绘画艺术的审美属性:主观还是客观?

D. Pećnjak
{"title":"绘画艺术的审美属性:主观还是客观?","authors":"D. Pećnjak","doi":"10.30958/AJHA.6-1-4","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"entities, many other kinds of art, and even perhaps performances of abstract artworks, certainly have aesthetic properties. Conceiving of Aesthetic Properties A description of how aesthetic properties are conceived follows, through which it will be clear that there can be a full description of \"how matters are\" (concerning aesthetic properties) without anyone being able to definitely say whether aesthetic properties are subjective or objective. Thus, perhaps it does not matter, or, an answer may be that aesthetic properties have both subjective and objective aspects, which are perhaps even inseparable, at the same time.13 Let us take an example of a certain property which obviously is an aesthetic property. Certainly beauty seems to be par exellence an example of a property which is an aesthetic property, regardless of what it may truly be in fact.14 Besides beauty, which first comes to mind as an aesthetic property, when we speak about art and artworks, examples of other aesthetic properties are balance, symmetry, 10. Jerrold Levinson, Music, Art and Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 63-88, 215-263. 11. Currie, An Ontology of Art. 12. David Davies, Art as Performance (Malden: Blackwell, 2004). 13. Perhaps we may say that \"aesthetic\" properties supervene at the same time, both, on mental and non-mental facts or properties. We can say, perhaps, when certain facts, both mentally and non-mentally obtain, then we have an aesthetic property realized. But I shall not pursue supervenience theory of aesthetic properties in any form here. About supervenience in artworks see for example Levinson, ''Aesthetic Supervenience.'' 14. For various theories of beauty see, for example, St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, trans. Fathers of the English Dominican Province (Benziger 1947), 33, 270; Immanuel Kant, Kritika moći suđenja (Critique of Judgement) trans. Viktor Sonnenfeld (Naprijed: Zagreb, 1976), 45-50; Nick Zangwill, The Metaphysics of Beauty (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University, 2001). Vol. 6, No. 1 Pećnjak: Aesthetic Properties of the Art of Painting... 74 elegance, gracefulness, and unity.15 Of course, there are still other valuable aesthetic properties. Each of these properties may pose a problem for itself – it can be asked what it is in fact and what it is in relation to other aesthetic properties. There is no need to analyze in detail the specificity of each aesthetic property and various possible specific realizations of each property. On the other hand, of course, it will be necessary to say something about some property, but it is not necessary to go into depth for each property. The primary aim of this text is to examine some basics concerning relations of various aesthetic properties. In doing this, by necessity we must also examine and consider the relations aesthetic properties have to other properties which are not aesthetic. There are two ways of examining: top-down and bottom-up. It may be, for example, stipulated that beauty is the highest aesthetic property an artwork may have, and we may struggle to see in a downward way what (stipulated) beauty consists of. We could also take ordinary properties of art objects qua objects like any other object in our world and try to see how these properties build up or are put together to embrace or constitute properties of the kind we call \"aesthetic\" properties. Of course, both ways, if possible, should come to the same conclusion, especially if there is a unique construction of the relations of ordinary properties and \"aesthetic\" properties. Here, \"unique\" should not be taken literally, meaning \"only one\" or \"just a small number,\" but only logically or explanatory – that there can be a coherent way to explain and relate various kinds of properties as simply as possible. This way can be even generic in the sense that it could allow aesthetic properties, or at least some of them, to be realized in a multitude of ways. This is a potential advantage of such an explanation, because many different artworks are considered beautiful. Therefore, it seems that beauty can be achieved, concerning individual artworks, in various ways, but something seems to be characteristic and shared between all those individual manifestations. If explanation should be generic, then some kind of underlying structure of achieving beauty should be common, and