超越芭丝谢芭:通过实用主义伦理管理伦理氛围

Joseph E. Long
{"title":"超越芭丝谢芭:通过实用主义伦理管理伦理氛围","authors":"Joseph E. Long","doi":"10.22543/0733.102.1194","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"This paper explores the puzzling nature of leader behavior in order to understand the conditions that encourage unethical decision-making. Building on the extant literature of pragmatic ethics, I explore how leaders can increase the quality of ethical decision-making within their organizations by understanding the incentives of rational choice. I have developed a rational choice-based ethical decision-making model to understand the incentives behind ethical leader behavior and find that ethical behavior is likely to be rational as long as audience costs remain higher than the savings benefits incurred by unethical behavior. I conclude with analysis of how the ethical rational model compares to other prominent theories that explain unethical leader behavior and propose that the probable outcomes derived from my model better explain bad leader behavior than competing control-oriented models. The results of this inquiry underscore the transactional and practical characteristics of leadership as a tool to help leaders manage their ethical climates, improve business practices and management policies, understand the nature of individual incentives, and capture transactional components of leader behavior. Introduction Ethical literature provides broad considerations for guiding individual and social interaction and enhancing the general welfare of society. However, despite the maturity of the scholarly ethical discipline, stories of leaders who exhibit unethical behavior are legion. Such leaders exhibit such poor behavior for seemingly no logical reason; as prominent business, government, and military leaders, they are all highly intelligent, well educated, economically well off, and professionally accepted at the highest levels. These leaders appear to have everything going for them, yet risk ethical misbehavior for relatively modest gains. This observation presents an interesting puzzle: why do seemingly advantaged leaders engage in poor ethical behavior when they already have such an advantage over others? Moreover, what can leaders do to avoid such behavior? In answering this puzzle, several explanations come to mind. Theories involving issues of greed, competition, relative power differences at top echelons of responsibility, and mental illness could offer simple explanations for potentially complicated behavior. However, scholars offer other explanations that are more helpful but that remain altogether unsatisfying. Park, Westphal, and Stern (2011) find that flattering comments from subordinates to CEOs are causal in producing leader overconfidence and biased decisionmaking (Park, Westphal, & Stern, 2011). Park et al. find that high social status in leaders exposes them to increasing levels of flattering comments and behavior (p. 261) which JOSEPH E. LONG CHARLESTON, WEST VIRGINIA, US inflates a leader’s sense of effective personal judgment and decreases a leader’s ability to recognize poor performance or challenge ineffective strategies (p. 267). Park et al.’s research suggests that leader behavior evolves over time so that leaders expect unwavering conformity and fall victim to “believing their own press” where they lose the ability to identify personal and performance-oriented shortcomings (p. 259). Other scholars offer a simpler explanation for unethical leader behavior related to competition and relative power differentials at top levels of leadership. Ludwig and Longenecker (1993) noted that “ethical violations by upper managers are the by-product of success, not of competitive pressures” which makes the aforementioned puzzle even more intriguing (Ludwig & Longenecker, 1993, p. 265). According to the authors, ethical misbehavior evolves as leaders become complacent, gain access to privileged information, increase access to critical resources, and gain the ability to manipulate more favorable outcomes (p. 265). In short, this theory provides an ego-centric approach to understanding bad leader behavior, in contrast to the success-oriented theory proposed by Park et al., to explain unethical leader behavior as involving more than the need to cut corners in an increasingly competitive environment. In