通情达理的人的神秘案例

John Gardner
{"title":"通情达理的人的神秘案例","authors":"John Gardner","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780198852940.003.0008","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Who is the ‘reasonable person’, that ‘excellent but odious character’1 who seems to inhabit every nook and cranny of the common law? Until I read Arthur Ripstein’s book Equality, Responsibility and the Law, I thought I knew the answer. I generally understood the word ‘reasonable’, in legal contexts, to mean no more and no less than ‘justified’. A reasonable action is a justified action, a reasonable belief is a justified belief, a reasonable fear is a justified fear, a reasonable measure of care is a justified measure of care, etc. By the same token, the common law’s reasonable person (I fondly thought) is none other than a justified person, i.e. a person who is justified in all those aspects of her life that properly call for justification. She is justified in her actions, her beliefs, her fears, the measure of care she takes, and so on. Thus, to say that one’s actions or beliefs or emotions or attitudes etc. were those of the reasonable person is merely to say, in a typically roundabout lawyer’s way, that one’s actions or beliefs or emotions or attitudes etc. were justified ones. It may be thought that at least some of the law’s uses of its reasonableness standard plainly defy this interpretation, so that it should not have taken a philosophical virtuoso like Ripstein to alert me to its deficiencies. What about the familiar cases, mentioned in even the most pedestrian of criminal-law","PeriodicalId":431450,"journal":{"name":"Jurisprudence & Legal Philosophy","volume":"56 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2001-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"16","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"The Mysterious Case of the Reasonable Person\",\"authors\":\"John Gardner\",\"doi\":\"10.1093/oso/9780198852940.003.0008\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Who is the ‘reasonable person’, that ‘excellent but odious character’1 who seems to inhabit every nook and cranny of the common law? Until I read Arthur Ripstein’s book Equality, Responsibility and the Law, I thought I knew the answer. I generally understood the word ‘reasonable’, in legal contexts, to mean no more and no less than ‘justified’. A reasonable action is a justified action, a reasonable belief is a justified belief, a reasonable fear is a justified fear, a reasonable measure of care is a justified measure of care, etc. By the same token, the common law’s reasonable person (I fondly thought) is none other than a justified person, i.e. a person who is justified in all those aspects of her life that properly call for justification. She is justified in her actions, her beliefs, her fears, the measure of care she takes, and so on. Thus, to say that one’s actions or beliefs or emotions or attitudes etc. were those of the reasonable person is merely to say, in a typically roundabout lawyer’s way, that one’s actions or beliefs or emotions or attitudes etc. were justified ones. It may be thought that at least some of the law’s uses of its reasonableness standard plainly defy this interpretation, so that it should not have taken a philosophical virtuoso like Ripstein to alert me to its deficiencies. What about the familiar cases, mentioned in even the most pedestrian of criminal-law\",\"PeriodicalId\":431450,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Jurisprudence & Legal Philosophy\",\"volume\":\"56 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2001-01-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"16\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Jurisprudence & Legal Philosophy\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198852940.003.0008\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Jurisprudence & Legal Philosophy","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198852940.003.0008","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 16

摘要

谁是“通情达理的人”,谁是“优秀但令人讨厌的人物”,谁似乎占据了普通法的每个角落和缝隙?直到我读了亚瑟·里普斯坦的《平等、责任和法律》,我才知道答案。在法律语境中,我对“合理”一词的理解一般是“正当”。一个合理的行为是一个合理的行为,一个合理的信念是一个合理的信念,一个合理的恐惧是一个合理的恐惧,一个合理的谨慎是一个合理的谨慎,等等。同样的道理,普通法中的通情达理的人(我天真地认为)就是一个被证明是正当的人,也就是说,一个在生活中所有需要正当理由的方面都是正当的人。她的行为,她的信仰,她的恐惧,她所采取的措施等等都是合理的。因此,说一个人的行为、信仰、情感或态度等是理性的人的行为、信仰、情感或态度等,只不过是以典型的迂回律师的方式说,一个人的行为、信仰、情感或态度等是合理的。可以认为,至少法律对其合理性标准的某些使用明显违背了这种解释,因此不应该需要像里普斯坦这样的哲学大师来提醒我它的缺陷。那些连最平淡无奇的刑法也提到过的熟悉的案件呢
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
The Mysterious Case of the Reasonable Person
Who is the ‘reasonable person’, that ‘excellent but odious character’1 who seems to inhabit every nook and cranny of the common law? Until I read Arthur Ripstein’s book Equality, Responsibility and the Law, I thought I knew the answer. I generally understood the word ‘reasonable’, in legal contexts, to mean no more and no less than ‘justified’. A reasonable action is a justified action, a reasonable belief is a justified belief, a reasonable fear is a justified fear, a reasonable measure of care is a justified measure of care, etc. By the same token, the common law’s reasonable person (I fondly thought) is none other than a justified person, i.e. a person who is justified in all those aspects of her life that properly call for justification. She is justified in her actions, her beliefs, her fears, the measure of care she takes, and so on. Thus, to say that one’s actions or beliefs or emotions or attitudes etc. were those of the reasonable person is merely to say, in a typically roundabout lawyer’s way, that one’s actions or beliefs or emotions or attitudes etc. were justified ones. It may be thought that at least some of the law’s uses of its reasonableness standard plainly defy this interpretation, so that it should not have taken a philosophical virtuoso like Ripstein to alert me to its deficiencies. What about the familiar cases, mentioned in even the most pedestrian of criminal-law
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
期刊最新文献
Why Tolerate Religion? The Standards of Property England and the Rediscovery of Constitutional Faith The Indelible Science of Law The Principle Theory: How Many Theories and What is Their Merit?
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1