon &amp; Solingen, <span>2023</span>). Too many presumed thresholds have already been crossed and even a broken clock is right twice a day. As argued, invoking the US alliance to salvage predictive failure constitutes a major logical departure from first neorealist principles, where alliances can never be trusted and are clearly theorized to lack heft anyway.</p><p>Why so many empirical failures of prediction, quantitative and qualitative? First, Tetlock et al. find that the more bias-resistant and logically coherent the forecasting agents, the more accurate their predictions. Alas, neorealism suffers variously from explanatory inconsistency, logical incoherence, or unfalsifiable predictions. Many outcomes can be made to fit vague ad-hoc notions of security maximization (a posteriori). At best the approach is under-determining and its corollaries are inconclusive and open-ended: Japan should acquire nuclear weapons; not acquire them; substitute for them conventionally; not substitute; rely on the alliance; not rely; and so on, all in the name of <i>the same</i> first principles of security maximization under anarchy. There isn't a singular structural logic at play: acquiring nuclear weapons can effectively lead to higher <i>in</i>security and vulnerability. Second, neorealist arguments are time-invariant, stemming from a putatively inexorable, ahistorical “balance of power” untouched by evolving world-time. Third, as an invisible hand, “balance of power” is surely among the most invisible of them all, under-defined, unmeasurable, and unquantifiable; a wobbly, vague concept with low intersubjective reliability. Fourth, Tetlock et al. also expect that “accuracy will fall off more slowly for experts who demonstrate a command of predictively useful knowledge in the early periods.” This intuition is borne out by the fact that neorealist accounts typically hinge less on deep knowledge of any cases than on simplified “Occam razor”-style assumptions. This theoretical penchant for extreme parsimony leads to information asymmetry between neorealist-based predictions and those relying on richer knowledge of cases. Coming to term with these shortcomings, in recent decades studies began challenging previously unquestioned confidence in this theory as <i>the</i> driving force of all nuclear decisions (Ogilvie-White, <span>1996</span>; Solingen, <span>1994a</span>, <span>1994b</span>).</p><p>Having identified a key intellectual culprit of over-predictions, I turn to alternative approaches that may account for the superior predictive tally reported in Tetlock et al.'s study. Meliorists can rejoice in their initial findings that experts leaning on tolerance of ambiguity and dissonance, scope-sensitivity, bounded claims, and self-criticism may generate predictions that have proven better endowed to withstand the test of time. To the extent that these approaches avoided False Alarms of proliferation cascades, they already bring an epistemic edge to the table. The list of hypotheses under this rubric is diverse and more extensively discussed in Solingen (<span>1994a</span>, <span>2018a</span>). In this brief essay, I confine myself to an argument I developed in International Security (1994a), later elaborated in <i>Nuclear Logics</i> (Solingen, <span>1994a</span>, <span>1994b</span>, <span>2007</span>). An influential meta-study on failed proliferation chains by Potter and Mukhatzhanova (<span>2008</span>) wielded it as an example that obviated over-predicted cascades. Another study (Sil &amp; Katzenstein, <span>2010</span>) considered <i>Nuclear Logics'</i> core argument to have been <i>the</i> most undertheorized in this field hitherto as well as an analytically eclectic—yet clearly formulated—framework for estimating nuclear scenarios.