the spirit of pragmatic ethics, I am proposing a more parsimonious explanation for leader behavior. As scholars note, pragmatic ethics is about the process of decisionmaking such that “good ethical choices emerge through the use of inquiry” (Johnson, 2015), as well as “giving primacy to habits” which “carry the past into the present” (LaFollette, 2013, p. 402). In understanding pragmatic ethics, a strategic choice model will add to ethical leadership literature and provide a unique explanation for how ethical considerations positively or negatively influence expected leader behavior. The results of this inquiry underscore the transactional and practical characteristics of leadership as a tool to help leaders manage their ethical climates, improve business practices and management policies, understand the nature of individual incentives, and capture transactional components of leader behavior. This paper employs a deep-dive approach to understanding pragmatic ethics to uncover how pragmatic ethical processes give primacy to more strategic ethical decision-making. Furthermore, I employ the expectations of pragmatic ethics as utility variables that impact the strategic nature of ethical decision-making and present a rational choice model to uncover the conditions that incentivize ethical leader choices. Pragmatic Ethics Pragmatic ethics can positively influence strategic decision-making to underscore the fundamental and continuing Deweyan notion that pragmatic ethics remain process-centric, scientifically compatible, logical, and habit-driven (Johnson, 2015; LaFollette, 2013). Furthermore, the literature of pragmatic ethics sufficiently uncovers a relationship between ethical considerations and strategic choices that provide a nuanced understanding of the variables that inform leader choices in ethically-challenging environments. Whitford (2002) challenges rational actor theory and its assumed “paradigmatic privilege” by challenging the “portfolio” assumption that beliefs and desires are sufficient inputs for strategic utility models (Whitford, 2002, p. 327). However, Whitford’s theory takes an overly continuous view of pragmatism where “ends” of one choice become the “means” of the next choice. In countering Whitford’s argument, a strategic choice model would reduce the level of analysis from the systematic to the individual level and take a Bayesian approach to understanding changes in decision-making over time. In pragmatic terms, lessons learned through early leader choices impact the habits of leader choices in later decisions (LaFollette, 2013). Using a business-oriented model, Woiceshyn (2011) examines ethical decision-making through the premise that “unethical decisions harm the decision makers themselves as well as others, whereas ethical decision makers have the opposite effect” (Woiceshyn, 2011, p. 311). The author presents a theory of rational egoism where “reasoning (conscious processing) and intuition (subconscious processing) interact through forming, recalling, and applying moral principles necessary for long-term success in business” (p. 312). Woiceshyn also considers previous studies that found “managers employ the same process when making decisions involving ethics as they do for any long-term decisions affecting their companies” to imply that ethical choices can be more optimal than unethical ones, which supports my research interests in rational ethics (p. 312). Furthermore, Woiceshyn introduces causal factors for leader behavior to include audience costs and the probability of getting caught; this “moral intensity” according to Trevino and Youngblood, can be applied in a strategic choice model (p. 312). In addressing LaFollette’s (2013) habit-forming aspects of pragmatic ethics, Caras and Sandu (2014) argue for the “epistemic and pragmatic need and academic functioning of a model embodied in ethical expertise” (Caras & Sandu, 2014, p. 142). For Caras and Sandu, ethical expertise involves “rigorous training in moral philosophy” as “an imperative condition for an ethics expert, precisely because his role is to provide professional counseling to professionals whose expertise does not involve ethics exclusively” (p. 143). Although Caras and Sandu fail to address the relative utility of expert counsel, they clarify the distinction between performative and pragmatic