that structure should have a generic capability that would enable a multitude of individual concrete paths to achieving beauty (or any other aesthetic property). It should also to be such that we can demarcate those structures or entities which are beautiful from those which are not. It may be said for now provisionally, that beauty would be structure in the structure. That generic capability should be in 15. As examples for various approaches to aesthetic properties, see Frank Sibley, ''Aesthetic Concepts,'' in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art, ed. Peter Lamarque and Stein Haugom Olsen (Malden: Blackwell, 2004), 127-141; Kendall L. Walton, \"Categories of Art,\" in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art, ed. Peter Lamarque and Stein Haugom Olsen (Malden: Blackwell, 2004), 142-157; Robert Stecker, Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art (Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, 2010), 65-92; Peter Lamarque, \"Aesthetic Empiricism,\" in Work and Object, ed. Peter Lamarque (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), 122-138. Athens Journal of Humanities and Arts January 2019 75 fact something like a schema and should have an ability to generate certain aesthetic properties when appropriately filled with its elements. From the above, it can be provisionally concluded that the beauty of an artwork emerges from its having some other aesthetic properties laid out, combined and composed in a certain way. This leads to thinking that, if true, among other relations, there is a certain hierarchy of aesthetic properties. Again, if this is true, then it implies that there are \"higher-order\" aesthetic properties and more basic aesthetic properties. Further, some more basic aesthetic properties depend on certain arrangements of various non-aesthetic properties, and perhaps, not only on them, but also on psychological states and processes of experiences of artworks as well. By the hierarchy of aesthetic properties, we mean in ontological terms and not in terms of value. Taking painting as an example, a theory will be created about aesthetic properties considering this kind of art, but it seems that this could be extended, with necessary adjustments, to other kinds of art as well. If not, then at least it is applicable to painting, thus fulfilling the aim of this text, which is to show that, at least for the art of painting, there can be a full description of how aesthetic properties are realized without saying definitively whether they are subjective or objective. There can be, in fact, a case which enables us to say that aesthetic properties are complex composite entities, so their realization depends on simultaneously present subjectivity and objectivity. Architectonic of Aesthetic Properties That being settled, some kind of architectonic of properties for artworks in the domain of painting can be made. Using a bottom-up approach, the description begins with a basic fundamental layer that contains properties which are certainly and unproblematically non-aesthetic, i.e. they are some common ordinary properties of objects. First, there is some physical foundation on which the paint will be laid. It is usually a wooden plate, canvas or a wall (in the case of frescoes). There can be other kinds of foundations as well. Then, patches of colors are laid on the prepared foundation; some of the patches are so thin that we can consider them as lines (colored). It could be the case that basic drawing, as an elementary scheme, precedes putting the patches of colors. Colors can be, and often are, mixed and placed in layers in order to achieve various nuances, brightness and effects. After enough color is put down on a foundation, the painting is finished and it is let to dry. Of course, some amendments can be made afterwards but nothing essentially new happens. After the painting has dried, it can be shown to the public. What happens now, when the public is looking at the painting? Certain amount of photons fall on the painting; some wavelengths are absorbed, some Vol. 6, No. 1 Pećnjak: Aesthetic Properties of the Art of Painting... 