</p><p>At its core, this framework highlighted that conceptions of security threats were not simple derivatives of abstract, elusive balances of power but were, instead, highly influenced by domestic models of political survival. These models hinged on competing orientations to the global political economy and offered important clues for estimating nuclear choices since the inception of the Nonproliferation Treaty in 1968. Internationalizing models were predicted to <i>lower the likelihood</i> of nuclear weapons' acquisition based on identified causal mechanisms upholding that relationship. Indeed, for over 50 years every decision to renounce nuclear weapons by states that had previously entertained them was nested in broader shifts toward internationalizing models. By contrast, most defiant nuclear courses since 1968 unfolded under inward-looking models hostile to integration in the global political economy. This pattern found support across different regional security contexts and diverse associations with hegemons and alliances. That it does so in a theoretically unfriendly terrain is especially suggestive; nuclear choices are arguably a “least likely” arena for corroborating the explanatory and predictive heft of domestic political economy models. And yet, despite the regularities the approach uncovered, it had been omitted from the canonical causal repertoire. That omission led to an overestimation of other presumed causal variables, especially neorealist ones.</p><p>Models of political survival explain both synchronic variation in nuclear preferences across states and overtime variation within the same state; varying state compliance with nonproliferation commitments; varying readings of security dilemmas as more (or less) intractable; variance in ranking alliances higher than self-reliance or vice versa; variance in relative receptivity to external sanctions and inducements; why and when external coercion and inducements may be effective; and why nuclear ambitions were renounced where one might have expected them. And yet, as Sil and Katzenstein note, domestic models were not portrayed as a holy grail that displaces other perspectives; the title “Nuclear Logics”—in the plural—made clear that, while making a compelling case, this argument is not the only game in town. Sil and Katzenstein deem it a pragmatic, self-conscious effort to avoid the trap of becoming so deeply embedded in a single paradigm that makes it impossible to “look at the world with fresh eyes.” Instead, the proposed models provide a useful prism that helps weigh and re-order the relative relevance of other drivers, including structural power, interests, norms, and institutions. The models refract, interpret, and filter external stimuli, offering a nimble analytical category to accommodate the reality of multiple causation. The very definition of security is endogenous to these models rather than an independent variable, as neorealism would have it.</p><p>Furthermore, the framework identified important caveats and scope conditions, making the association between models and nuclear choices neither deterministic nor inevitable but probabilistic and eminently falsifiable. One temporal scope condition was that the post-NPT “world-time” or “second nuclear age” posed different systemic constraints than those preceding it and possibly superseding it. Temporal sequencing also matters: nuclear reversals might be much harder when nuclear weapons acquisition precedes the inception of internationalizing models (e.g., China, India, Israel). Abandoning nuclear weapons once they already exist is more costly politically than ending a program before fruition, as prospect theory would submit. Another scope condition stipulated that the relative incidence of internationalizing versus inward-looking models at the regional level would inhibit or exacerbate domestic preferences regarding nuclear weapons in either direction. The framework also specified that the choice for or against alliances (which might/might not substitute for an indigenous deterrent) was also endogenous to domestic models. Sensitive to the fact that hegemony has its limits, this take is in notable agreement with Waltz's (<span>1981</span>) who rightfully argued that “in the past half-century, no country has been able to prevent other countries from going nuclear if they were determined to do so.” But this assertion evokes, once again, a conundrum for neorealist logic: Why were most countries <i>not</i> determined to do so in the first place in a world of anarchy, insecurity, and zero-sumness?