expertise, which makes a valuable connection between ethical counseling and utility. Ali and Lin (2013) explore pragmatism in voter theory to identify when a rational person would “incur the cost of voting, even when it is improbable that any one of them is pivotal” (Ali & Lin, 2013. p. 73). This gives explanatory power to understanding the potential costs of ethical behavior given inherent inefficiencies in achieving outcomes in intensely competitive environments. Ali and Lin also offer a mathematical explanation for voter behavior and add support for the rational approach by identifying how audience costs and varying probabilities of being caught can impact the expected utility of leader choices. They also imply that increased transparency can influence the above factors and add further explanatory power to a strategic choice model to imply that ethical transparency might also motivate ethical decision-making for a rational actor. Pihlström (2013) investigates religious pragmatism as “a middle path option for those who do not want to give up either their scientific worldview or their possible religious sensibilities” (Pihlström, 2013, p. 27). This concept avoids the scientific implications of my research into rational pragmatism by sidelining the strictness of empirical evidence toward a “richer conception of evidence as something that can be had, or may be lacking, in the 'laboratory of life’“(p. 28). However, the author does suggest ","PeriodicalId":203965,"journal":{"name":"The Journal of Values-Based Leadership","volume":"7 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2017-07-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Beyond Bathsheba: Managing Ethical Climates Through Pragmatic Ethics\",\"authors\":\"Joseph E. Long\",\"doi\":\"10.22543/0733.102.1194\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"This paper explores the puzzling nature of leader behavior in order to understand the conditions that encourage unethical decision-making. Building on the extant literature of pragmatic ethics, I explore how leaders can increase the quality of ethical decision-making within their organizations by understanding the incentives of rational choice. I have developed a rational choice-based ethical decision-making model to understand the incentives behind ethical leader behavior and find that ethical behavior is likely to be rational as long as audience costs remain higher than the savings benefits incurred by unethical behavior. I conclude with analysis of how the ethical rational model compares to other prominent theories that explain unethical leader behavior and propose that the probable outcomes derived from my model better explain bad leader behavior than competing control-oriented models. The results of this inquiry underscore the transactional and practical characteristics of leadership as a tool to help leaders manage their ethical climates, improve business practices and management policies, understand the nature of individual incentives, and capture transactional components of leader behavior. Introduction Ethical literature provides broad considerations for guiding individual and social interaction and enhancing the general welfare of society. However, despite the maturity of the scholarly ethical discipline, stories of leaders who exhibit unethical behavior are legion. Such leaders exhibit such poor behavior for seemingly no logical reason; as prominent business, government, and military leaders, they are all highly intelligent, well educated, economically well off, and professionally accepted at the highest levels. These leaders appear to have everything going for them, yet risk ethical misbehavior for relatively modest gains. This observation presents an interesting puzzle: why do seemingly advantaged leaders engage in poor ethical behavior when they already have such an advantage over others? Moreover, what can leaders do to avoid such behavior? In answering this puzzle, several explanations come to mind. Theories involving issues of greed, competition, relative power differences at top echelons of responsibility, and mental illness could offer simple explanations for potentially complicated behavior. However, scholars offer other explanations that are more helpful but that remain altogether unsatisfying. Park, Westphal, and Stern (2011) find that