76 reflected, and those that are reflected travel under normal conditions to the eye of the beholder.16 Light is refracted through the lens, falls on the retina and is transformed into the electrical impulses that travel through optical nerves further to the brain and, finally, cause states and processes in the various visual areas of the brain. We should add, because we are dualists, that these are a further cause of some non-physical mental states and processes, but nothing depends on this further claim; nothing we shall say here about hierarchy and the architectonic of properties, both aesthetic and non-aesthetic, depends on the dualist picture of the mind. Particular instantaneous sensations are integrated into a percept so they all combine to give a structured visual perception (of the painting). Ultimately, the beholder has a perceptive experience of the painting. Origin, Properties and Different Layers What are the origins of a painting? Of course, paintings are produced through complex intentional processes, using various physical processes, which consist in many subprocesses. Broadly speaking, these count as part of the history of production. Author(s), or in our case painters, use their various skills, knowledge and imagination in this intentional production of a work. It sounds simple, but it is not – indeed, there are rather complex relationships between these factors. Thus, it seems that there are many states and processes, both physical and psychological, of different levels and of different ontological characterizations","PeriodicalId":325459,"journal":{"name":"ATHENS JOURNAL OF HUMANITIES & ARTS","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Aesthetic Properties of the Art of Painting: Subjective or Objective?\",\"authors\":\"D. Pećnjak\",\"doi\":\"10.30958/AJHA.6-1-4\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"entities, many other kinds of art, and even perhaps performances of abstract artworks, certainly have aesthetic properties. Conceiving of Aesthetic Properties A description of how aesthetic properties are conceived follows, through which it will be clear that there can be a full description of \\\"how matters are\\\" (concerning aesthetic properties) without anyone being able to definitely say whether aesthetic properties are subjective or objective. Thus, perhaps it does not matter, or, an answer may be that aesthetic properties have both subjective and objective aspects, which are perhaps even inseparable, at the same time.13 Let us take an example of a certain property which obviously is an aesthetic property. Certainly beauty seems to be par exellence an example of a property which is an aesthetic property, regardless of what it may truly be in fact.14 Besides beauty, which first comes to mind as an aesthetic property, when we speak about art and artworks, examples of other aesthetic properties are balance, symmetry, 10. Jerrold Levinson, Music, Art and Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 63-88, 215-263. 11. Currie, An Ontology of Art. 12. David Davies, Art as Performance (Malden: Blackwell, 2004). 13. Perhaps we may say that \\\"aesthetic\\\" properties supervene at the same time, both, on mental and non-mental facts or properties. We can say, perhaps, when certain facts, both mentally and non-mentally obtain, then we have an aesthetic property realized. But I shall not pursue supervenience theory of aesthetic properties in any form here. About supervenience in artworks see for example Levinson, ''Aesthetic Supervenience.'' 14. For various theories of beauty see, for example, St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, trans. Fathers of the English Dominican Province (Benziger 1947), 33, 270; Immanuel Kant, Kritika moći suđenja (Critique of Judgement) trans. Viktor Sonnenfeld (Naprijed: Zagreb, 1976), 45-50; Nick Zangwill, The Metaphysics of Beauty (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University, 2001). Vol. 6, No. 1 Pećnjak: Aesthetic Properties of the Art of Painting... 74 elegance, gracefulness, and unity.15 Of course, there are still other valuable aesthetic properties. Each of these properties may pose a problem for itself – it can be asked what it is in fact and what it is in relation to other aesthetic properties. There is no need to analyze in detail the specificity of each aesthetic property and various possible specific realizations of each property. On the other hand, of course, it will be necessary to say something about some property, but it is not necessary to go into depth for each property. The primary aim of this text is to examine some basics concerning relations of various aesthetic properties. In doing this, by necessity we must also examine and consider the relations aesthetic properties have to other properties which are not aesthetic. There are two ways of examining: top-down and bottom-up. It may be, for example, stipulated that beauty is the highest aesthetic property an artwork may have, and we may struggle to see in a downward