</p><p>Political survival models are a dynamic category, entailing no linear or irreversible trajectory in either direction. Its predictive scenarios specified the logical conditions under which scenarios might obtain, the kind of evidence that would question or validate expectations, and the outcomes that would corroborate or falsify the theory. Even where past predictive performance over a relatively extended temporal range may have been reassuring, much to our dismay social theories don't typically work for eternity and may be less useful henceforth. Tetlock et al. acknowledge that easy questions posed during a placid period of history (slow-motion variables with low base rates of change) may help the case for Meliorism and long-range predictability. This suggests that the world-time under which a predictive study is conducted (e.g., the heart of the Cold War vs. the zenith of globalization or “end of history”) may affect aggregate forecasts by experts and nonexperts alike. Net predictability hinges not only on the skill or bias of forecasters but also on historical world-time. Alas, the contemporary geopolitical landscape may alter the relative stability of the last 30–40 years. Global and domestic shocks have rendered too many political, economic, technological, and other variables highly uncertain. Russia's attack on Ukraine compounded those shocks inducing nearly chaotic perturbation of significant relevance to nuclear futures. Ukraine had renounced the nuclear weapons it possessed in exchange of security guarantees from major powers including Russia (another anomaly for neorealism?). Putin proceeded to invade Ukraine in 2014 and 2022 and shower nuclear threats on several targets in and beyond Ukraine. Finally, a putative “third nuclear age” driven by artificial intelligence ambitions might return the “cascade” scenario forecasted by President Kennedy and so many others since the 1960s. But in line with the cautionary advice in Tetlock et al., one must also consider the distinct possibility that the emerging world time might retain some of the basic underlying conditions that obviated cascades in the past. Path dependence can persist. It may be premature to proclaim a wholesale <i>Zeitenwende</i> in nuclear forecasting. Even so, discontinuities and inefficient history (March &amp; Olsen, <span>1998</span>) could burden longer-range predictions under the current geopolitical juncture, pregnant with the highest levels of uncertainty in decades.</p><p>An enduring allegiance to failed epistemologies and ontologies is a sure path to fuel Radical Skeptics' convictions. Similar errors stemming from reductionist conceptualization have led to repeated falsified predictions of NATO's demise for over 70 years and much more. To be sure, neorealism is not the only source of prediction error. A related approach associated with technological determinism also exhibits a substantial number of “most likely cases” that renounced nuclear weapons and “least likely cases” that pursued them (Miller, <span>2017</span>). As Lewis (<span>2016</span>) argued, whether or not states decide not to acquire nuclear weapons has often far more to do with restraint than with technological barriers, given a 65-year-old technology. As the sheer size of failed predictions became evident, new studies pledging neorealist roots sought to rectify some of the noted deficiencies. In so doing, that work departs from first neorealist principles in several ways: it suddenly endows alliances with colossal analytical heft and attaches a large number of contingencies that throw “Occam razor” out the window (Debs &amp; Monteiro, <span>2016</span>). That is a commendable step that could enhance the potential for “adversarial collaborations” and improved predictions. Retaining other first (neorealist) principles, however, may also retain logical inconsistency. A consistent focus on the logic of anarchy trumps the idea that states can substitute self-help for external protection. Furthermore, continued reliance on fuzzy, elastic, and highly subjective definitions of balance of power, self-help, insecurity, and power itself make predictions even more elusive and possibly unfalsifiable. Scenarios hinging on external threats—not a figment of neorealist imagination—could do better when considering the domestic political landscapes that heighten or dampen pressures to respond to threats with nuclear weapons' acquisition. Important work along the lines of classical and neoclassical realism (Wohlforth, <span>1993</span>) does just that.