flattering comments from subordinates to CEOs are causal in producing leader overconfidence and biased decisionmaking (Park, Westphal, & Stern, 2011). Park et al. find that high social status in leaders exposes them to increasing levels of flattering comments and behavior (p. 261) which JOSEPH E. LONG CHARLESTON, WEST VIRGINIA, US inflates a leader’s sense of effective personal judgment and decreases a leader’s ability to recognize poor performance or challenge ineffective strategies (p. 267). Park et al.’s research suggests that leader behavior evolves over time so that leaders expect unwavering conformity and fall victim to “believing their own press” where they lose the ability to identify personal and performance-oriented shortcomings (p. 259). Other scholars offer a simpler explanation for unethical leader behavior related to competition and relative power differentials at top levels of leadership. Ludwig and Longenecker (1993) noted that “ethical violations by upper managers are the by-product of success, not of competitive pressures” which makes the aforementioned puzzle even more intriguing (Ludwig & Longenecker, 1993, p. 265). According to the authors, ethical misbehavior evolves as leaders become complacent, gain access to privileged information, increase access to critical resources, and gain the ability to manipulate more favorable outcomes (p. 265). In short, this theory provides an ego-centric approach to understanding bad leader behavior, in contrast to the success-oriented theory proposed by Park et al., to explain unethical leader behavior as involving more than the need to cut corners in an increasingly competitive environment. In the spirit of pragmatic ethics, I am proposing a more parsimonious explanation for leader behavior. As scholars note, pragmatic ethics is about the process of decisionmaking such that “good ethical choices emerge through the use of inquiry” (Johnson, 2015), as well as “giving primacy to habits” which “carry the past into the present” (LaFollette, 2013, p. 402). In understanding pragmatic ethics, a strategic choice model will add to ethical leadership literature and provide a unique explanation for how ethical considerations positively or negatively influence expected leader behavior. The results of this inquiry underscore the transactional and practical characteristics of leadership as a tool to help leaders manage their ethical climates, improve business practices and management policies, understand the nature of individual incentives, and capture transactional components of leader behavior. This paper employs a deep-dive approach to understanding pragmatic ethics to uncover how pragmatic ethical processes give primacy to more strategic ethical decision-making. Furthermore, I employ the expectations of pragmatic ethics as utility variables that impact the strategic nature of ethical decision-making and present a rational choice model to uncover the conditions that incentivize ethical leader choices. Pragmatic Ethics Pragmatic ethics can positively influence strategic decision-making to underscore the fundamental and continuing Deweyan notion that pragmatic ethics remain process-centric, scientifically compatible, logical, and habit-driven (Johnson, 2015; LaFollette, 2013). Furthermore, the literature of pragmatic ethics sufficiently uncovers a relationship between ethical considerations and strategic choices that provide a nuanced understanding of the variables that inform leader choices in ethically-challenging environments. Whitford (2002) challenges rational actor theory and its assumed “paradigmatic privilege” by challenging the “portfolio” assumption that beliefs and desires are sufficient inputs for strategic utility models (Whitford, 2002, p. 327). However, Whitford’s theory takes an overly continuous view of pragmatism where “ends” of one choice become the “means” of the next choice. In countering Whitford’s argument, a strategic choice model would reduce the level of analysis from the systematic to the individual level and take a Bayesian approach to understanding changes in decision-making over time. In pragmatic terms, lessons learned through early leader choices impact the habits of leader choices in later decisions (LaFollette, 2013). Using a business-oriented model, Woiceshyn (2011) examines ethical decision-making