way what (stipulated) beauty consists of. We could also take ordinary properties of art objects qua objects like any other object in our world and try to see how these properties build up or are put together to embrace or constitute properties of the kind we call \\\"aesthetic\\\" properties. Of course, both ways, if possible, should come to the same conclusion, especially if there is a unique construction of the relations of ordinary properties and \\\"aesthetic\\\" properties. Here, \\\"unique\\\" should not be taken literally, meaning \\\"only one\\\" or \\\"just a small number,\\\" but only logically or explanatory – that there can be a coherent way to explain and relate various kinds of properties as simply as possible. This way can be even generic in the sense that it could allow aesthetic properties, or at least some of them, to be realized in a multitude of ways. This is a potential advantage of such an explanation, because many different artworks are considered beautiful. Therefore, it seems that beauty can be achieved, concerning individual artworks, in various ways, but something seems to be characteristic and shared between all those individual manifestations. If explanation should be generic, then some kind of underlying structure of achieving beauty should be common, and that structure should have a generic capability that would enable a multitude of individual concrete paths to achieving beauty (or any other aesthetic property). It should also to be such that we can demarcate those structures or entities which are beautiful from those which are not. It may be said for now provisionally, that beauty would be structure in the structure. That generic capability should be in 15. As examples for various approaches to aesthetic properties, see Frank Sibley, ''Aesthetic Concepts,'' in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art, ed. Peter Lamarque and Stein Haugom Olsen (Malden: Blackwell, 2004), 127-141; Kendall L. Walton, \\\"Categories of Art,\\\" in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art, ed. Peter Lamarque and Stein Haugom Olsen (Malden: Blackwell, 2004), 142-157; Robert Stecker, Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art (Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, 2010), 65-92; Peter Lamarque, \\\"Aesthetic Empiricism,\\\" in Work and Object, ed. Peter Lamarque (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), 122-138. Athens Journal of Humanities and Arts January 2019 75 fact something like a schema and should have an ability to generate certain aesthetic properties when appropriately filled with its elements. From the above, it can be provisionally concluded that the beauty of an artwork emerges from its having some other aesthetic properties laid out, combined and composed in a certain way. This leads to thinking that, if true, among other relations, there is a certain hierarchy of aesthetic properties. Again, if this is true, then it implies that there are \\\"higher-order\\\" aesthetic properties and more basic aesthetic properties. Further, some more basic aesthetic properties depend on certain arrangements of various non-aesthetic properties, and perhaps, not only on them, but also on psychological states and processes of experiences of artworks as well. By the hierarchy of aesthetic properties, we mean in ontological terms and not in terms of value. Taking painting as an example, a theory will be created about aesthetic properties considering this kind of art, but it seems that this could be extended, with necessary adjustments, to other kinds of art as well. If not, then at least it is applicable to painting, thus fulfilling the aim of this text, which is to show that, at least for the art of painting, there can be a full description of how aesthetic properties are realized without saying definitively whether they are subjective or objective. There can be, in fact, a case which enables us to say that aesthetic properties are complex composite entities, so their realization depends on simultaneously present subjectivity and objectivity. Architectonic of Aesthetic Properties That being settled, some kind of architectonic of properties for artworks in the domain of painting can be made. Using a bottom-up approach, the description begins with a basic fundamental layer that contains properties which are certainly and unproblematically non-aesthetic, i.e. they are some common ordinary properties of objects. First, there is some physical foundation on which the paint will be laid. It is usually a wooden plate, canvas or a wall (in the case