</p><p>Adversarial collaborations proposed by Tetlock et al. would have to overcome deep cleavages in this field of inquiry, including methodological ones, that may have hindered progress hitherto. Such collaborations could, however, facilitate the crafting of “coherence hypotheses” that bear on the connections between the empirical accuracy of forecasts and the logical rigor with which forecasters make cumulative-risk judgments. “Viewpoint-variable” hypotheses can consider systematic bias stemming from the connections among ideology, forecasts, and forecasting accuracy. Other rules of thumb for converging on adversarial collaborations include greater attention to complex systemic effects, replacing analytically impoverished and grossly deficient—if parsimonious—forecasts. Hypotheses must be cast in falsifiable terms, with greater precision and better specification of threshold and boundary conditions; avoid circularity and ex-post-facto rationalizations; stipulate the kind of evidence that would challenge or corroborate their expectations; assess findings against competing theoretical claims; consider ways to discover, dissect, and assess indirect causal pathways, even if they are more difficult to work with; and devote attention to temporality and world time, or historical context. Above all, heightened tolerance for fallibility—especially for longer haul predictions—will remain forecasting's best friend, all the more so under current conditions of intensive and extensive domestic and systemic geopolitical uncertainty.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":100567,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"FUTURES & FORESIGHT SCIENCE\",\"volume\":\"6 1\",\"pages\":\"\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-08-17\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1002/ffo2.168\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"FUTURES & FORESIGHT SCIENCE\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/ffo2.168\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"FUTURES & FORESIGHT SCIENCE","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/ffo2.168","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

泰特洛克等人对长期地缘政治预测可能性的辩论做出了平衡的贡献,在关键时刻提供了有用的路线图。一个特别具有挑战性的地缘政治节点迫使人们高度关注这类系统性努力,这些努力既确定了专家判断的局限性,又提供了克服这些局限性的方法。这项任务可能极其困难——怀疑者比比皆是——但对于一门真正致力于促进和平与安全的社会科学来说,这是至关重要的。这篇文章受版权保护。版权所有。 它在一个理论上并不友好的环境中做到了这一点,这一点尤其具有启发性;可以说,核选择是一个 "最不可能 "证实国内政治经济学模型的解释力和预测力的领域。然而,尽管这种方法发现了一些规律性的东西,但它却被从典型的因果关系中遗漏了。这种忽略导致了对其他假定因果变量的高估,尤其是新现实主义变量。政治生存模型既能解释国家间核偏好的同步变化,也能解释同一国家内部的超时变化;国家对防扩散承诺的遵守情况各不相同;对安全困境的解读也各不相同,有的更棘手(有的不那么棘手),有的将结盟排在自力更生之前,有的则相反;对外部制裁和诱导的相对接受程度也各不相同;外部胁迫和诱导为何有效,何时有效;以及为何人们本以为会放弃核野心的地方却放弃了核野心。然而,正如西尔和卡曾斯坦所指出的,国内模式并没有被描绘成取代其他观点的圣杯;标题 "核逻辑"--复数--清楚地表明,尽管这一论点令人信服,但它并不是镇上唯一的游戏。西尔和卡岑斯坦认为,这是一种务实的、自觉的努力,以避免陷入一种单一范式的陷阱,从而无法 "用新的眼光看世界"。相反,所提出的模式提供了一个有用的棱镜,有助于权衡和重新排列其他驱动因素的相对相关性,包括结构性权力、利益、规范和制度。这些模型可以折射、解释和过滤外部刺激,为适应多重因果关系的现实提供了一个灵活的分析类别。安全的定义本身就是这些模型的内生因素,而不是新现实主义所认为的独立变量。此外,该框架还确定了重要的注意事项和范围条件,使模型与核选择之间的关联既不是确定的,也不是必然的,而是概率性的,而且是完全可以证伪的。其中一个时间范围条件是,《不扩散条约》之后的 "世界时间 "或 "第二个核时代 "所带来的系统约束与之前的以及可能取代它的约束不同。时间顺序也很重要:如果核武器的获取早于国际化模式(如中国、印度、以色列)的开始,核逆转可能会更加困难。正如前景理论所言,一旦核武器已经存在,放弃核武器的政治代价要比在项目取得成果之前结束项目的代价更大。另一个范围条件规定,在地区层面,国际化模式与内向型模式的相对发生率会抑制或加剧国内对核武器的偏好。该框架还规定,选择或反对结盟(可能/不可能替代本土威慑力量)也是国内模式的内生因素。华尔兹(1981 年)认为 "在过去的半个世纪中,没有一个国家能够阻止其他国家发展核武器,如果它们决心这样做的话"。但这一论断再次唤起了新现实主义逻辑的困惑:在一个无政府、不安全和零和的世界里,为什么大多数国家一开始就没有决心这样做呢?"政治生存模式是一个动态的范畴,不存在线性或不可逆转的轨迹。它的预测情景规定了情景可能出现的逻辑条件、质疑或验证预期的证据类型,以及证实或证伪理论的结果。即使过去在一个相对较长的时间范围内的预测表现可能令人欣慰,但令我们沮丧的是,社会理论通常不会永远有效,而且从今以后可能也不会那么有用了。特特洛克等人承认,在平和的历史时期提出简单的问题(基本变化率较低的慢动作变量),可能有助于证明梅利奥主义和长期可预测性。这表明,进行预测研究时所处的世界时间(如冷战中心与全球化顶峰或 "历史终结")可能会影响专家和非专家的综合预测。净可预测性不仅取决于预测者的技能或偏见,还取决于历史世界时间。遗憾的是,当代地缘政治格局可能会改变过去 30-40 年的相对稳定性。全球和国内的冲击使太多的政治、经济、技术和其他变量变得高度不确定。俄罗斯对乌克兰的攻击加剧了这些冲击,造成了近乎混乱的扰动,对核未来具有重大意义。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Nuclear cascades or more of the same? Why meliorists may have gotten it right: A commentary on Tetlock et al. (2023)