through the premise that “unethical decisions harm the decision makers themselves as well as others, whereas ethical decision makers have the opposite effect” (Woiceshyn, 2011, p. 311). The author presents a theory of rational egoism where “reasoning (conscious processing) and intuition (subconscious processing) interact through forming, recalling, and applying moral principles necessary for long-term success in business” (p. 312). Woiceshyn also considers previous studies that found “managers employ the same process when making decisions involving ethics as they do for any long-term decisions affecting their companies” to imply that ethical choices can be more optimal than unethical ones, which supports my research interests in rational ethics (p. 312). Furthermore, Woiceshyn introduces causal factors for leader behavior to include audience costs and the probability of getting caught; this “moral intensity” according to Trevino and Youngblood, can be applied in a strategic choice model (p. 312). In addressing LaFollette’s (2013) habit-forming aspects of pragmatic ethics, Caras and Sandu (2014) argue for the “epistemic and pragmatic need and academic functioning of a model embodied in ethical expertise” (Caras & Sandu, 2014, p. 142). For Caras and Sandu, ethical expertise involves “rigorous training in moral philosophy” as “an imperative condition for an ethics expert, precisely because his role is to provide professional counseling to professionals whose expertise does not involve ethics exclusively” (p. 143). Although Caras and Sandu fail to address the relative utility of expert counsel, they clarify the distinction between performative and pragmatic expertise, which makes a valuable connection between ethical counseling and utility. Ali and Lin (2013) explore pragmatism in voter theory to identify when a rational person would “incur the cost of voting, even when it is improbable that any one of them is pivotal” (Ali & Lin, 2013. p. 73). This gives explanatory power to understanding the potential costs of ethical behavior given inherent inefficiencies in achieving outcomes in intensely competitive environments. Ali and Lin also offer a mathematical explanation for voter behavior and add support for the rational approach by identifying how audience costs and varying probabilities of being caught can impact the expected utility of leader choices. They also imply that increased transparency can influence the above factors and add further explanatory power to a strategic choice model to imply that ethical transparency might also motivate ethical decision-making for a rational actor. Pihlström (2013) investigates religious pragmatism as “a middle path option for those who do not want to give up either their scientific worldview or their possible religious sensibilities” (Pihlström, 2013, p. 27). This concept avoids the scientific implications of my research into rational pragmatism by sidelining the strictness of empirical evidence toward a “richer conception of evidence as something that can be had, or may be lacking, in the 'laboratory of life’“(p. 28). However, the author does suggest \",\"PeriodicalId\":203965,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"The Journal of Values-Based Leadership\",\"volume\":\"7 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2017-07-10\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"The Journal of Values-Based Leadership\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.22543/0733.102.1194\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"The Journal of Values-Based Leadership","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.22543/0733.102.1194","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