of frescoes). There can be other kinds of foundations as well. Then, patches of colors are laid on the prepared foundation; some of the patches are so thin that we can consider them as lines (colored). It could be the case that basic drawing, as an elementary scheme, precedes putting the patches of colors. Colors can be, and often are, mixed and placed in layers in order to achieve various nuances, brightness and effects. After enough color is put down on a foundation, the painting is finished and it is let to dry. Of course, some amendments can be made afterwards but nothing essentially new happens. After the painting has dried, it can be shown to the public. What happens now, when the public is looking at the painting? Certain amount of photons fall on the painting; some wavelengths are absorbed, some Vol. 6, No. 1 Pećnjak: Aesthetic Properties of the Art of Painting... 76 reflected, and those that are reflected travel under normal conditions to the eye of the beholder.16 Light is refracted through the lens, falls on the retina and is transformed into the electrical impulses that travel through optical nerves further to the brain and, finally, cause states and processes in the various visual areas of the brain. We should add, because we are dualists, that these are a further cause of some non-physical mental states and processes, but nothing depends on this further claim; nothing we shall say here about hierarchy and the architectonic of properties, both aesthetic and non-aesthetic, depends on the dualist picture of the mind. Particular instantaneous sensations are integrated into a percept so they all combine to give a structured visual perception (of the painting). Ultimately, the beholder has a perceptive experience of the painting. Origin, Properties and Different Layers What are the origins of a painting? Of course, paintings are produced through complex intentional processes, using various physical processes, which consist in many subprocesses. Broadly speaking, these count as part of the history of production. Author(s), or in our case painters, use their various skills, knowledge and imagination in this intentional production of a work. It sounds simple, but it is not – indeed, there are rather complex relationships between these factors. Thus, it seems that there are many states and processes, both physical and psychological, of different levels and of different ontological characterizations\",\"PeriodicalId\":325459,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"ATHENS JOURNAL OF HUMANITIES & ARTS\",\"volume\":\"1 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2019-01-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"ATHENS JOURNAL OF HUMANITIES & ARTS\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.30958/AJHA.6-1-4\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"ATHENS JOURNAL OF HUMANITIES & ARTS","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.30958/AJHA.6-1-4","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

Peter Lamarque和Stein Haugom Olsen (Malden: Blackwell, 2004), 127-141;肯德尔·l·沃尔顿,《艺术的类别》,《美学与艺术哲学》,彼得·拉马克和斯坦·豪戈姆·奥尔森主编(马尔登:布莱克威尔出版社,2004年),142-157页;罗伯特·斯特克,《美学与艺术哲学》(兰哈姆:罗曼和利特菲尔德出版社,2010),第65-92页;彼得·拉马克,“美学经验主义,”在工作和对象,编辑。彼得·拉马克(牛津:牛津大学出版社,2010),122-138。雅典人文与艺术杂志2019年1月75事实有点像图式,当适当地填充其元素时,应该能够产生某些美学属性。综上所述,我们可以暂时得出结论,一件艺术品的美来自于它以某种方式布局、组合和组合了一些其他的美学属性。这让我们想到,如果这是真的,在其他关系中,审美属性有一定的等级。再一次,如果这是真的,那么它就意味着存在“高阶”美学属性和更基本的美学属性。此外,一些更基本的审美属性取决于各种非审美属性的某种安排,也许,不仅取决于它们,还取决于艺术作品的心理状态和体验过程。所谓审美属性的层次,我们指的是本体论上的,而不是价值上的。以绘画为例,考虑到这种艺术,就会产生一种关于美学属性的理论,但似乎也可以通过必要的调整来扩展到其他艺术。如果不能,那么它至少适用于绘画,从而实现了本文的目的,即至少对于绘画艺术,可以对审美特性如何实现进行完整的描述,而不必明确地说它们是主观的还是客观的。事实上,我们可以说,审美属性是复杂的复合实体,因此它们的实现同时依赖于当下的主观性和客观性。解决了这个问题,就可以为绘画领域的艺术作品创造某种结构属性。使用自底向上的方法,描述从一个基本的基础层开始,其中包含肯定且毫无疑问是非美学的属性,即它们是物体的一些常见属性。首先,有一些物理基础,油漆将在其上铺设。它通常是一个木板,帆布或墙壁(在壁画的情况下)。也可以有其他类型的基金会。然后,在准备好的基础上铺设色块;有些斑块非常薄,我们可以将它们视为线(彩色)。可能是这样的情况,基本的绘图,作为一个基本的方案,在添加色块之前。为了达到各种细微差别、亮度和效果,颜色可以并且经常被混合和分层放置。在底漆上涂上足够的颜色后,画就完成了,然后让它晾干。当然,之后可以做一些修改,但本质上没有什么新的事情发生。这幅画晾干后,就可以向公众展出了。当公众看到这幅画的时候,会发生什么?一定量的光子落在画上;一些波长被吸收,一些第6卷,第1号Pećnjak:绘画艺术的美学特性……被反射的光在正常情况下到达观看者的眼睛光线通过晶状体折射,落在视网膜上,并转化为电脉冲,通过视神经进一步传递到大脑,最终在大脑的各个视觉区域引起状态和过程。我们应该补充一点,因为我们是二元论者,它们是一些非物质精神状态和过程的进一步原因,但没有任何东西取决于这个进一步的主张;在这里,我们不会说任何关于层次和美学和非美学性质的结构,取决于心灵的二元论图景。特定的瞬时感觉被整合到一个感知中,所以它们都结合在一起,给人一种结构化的视觉感知(绘画)。最终,观者对画作有了一种感性的体验。一幅画的起源是什么?当然,绘画是通过复杂的有意过程产生的,使用各种物理过程,这些物理过程包含许多子过程。一般来说,这些都是生产历史的一部分。作者,或在我们的情况下画家,使用他们的各种技能,知识和想象力在这种有意生产的工作。这听起来很简单,但事实并非如此——事实上,这些因素之间存在相当复杂的关系。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Aesthetic Properties of the Art of Painting: Subjective or Objective?