Tetlock et al.'s balanced contribution to the debate over the possibility of long-range geopolitical forecasting provides a useful roadmap at a critical time. An especially challenging geopolitical juncture compels heightened attention to systematic efforts of this sort that both identify limits on expert judgment and offer ways to overcome them. The task may be extremely difficult—skeptics abound—but is nevertheless vital for a social science true to the mission of enhancing peace and security. Tetlock et al. report findings from a previous study suggesting that expertise in nuclear weapons improved accuracy in predicting long-range proliferation. In particular, they argue, experts did not cry wolf; they exhibited low False-Alarm rates. Meliorists could find some reassurance there. And yet this field of inquiry has also seen significant and repeated overestimation of the odds of nuclear proliferation cascades. In 1963 President Kennedy foresaw the potential of between 15 and 25 nuclear weapons states by 1975. Yet rather than actual proliferation cascades, it is only predictions of imminent cascades, chains, and dominoes that have proliferated since (Potter & Mukhatzhanova, 2008). Such predictions have failed to materialize thus far for well over 60 years, a significantly long range. Radical Skeptics might find this vindicating. Understanding the sources of over-predicted proliferation on the one hand, and of the more accurate tally in Tetlock et al.'s findings on the other, may shed light on these two distinctive (past) readings of the future. It may also further improve the Meliorist's case for long-range predictions.

Over-predictions of nuclear proliferation may run the epistemological-ontological gamut, but I focus here on one systematic source of bias leading to massive False Positives for over 60 years. This record is especially, though not uniquely, the domain of a brand of neorealist theory alluring for its simplicity—“it's all about systemic anarchy and balance of power.” Anarchy presumably renders all states insecure, compelling self-help while acquiring nuclear weapons provides security, helps balance power, delivers stability, and minimizes the chances of war (the classic and most impressive locus is Waltz, 19791981). Yet this analytical foundation has proved fatally flawed in its predictive tally. The massive number of predicted False Positives and anomalies in neorealist studies include Ukraine, Poland, Germany, Japan, and many, many more cases.1 If one abides by the theory's core tenets, anarchy, uncertainty, and self-help should have led most if not all states to acquire nuclear weapons. Yet an overwhelming majority (191 states!) have renounced them while nine have acquired them. Even more modest predictions (Waltz, 1981) of 18 to 30 nuclear weapons states have not materialized; and even acutely vulnerable states (e.g., Vietnam, Egypt, Taiwan, and many others) have not matched those theoretical priors.

Other empirical anomalies for the theory stand out. Offers of “hegemonic protection” had disparate effects, with some states renouncing nuclear weapons but not others. In line with the theory's core tenet, alliances cannot explain nuclear abstention in an anarchic context: self-help dominates, making alliances feeble by definition. Indeed, “nuclear weapons make alliances obsolete” (Waltz, 19791981). The empirical record confirms that some allies abstained from acquiring them but not others, and that most states restrained their nuclear ambitions in the absence of superpower guarantees. Comparable structural conditions can (and have) lead to very different nuclear choices. Whereas the theory predicts that multipolarity leads to nuclearization, multipolarity has led to different outcomes across time and space (e.g., East Asia vs. the Middle East vs. Latin America). Predictive insolvency has thus manifested itself at all levels of aggregation—systemic, regional, bilateral, and individual cases—and for a large number of cumulative years that offered the opportunity to test the argument's validity. This record is especially odd for a theory operating at the heart—the inner sanctum—of states' security dilemmas, a predictive domain that loads the dice in its favor as the most auspicious terrain for corroborating its tenets. If the theory cannot make it here, some could wonder whether it can make it anywhere, borrowing from Levy's (2022, p. 442) “reverse Sinatra inference.”