本文探讨了领导行为令人困惑的本质,以了解鼓励不道德决策的条件。在现有实用主义伦理学文献的基础上,我探讨了领导者如何通过理解理性选择的激励来提高组织内道德决策的质量。我开发了一个基于理性选择的道德决策模型来理解道德领导者行为背后的动机,并发现只要受众成本高于不道德行为所带来的节约效益,道德行为就可能是理性的。最后,我分析了道德理性模型如何与其他解释不道德领导行为的著名理论进行比较,并提出从我的模型中得出的可能结果比竞争性的控制导向模型更好地解释了糟糕的领导行为。这项调查的结果强调了领导力作为一种工具的交易性和实践性特征,可以帮助领导者管理他们的道德氛围,改进商业实践和管理政策,理解个人激励的本质,并捕捉领导者行为的交易成分。伦理文学提供了广泛的考虑,指导个人和社会的互动,提高社会的普遍福利。然而,尽管学术伦理学科已经成熟,但表现出不道德行为的领导者的故事还是层出不穷。这些领导人表现出如此糟糕的行为,似乎没有合理的理由;作为杰出的商业、政府和军事领导人,他们都非常聪明,受过良好的教育,经济上很富裕,并且在专业上受到最高级别的认可。这些领导人似乎拥有一切有利条件,但为了相对微薄的收益,却冒着道德失当的风险。这一观察结果提出了一个有趣的难题:为什么看似优势明显的领导者在已经比其他人拥有优势的情况下,还会做出不道德的行为?此外,领导者可以做些什么来避免这种行为?在回答这个谜题时,我想到了几种解释。涉及贪婪、竞争、高层责任的相对权力差异和精神疾病等问题的理论可以为潜在的复杂行为提供简单的解释。然而,学者们提供了其他更有帮助的解释,但仍然完全不令人满意。Park, Westphal, and Stern(2011)发现,下属对ceo的奉承评论是导致领导者过度自信和有偏见的决策的原因(Park, Westphal, & Stern, 2011)。Park等人发现,领导者的高社会地位使他们暴露于越来越多的奉承言论和行为(第261页)。美国西弗吉尼亚州的JOSEPH E. LONG CHARLESTON夸大了领导者的有效个人判断力,降低了领导者识别不良表现或挑战无效策略的能力(第267页)。Park等人的研究表明,领导者的行为会随着时间的推移而演变,因此领导者会期望毫不动摇的从众,并成为“相信自己的压力”的受害者,从而失去识别个人和绩效导向缺点的能力(第259页)。其他学者对与高层领导的竞争和相对权力差异有关的不道德领导行为提供了更简单的解释。Ludwig和Longenecker(1993)指出,“高层管理人员违反道德是成功的副产品,而不是竞争压力的副产品”,这使得上述谜题更加有趣(Ludwig和Longenecker, 1993, p. 265)。根据两位作者的说法,随着领导者变得自满,获得特权信息,增加对关键资源的访问,并获得操纵更有利结果的能力,道德不当行为就会演变(第265页)。简而言之,这一理论提供了一种以自我为中心的方法来理解糟糕的领导者行为,与Park等人提出的以成功为导向的理论相反,该理论将不道德的领导者行为解释为不仅仅是在竞争日益激烈的环境中需要走捷径。本着实用主义伦理学的精神,我对领导者的行为提出了一个更简洁的解释。正如学者们所指出的,实用主义伦理学是关于决策过程的,即“通过使用调查出现良好的道德选择”(Johnson, 2015),以及“把习惯放在首位”,“把过去带到现在”(LaFollette, 2013, p. 402)。在理解实用主义伦理学时,战略选择模型将增加伦理领导文献,并为伦理考虑如何积极或消极地影响预期的领导者行为提供独特的解释。 这项调查的结果强调了领导力作为一种工具的交易性和实践性特征,可以帮助领导者管理他们的道德氛围,改进商业实践和管理政策,理解个人激励的本质,并捕捉领导者行为的交易成分。本文采用深入理解实用伦理学的方法来揭示实用伦理学过程如何在更具战略性的伦理决策中占据首要地位。此外,我将实用主义伦理学的期望作为影响道德决策战略性质的效用变量,并提出了一个理性选择模型,以揭示激励道德领导者选择的条件。实用主义伦理可以积极地影响战略决策,以强调基本的和持续的杜威主义观念,即实用主义伦理仍然以过程为中心,科学兼容,逻辑和习惯驱动(Johnson, 2015;2013年拉福莱特)。此外,实用伦理学的文献充分揭示了伦理考虑与战略选择之间的关系,提供了对在道德挑战环境中为领导者选择提供信息的变量的细致理解。Whitford(2002)通过挑战“投资组合”假设,即信念和欲望是战略效用模型的充分输入,挑战了理性行为人理论及其假定的“范式特权”(Whitford, 2002,第327页)。然而,惠特福德的理论采取了一种过度连续的实用主义观点,即一种选择的“目的”成为下一种选择的“手段”。为了反驳Whitford的观点,战略选择模型将把分析水平从系统层面降低到个人层面,并采用贝叶斯方法来理解决策随时间的变化。从实用主义的角度来看,通过早期领导选择获得的经验教训会影响后来决策中领导选择的习惯(LaFollette, 2013)。Woiceshyn(2011)使用以商业为导向的模型,通过“不道德的决策伤害决策者自己和他人,而道德决策者有相反的效果”(Woiceshyn, 2011, p. 311)的前提来检查道德决策。作者提出了一种理性利己主义理论,其中“推理(有意识的处理)和直觉(潜意识的处理)通过形成、回忆和应用商业中长期成功所必需的道德原则而相互作用”(第312页)。Woiceshyn还考虑了先前的研究,发现“管理者在做出涉及道德的决策时,采用与他们对影响公司的任何长期决策相同的过程”,这意味着道德选择可能比不道德的选择更理想,这支持了我对理性伦理的研究兴趣(第312页)。此外,Woiceshyn引入了领导者行为的因果因素,包括受众成本和被抓的概率;Trevino和Youngblood认为,这种“道德强度”可以应用于战略选择模型(第312页)。在解决LaFollette(2013)的实用主义伦理习惯形成方面的问题时,Caras和Sandu(2014)主张“体现在伦理专业知识中的模型的认识论和实用主义需求以及学术功能”(Caras和Sandu, 2014,第142页)。对于Caras和Sandu来说,伦理专业知识包括“严格的道德哲学训练”,作为“伦理专家的必要条件,正是因为他的角色是为那些专业知识不完全涉及伦理的专业人士提供专业咨询”(第143页)。尽管Caras和Sandu未能解决专家咨询的相对效用问题,但他们澄清了执行性专业知识和实用性专业知识之间的区别,这在伦理咨询和效用之间建立了有价值的联系。Ali和Lin(2013)探讨了选民理论中的实用主义,以确定一个理性的人何时会“承担投票的成本,即使其中任何一个都不太可能是关键的”(Ali & Lin, 2013)。p . 73)。这为理解道德行为的潜在成本提供了解释力,因为在激烈竞争的环境中实现结果的固有效率低下。Ali和Lin还提供了选民行为的数学解释,并通过确定受众成本和被抓住的不同概率如何影响领导者选择的预期效用,为理性方法提供了支持。他们还暗示,增加透明度可以影响上述因素,并为战略选择模型增加进一步的解释力,以暗示道德透明度也可能激励理性行为者的道德决策。Pihlström(2013)将宗教实用主义视为“那些不想放弃科学世界观或可能的宗教情感的人的中间道路选择”(Pihlström, 2013,第27页)。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Beyond Bathsheba: Managing Ethical Climates Through Pragmatic Ethics
This paper explores the puzzling nature of leader behavior in order to understand the conditions that encourage unethical decision-making. Building on the extant literature of pragmatic ethics, I explore how leaders can increase the quality of ethical decision-making within their organizations by understanding the incentives of rational choice. I have developed a rational choice-based ethical decision-making model to understand the incentives behind ethical leader behavior and find that ethical behavior is likely to be rational as long as audience costs remain higher than the savings benefits incurred by unethical behavior. I conclude with analysis of how the ethical rational model compares to other prominent theories that explain unethical leader behavior and propose that the probable outcomes derived from my model better explain bad leader behavior than competing control-oriented models. The results of this inquiry underscore the transactional and practical characteristics of leadership as a tool to help leaders manage their ethical climates, improve business practices and management policies, understand the nature of individual incentives, and capture transactional components of leader behavior. Introduction Ethical literature provides broad considerations for guiding individual and social interaction and enhancing the general welfare of society. However, despite the maturity of the scholarly ethical discipline, stories of leaders who exhibit unethical behavior are legion. Such leaders exhibit such poor behavior for seemingly no logical reason; as prominent business, government, and military leaders, they are all highly intelligent, well educated, economically well off, and professionally accepted at the highest levels. These leaders appear