entities, many other kinds of art, and even perhaps performances of abstract artworks, certainly have aesthetic properties. Conceiving of Aesthetic Properties A description of how aesthetic properties are conceived follows, through which it will be clear that there can be a full description of "how matters are" (concerning aesthetic properties) without anyone being able to definitely say whether aesthetic properties are subjective or objective. Thus, perhaps it does not matter, or, an answer may be that aesthetic properties have both subjective and objective aspects, which are perhaps even inseparable, at the same time.13 Let us take an example of a certain property which obviously is an aesthetic property. Certainly beauty seems to be par exellence an example of a property which is an aesthetic property, regardless of what it may truly be in fact.14 Besides beauty, which first comes to mind as an aesthetic property, when we speak about art and artworks, examples of other aesthetic properties are balance, symmetry, 10. Jerrold Levinson, Music, Art and Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 63-88, 215-263. 11. Currie, An Ontology of Art. 12. David Davies, Art as Performance (Malden: Blackwell, 2004). 13. Perhaps we may say that "aesthetic" properties supervene at the same time, both, on mental and non-mental facts or properties. We can say, perhaps, when certain facts, both mentally and non-mentally obtain, then we have an aesthetic property realized. But I shall not pursue supervenience theory of aesthetic properties in any form here. About supervenience in artworks see for example Levinson, ''Aesthetic Supervenience.'' 14. For various theories of beauty see, for example, St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, trans. Fathers of the English Dominican Province (Benziger 1947), 33, 270; Immanuel Kant, Kritika moći suđenja (Critique of Judgement) trans. Viktor Sonnenfeld (Naprijed: Zagreb, 1976), 45-50; Nick Zangwill, The Metaphysics of Beauty (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University, 2001). Vol. 6, No. 1 Pećnjak: Aesthetic Properties of the Art of Painting... 74 elegance, gracefulness, and unity.15 Of course, there are still other valuable aesthetic properties. Each of these properties may pose a problem for itself – it can be asked what it is in fact and what it is in relation to other aesthetic properties. There is no need to analyze in detail the specificity of each aesthetic property and various possible specific realizations of each property. On the other hand, of course, it will be necessary to say something about some property, but it is not necessary to go into depth for each property. The primary aim of this text is to examine some basics concerning relations of various aesthetic properties. In doing this, by necessity we must also examine and consider the relations aesthetic properties have to other properties which are not aesthetic. There are two ways of examining: top-down and bottom-up. It may be, for example, stipulated that beauty is the highest aesthetic property an artwork may have, and we may struggle to see in a downward way what (stipulated) beauty consists of. We could also take ordinary properties of art objects qua objects like any other object in our world and try to see how these properties build up or are put together to embrace or constitute properties of the kind we call "aesthetic" properties. Of course, both ways, if possible, should come to the same conclusion, especially if there is a unique construction of the relations of ordinary properties and "aesthetic" properties. Here, "unique" should not be taken literally, meaning "only one" or "just a small number," but only logically or explanatory – that there can be a coherent way to explain and relate various kinds of properties as simply as possible. This way can be even generic in the sense that it could allow aesthetic properties, or at least some of them, to be realized in a multitude of ways. This is a potential advantage of such an explanation, because many different artworks are considered beautiful. Therefore, it seems that beauty can be achieved, concerning individual artworks, in various ways, but something seems to be characteristic and shared between all those individual manifestations. If explanation should be generic, then some kind of underlying structure of achieving beauty should be common, and that structure should have a generic capability that would enable a multitude of individual concrete paths to achieving beauty (or any other aesthetic property). It should also to be such that we can demarcate those structures or entities which are beautiful from those which are not. It may be said for now provisionally, that beauty would be structure in the structure. That generic capability should be in 15. As examples for various approaches to aesthetic properties, see Frank Sibley, ''Aesthetic Concepts,'' in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art, ed. Peter Lamarque and Stein Haugom Olsen (Malden: Blackwell, 2004), 127-141; Kendall L. Walton, "Categories of Art," in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art, ed. Peter Lamarque and Stein Haugom Olsen (Malden: Blackwell, 2004), 142-157; Robert Stecker, Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art (Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, 2010), 65-92; Peter Lamarque, "Aesthetic Empiricism," in Work and Object, ed. Peter Lamarque (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), 122-138. Athens Journal of Humanities and Arts January 2019 75 fact something like a schema and should have an ability to generate certain aesthetic properties when appropriately filled with its elements. From the above, it can be provisionally concluded that the beauty of an artwork emerges from its having some other aesthetic properties laid out, combined and composed in a certain way. This leads to thinking that, if true, among other relations, there is a certain hierarchy of aesthetic properties. Again, if this is true, then it implies that there are "higher-order" aesthetic properties and more basic aesthetic properties. Further, some more basic aesthetic properties depend on certain arrangements of various non-aesthetic properties, and perhaps, not only on them, but also on psychological states and processes of experiences of artworks as well. By the hierarchy of aesthetic properties, we mean in ontological terms and not in terms of value. Taking painting as an example, a theory will be created about aesthetic properties considering this kind of art, but it seems that this could be extended, with necessary adjustments, to other kinds of art as well. If not, then at least it is applicable to painting, thus fulfilling the aim of this text, which is to show that, at least for the art of painting, there can be a full description of how aesthetic properties are realized without saying definitively whether they are subjective or objective. There can be, in fact, a case which enables us to say that aesthetic properties are complex composite entities, so their realization depends on simultaneously present subjectivity and objectivity. Architectonic of Aesthetic Properties That being settled, some kind of architectonic of properties for artworks in the domain of painting can be made. Using a bottom-up approach, the description begins with a basic fundamental layer that contains properties which are certainly and unproblematically non-aesthetic, i.e. they are some common ordinary properties of objects. First, there is some physical foundation on which the paint will be laid. It is usually a wooden plate, canvas or a wall (in the case of frescoes). There can be other kinds of foundations as well. Then, patches of colors are laid on the prepared foundation; some of the patches are so thin that we can consider them as lines (colored). It could be the case that basic drawing, as an elementary scheme, precedes putting the patches of colors. Colors can be, and often are, mixed and placed in layers in order to achieve various nuances, brightness and effects. After enough color is put down on a foundation, the painting is finished and it is let to dry. Of course, some amendments can be made afterwards but nothing essentially new happens. After the painting has dried, it can be shown to the public. What happens now, when the public is looking at the painting? Certain amount of photons fall on the painting; some wavelengths are absorbed, some Vol. 6, No. 1 Pećnjak: Aesthetic Properties of the Art of Painting... 76 reflected, and those that are reflected travel under normal conditions to the eye of the beholder.16 Light is refracted through the lens, falls on the retina and is transformed into the electrical impulses that travel through optical nerves further to the brain and, finally, cause states and processes in the various visual areas of the brain. We should add, because we are dualists, that these are a further cause of some non-physical mental states and processes, but nothing depends on this further claim; nothing we shall say here about hierarchy and the architectonic of properties, both aesthetic and non-aesthetic, depends on the dualist picture of the mind. Particular instantaneous sensations are integrated into a percept so they all combine to give a structured visual perception (of the painting). Ultimately, the beholder has a perceptive experience of the painting. Origin, Properties and Different Layers What are the origins of a painting? Of course, paintings are produced through complex intentional processes, using various physical processes, which consist in many subprocesses. Broadly speaking, these count as part of the history of production. Author(s), or in our case painters, use their various skills, knowledge and imagination in this intentional production of a work. It sounds simple, but it is not – indeed, there are rather complex relationships between these factors. Thus, it seems that there are many states and processes, both physical and psychological, of different levels and of different ontological characterizations
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
期刊最新文献
Evaluating the Emotional Impact of Environmental Artworks Using Q Methodology Research on Arts and Humanities: A Selected Survey and Works Presented at ATINER’s Annual Humanities and Arts Conferences Current Insights into the Evolution of Cameroon English: The Contribution of the ‘Anglophone Problem’ Some Remarks on the Five Criteria of Democracy Gorgo: Sparta’s Woman of Autonomy, Authority, and Agency
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1