Speaking of such inferences, a neorealist argument consistent with its tenets must easily place Japan among “most likely” cases for acquiring nuclear weapons. Japan has endured repeated and long-lasting cumulative shocks: not one, not two, but three of its rabid neighbors have acquired nuclear weapons (Soviet Union/Russia, China, and North Korea). Yet, in an astonishing blow to neorealist predictions (i.e., countries putatively go nuclear when adversarial neighbors do so) the perfect candidate for reactive nuclearization failed to acquire its own deterrent for 70 years (and counting). This is a very long-term predictive horizon indeed, no matter what happens next (Deacon & Solingen, 2023). Too many presumed thresholds have already been crossed and even a broken clock is right twice a day. As argued, invoking the US alliance to salvage predictive failure constitutes a major logical departure from first neorealist principles, where alliances can never be trusted and are clearly theorized to lack heft anyway.

Why so many empirical failures of prediction, quantitative and qualitative? First, Tetlock et al. find that the more bias-resistant and logically coherent the forecasting agents, the more accurate their predictions. Alas, neorealism suffers variously from explanatory inconsistency, logical incoherence, or unfalsifiable predictions. Many outcomes can be made to fit vague ad-hoc notions of security maximization (a posteriori). At best the approach is under-determining and its corollaries are inconclusive and open-ended: Japan should acquire nuclear weapons; not acquire them; substitute for them conventionally; not substitute; rely on the alliance; not rely; and so on, all in the name of the same first principles of security maximization under anarchy. There isn't a singular structural logic at play: acquiring nuclear weapons can effectively lead to higher insecurity and vulnerability. Second, neorealist arguments are time-invariant, stemming from a putatively inexorable, ahistorical “balance of power” untouched by evolving world-time. Third, as an invisible hand, “balance of power” is surely among the most invisible of them all, under-defined, unmeasurable, and unquantifiable; a wobbly, vague concept with low intersubjective reliability. Fourth, Tetlock et al. also expect that “accuracy will fall off more slowly for experts who demonstrate a command of predictively useful knowledge in the early periods.” This intuition is borne out by the fact that neorealist accounts typically hinge less on deep knowledge of any cases than on simplified “Occam razor”-style assumptions. This theoretical penchant for extreme parsimony leads to information asymmetry between neorealist-based predictions and those relying on richer knowledge of cases. Coming to term with these shortcomings, in recent decades studies began challenging previously unquestioned confidence in this theory as the driving force of all nuclear decisions (Ogilvie-White, 1996; Solingen, 1994a1994b).

Having identified a key intellectual culprit of over-predictions, I turn to alternative approaches that may account for the superior predictive tally reported in Tetlock et al.'s study. Meliorists can rejoice in their initial findings that experts leaning on tolerance of ambiguity and dissonance, scope-sensitivity, bounded claims, and self-criticism may generate predictions that have proven better endowed to withstand the test of time. To the extent that these approaches avoided False Alarms of proliferation cascades, they already bring an epistemic edge to the table. The list of hypotheses under this rubric is diverse and more extensively discussed in Solingen (1994a2018a). In this brief essay, I confine myself to an argument I developed in International Security (1994a), later elaborated in Nuclear Logics (Solingen, 1994a1994b2007). An influential meta-study on failed proliferation chains by Potter and Mukhatzhanova (2008) wielded it as an example that obviated over-predicted cascades. Another study (Sil & Katzenstein, 2010) considered Nuclear Logics' core argument to have been the most undertheorized in this field hitherto as well as an analytically eclectic—yet clearly formulated—framework for estimating nuclear scenarios.