to have everything going for them, yet risk ethical misbehavior for relatively modest gains. This observation presents an interesting puzzle: why do seemingly advantaged leaders engage in poor ethical behavior when they already have such an advantage over others? Moreover, what can leaders do to avoid such behavior? In answering this puzzle, several explanations come to mind. Theories involving issues of greed, competition, relative power differences at top echelons of responsibility, and mental illness could offer simple explanations for potentially complicated behavior. However, scholars offer other explanations that are more helpful but that remain altogether unsatisfying. Park, Westphal, and Stern (2011) find that flattering comments from subordinates to CEOs are causal in producing leader overconfidence and biased decisionmaking (Park, Westphal, & Stern, 2011). Park et al. find that high social status in leaders exposes them to increasing levels of flattering comments and behavior (p. 261) which JOSEPH E. LONG CHARLESTON, WEST VIRGINIA, US inflates a leader’s sense of effective personal judgment and decreases a leader’s ability to recognize poor performance or challenge ineffective strategies (p. 267). Park et al.’s research suggests that leader behavior evolves over time so that leaders expect unwavering conformity and fall victim to “believing their own press” where they lose the ability to identify personal and performance-oriented shortcomings (p. 259). Other scholars offer a simpler explanation for unethical leader behavior related to competition and relative power differentials at top levels of leadership. Ludwig and Longenecker (1993) noted that “ethical violations by upper managers are the by-product of success, not of competitive pressures” which makes the aforementioned puzzle even more intriguing (Ludwig & Longenecker, 1993, p. 265). According to the authors, ethical misbehavior evolves as leaders become complacent, gain access to privileged information, increase access to critical resources, and gain the ability to manipulate more favorable outcomes (p. 265). In short, this theory provides an ego-centric approach to understanding bad leader behavior, in contrast to the success-oriented theory proposed by Park et al., to explain unethical leader behavior as involving more than the need to cut corners in an increasingly competitive environment. In the spirit of pragmatic ethics, I am proposing a more parsimonious explanation for leader behavior. As scholars note, pragmatic ethics is about the process of decisionmaking such that “good ethical choices emerge through the use of inquiry” (Johnson, 2015), as well as “giving primacy to habits” which “carry the past into the present” (LaFollette, 2013, p. 402). In understanding pragmatic ethics, a strategic choice model will add to ethical leadership literature and provide a unique explanation for how ethical considerations positively or negatively influence expected leader behavior. The results of this inquiry underscore the transactional and practical characteristics of leadership as a tool to help leaders manage their ethical climates, improve business practices and management policies, understand the nature of individual incentives, and capture transactional components of leader behavior. This paper employs a deep-dive approach to understanding pragmatic ethics to uncover how pragmatic ethical processes give primacy to more strategic ethical decision-making. Furthermore, I employ the expectations of pragmatic ethics as utility variables that impact the strategic nature of ethical decision-making and present a rational choice model to uncover the conditions that incentivize ethical leader choices. Pragmatic Ethics Pragmatic ethics can positively influence strategic decision-making to underscore the fundamental and continuing Deweyan notion that pragmatic ethics remain process-centric, scientifically compatible, logical, and habit-driven (Johnson, 2015; LaFollette, 2013). Furthermore, the literature of pragmatic ethics sufficiently uncovers a relationship between ethical considerations and strategic choices that provide a nuanced understanding of the variables that inform leader choices in ethically-challenging environments. Whitford (2002) challenges rational actor theory and its assumed “paradigmatic privilege” by