At its core, this framework highlighted that conceptions of security threats were not simple derivatives of abstract, elusive balances of power but were, instead, highly influenced by domestic models of political survival. These models hinged on competing orientations to the global political economy and offered important clues for estimating nuclear choices since the inception of the Nonproliferation Treaty in 1968. Internationalizing models were predicted to lower the likelihood of nuclear weapons' acquisition based on identified causal mechanisms upholding that relationship. Indeed, for over 50 years every decision to renounce nuclear weapons by states that had previously entertained them was nested in broader shifts toward internationalizing models. By contrast, most defiant nuclear courses since 1968 unfolded under inward-looking models hostile to integration in the global political economy. This pattern found support across different regional security contexts and diverse associations with hegemons and alliances. That it does so in a theoretically unfriendly terrain is especially suggestive; nuclear choices are arguably a “least likely” arena for corroborating the explanatory and predictive heft of domestic political economy models. And yet, despite the regularities the approach uncovered, it had been omitted from the canonical causal repertoire. That omission led to an overestimation of other presumed causal variables, especially neorealist ones.

Models of political survival explain both synchronic variation in nuclear preferences across states and overtime variation within the same state; varying state compliance with nonproliferation commitments; varying readings of security dilemmas as more (or less) intractable; variance in ranking alliances higher than self-reliance or vice versa; variance in relative receptivity to external sanctions and inducements; why and when external coercion and inducements may be effective; and why nuclear ambitions were renounced where one might have expected them. And yet, as Sil and Katzenstein note, domestic models were not portrayed as a holy grail that displaces other perspectives; the title “Nuclear Logics”—in the plural—made clear that, while making a compelling case, this argument is not the only game in town. Sil and Katzenstein deem it a pragmatic, self-conscious effort to avoid the trap of becoming so deeply embedded in a single paradigm that makes it impossible to “look at the world with fresh eyes.” Instead, the proposed models provide a useful prism that helps weigh and re-order the relative relevance of other drivers, including structural power, interests, norms, and institutions. The models refract, interpret, and filter external stimuli, offering a nimble analytical category to accommodate the reality of multiple causation. The very definition of security is endogenous to these models rather than an independent variable, as neorealism would have it.

Furthermore, the framework identified important caveats and scope conditions, making the association between models and nuclear choices neither deterministic nor inevitable but probabilistic and eminently falsifiable. One temporal scope condition was that the post-NPT “world-time” or “second nuclear age” posed different systemic constraints than those preceding it and possibly superseding it. Temporal sequencing also matters: nuclear reversals might be much harder when nuclear weapons acquisition precedes the inception of internationalizing models (e.g., China, India, Israel). Abandoning nuclear weapons once they already exist is more costly politically than ending a program before fruition, as prospect theory would submit. Another scope condition stipulated that the relative incidence of internationalizing versus inward-looking models at the regional level would inhibit or exacerbate domestic preferences regarding nuclear weapons in either direction. The framework also specified that the choice for or against alliances (which might/might not substitute for an indigenous deterrent) was also endogenous to domestic models. Sensitive to the fact that hegemony has its limits, this take is in notable agreement with Waltz's (1981) who rightfully argued that “in the past half-century, no country has been able to prevent other countries from going nuclear if they were determined to do so.” But this assertion evokes, once again, a conundrum for neorealist logic: Why were most countries not determined to do so in the first place in a world of anarchy, insecurity, and zero-sumness?

Political survival models are a dynamic category, entailing no linear or irreversible trajectory in either direction. Its predictive scenarios specified the logical conditions under which scenarios might obtain, the kind of evidence that would question or validate expectations, and the outcomes that would corroborate or falsify the theory. Even where past predictive performance over a relatively extended temporal range may have been reassuring, much to our dismay social theories don't typically work for eternity and may be less useful henceforth. Tetlock et al. acknowledge that easy questions posed during a placid period of history (slow-motion variables with low base rates of change) may help the case for Meliorism and long-range predictability. This suggests that the world-time under which a predictive study is conducted (e.g., the heart of the Cold War vs. the zenith of globalization or “end of history”) may affect aggregate forecasts by experts and nonexperts alike. Net predictability hinges not only on the skill or bias of forecasters but also on historical world-time. Alas, the contemporary geopolitical landscape may alter the relative stability of the last 30–40 years. Global and domestic shocks have rendered too many political, economic, technological, and other variables highly uncertain. Russia's attack on Ukraine compounded those shocks inducing nearly chaotic perturbation of significant relevance to nuclear futures. Ukraine had renounced the nuclear weapons it possessed in exchange of security guarantees from major powers including Russia (another anomaly for neorealism?). Putin proceeded to invade Ukraine in 2014 and 2022 and shower nuclear threats on several targets in and beyond Ukraine. Finally, a putative “third nuclear age” driven by artificial intelligence ambitions might return the “cascade” scenario forecasted by President Kennedy and so many others since the 1960s. But in line with the cautionary advice in Tetlock et al., one must also consider the distinct possibility that the emerging world time might retain some of the basic underlying conditions that obviated cascades in the past. Path dependence can persist. It may be premature to proclaim a wholesale Zeitenwende in nuclear forecasting. Even so, discontinuities and inefficient history (March & Olsen, 1998) could burden longer-range predictions under the current geopolitical juncture, pregnant with the highest levels of uncertainty in decades.

An enduring allegiance to failed epistemologies and ontologies is a sure path to fuel Radical Skeptics' convictions. Similar errors stemming from reductionist conceptualization have led to repeated falsified predictions of NATO's demise for over 70 years and much more. To be sure, neorealism is not the only source of prediction error. A related approach associated with technological determinism also exhibits a substantial number of “most likely cases” that renounced nuclear weapons and “least likely cases” that pursued them (Miller, 2017). As Lewis (2016) argued, whether or not states decide not to acquire nuclear weapons has often far more to do with restraint than with technological barriers, given a 65-year-old technology. As the sheer size of failed predictions became evident, new studies pledging neorealist roots sought to rectify some of the noted deficiencies. In so doing, that work departs from first neorealist principles in several ways: it suddenly endows alliances with colossal analytical heft and attaches a large number of contingencies that throw “Occam razor” out the window (Debs & Monteiro, 2016). That is a commendable step that could enhance the potential for “adversarial collaborations” and improved predictions. Retaining other first (neorealist) principles, however, may also retain logical inconsistency. A consistent focus on the logic of anarchy trumps the idea that states can substitute self-help for external protection. Furthermore, continued reliance on fuzzy, elastic, and highly subjective definitions of balance of power, self-help, insecurity, and power itself make predictions even more elusive and possibly unfalsifiable. Scenarios hinging on external threats—not a figment of neorealist imagination—could do better when considering the domestic political landscapes that heighten or dampen pressures to respond to threats with nuclear weapons' acquisition. Important work along the lines of classical and neoclassical realism (Wohlforth, 1993) does just that.

Adversarial collaborations proposed by Tetlock et al. would have to overcome deep cleavages in this field of inquiry, including methodological ones, that may have hindered progress hitherto. Such collaborations could, however, facilitate the crafting of “coherence hypotheses” that bear on the connections between the empirical accuracy of forecasts and the logical rigor with which forecasters make cumulative-risk judgments. “Viewpoint-variable” hypotheses can consider systematic bias stemming from the connections among ideology, forecasts, and forecasting accuracy. Other rules of thumb for converging on adversarial collaborations include greater attention to complex systemic effects, replacing analytically impoverished and grossly deficient—if parsimonious—forecasts. Hypotheses must be cast in falsifiable terms, with greater precision and better specification of threshold and boundary conditions; avoid circularity and ex-post-facto rationalizations; stipulate the kind of evidence that would challenge or corroborate their expectations; assess findings against competing theoretical claims; consider ways to discover, dissect, and assess indirect causal pathways, even if they are more difficult to work with; and devote attention to temporality and world time, or historical context. Above all, heightened tolerance for fallibility—especially for longer haul predictions—will remain forecasting's best friend, all the more so under current conditions of intensive and extensive domestic and systemic geopolitical uncertainty.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
7.00
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
期刊最新文献
Issue Information Issue Information Simplification errors in predictive models Don't push the wrong button. The concept of microperspective in futures research Science fiction in military planning—Case allied command transformation and visions of warfare 2036
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1