challenging the “portfolio” assumption that beliefs and desires are sufficient inputs for strategic utility models (Whitford, 2002, p. 327). However, Whitford’s theory takes an overly continuous view of pragmatism where “ends” of one choice become the “means” of the next choice. In countering Whitford’s argument, a strategic choice model would reduce the level of analysis from the systematic to the individual level and take a Bayesian approach to understanding changes in decision-making over time. In pragmatic terms, lessons learned through early leader choices impact the habits of leader choices in later decisions (LaFollette, 2013). Using a business-oriented model, Woiceshyn (2011) examines ethical decision-making through the premise that “unethical decisions harm the decision makers themselves as well as others, whereas ethical decision makers have the opposite effect” (Woiceshyn, 2011, p. 311). The author presents a theory of rational egoism where “reasoning (conscious processing) and intuition (subconscious processing) interact through forming, recalling, and applying moral principles necessary for long-term success in business” (p. 312). Woiceshyn also considers previous studies that found “managers employ the same process when making decisions involving ethics as they do for any long-term decisions affecting their companies” to imply that ethical choices can be more optimal than unethical ones, which supports my research interests in rational ethics (p. 312). Furthermore, Woiceshyn introduces causal factors for leader behavior to include audience costs and the probability of getting caught; this “moral intensity” according to Trevino and Youngblood, can be applied in a strategic choice model (p. 312). In addressing LaFollette’s (2013) habit-forming aspects of pragmatic ethics, Caras and Sandu (2014) argue for the “epistemic and pragmatic need and academic functioning of a model embodied in ethical expertise” (Caras & Sandu, 2014, p. 142). For Caras and Sandu, ethical expertise involves “rigorous training in moral philosophy” as “an imperative condition for an ethics expert, precisely because his role is to provide professional counseling to professionals whose expertise does not involve ethics exclusively” (p. 143). Although Caras and Sandu fail to address the relative utility of expert counsel, they clarify the distinction between performative and pragmatic expertise, which makes a valuable connection between ethical counseling and utility. Ali and Lin (2013) explore pragmatism in voter theory to identify when a rational person would “incur the cost of voting, even when it is improbable that any one of them is pivotal” (Ali & Lin, 2013. p. 73). This gives explanatory power to understanding the potential costs of ethical behavior given inherent inefficiencies in achieving outcomes in intensely competitive environments. Ali and Lin also offer a mathematical explanation for voter behavior and add support for the rational approach by identifying how audience costs and varying probabilities of being caught can impact the expected utility of leader choices. They also imply that increased transparency can influence the above factors and add further explanatory power to a strategic choice model to imply that ethical transparency might also motivate ethical decision-making for a rational actor. Pihlström (2013) investigates religious pragmatism as “a middle path option for those who do not want to give up either their scientific worldview or their possible religious sensibilities” (Pihlström, 2013, p. 27). This concept avoids the scientific implications of my research into rational pragmatism by sidelining the strictness of empirical evidence toward a “richer conception of evidence as something that can be had, or may be lacking, in the 'laboratory of life’“(p. 28). However, the author does suggest
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
期刊最新文献
Ethical Leadership: A Study of Behaviors of Leaders in Higher Education Today Book Review: Inequality in America: Causes and Consequences Lessons from History: The Remarkable Leadership of Eleanor Roosevelt and Why It Matters Today (Part 2) Book Review: Scaling People: Tactics for Management and Company Building Avert Suicidal Thoughts to Lead an Exciting and Meaningful Life
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1