首页 > 最新文献

Jurisprudence & Legal Philosophy最新文献

英文 中文
Why Tolerate Religion? 为什么要容忍宗教?
Pub Date : 2012-10-28 DOI: 10.5860/choice.50-4946
B. Leiter
This provocative book addresses one of the most enduring puzzles in political philosophy and constitutional theory—why is religion singled out for preferential treatment in both law and public discourse? Why are religious obligations that conflict with the law accorded special toleration while other obligations of conscience are not? In Why Tolerate Religion?, Brian Leiter shows why our reasons for tolerating religion are not specific to religion but apply to all claims of conscience, and why a government committed to liberty of conscience is not required by the principle of toleration to grant exemptions to laws that promote the general welfare.
这本挑衅性的书解决了政治哲学和宪法理论中一个最持久的谜题——为什么宗教在法律和公共话语中都得到了优待?为什么与法律相冲突的宗教义务得到了特别的宽容,而其他良心义务却没有?《为什么要容忍宗教?》布赖恩·雷特(Brian Leiter)解释了为什么我们容忍宗教的理由不是特定于宗教,而是适用于所有的良心要求,以及为什么一个致力于良心自由的政府不需要根据宽容原则对促进普遍福利的法律给予豁免。
{"title":"Why Tolerate Religion?","authors":"B. Leiter","doi":"10.5860/choice.50-4946","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5860/choice.50-4946","url":null,"abstract":"This provocative book addresses one of the most enduring puzzles in political philosophy and constitutional theory—why is religion singled out for preferential treatment in both law and public discourse? Why are religious obligations that conflict with the law accorded special toleration while other obligations of conscience are not? In Why Tolerate Religion?, Brian Leiter shows why our reasons for tolerating religion are not specific to religion but apply to all claims of conscience, and why a government committed to liberty of conscience is not required by the principle of toleration to grant exemptions to laws that promote the general welfare.","PeriodicalId":431450,"journal":{"name":"Jurisprudence & Legal Philosophy","volume":"21 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2012-10-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"125091921","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 129
The Standards of Property 财产标准
Pub Date : 2009-09-02 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.1467087
Amnon Lehavi
Much scholarly attention has been paid recently to the optimal design of legal norms as constituting either clear-cut “rules�? or open-ended “standards.�? The reemergence of formalist thought across schools and ideologies calling to reinforce a more rule-based regime in various legal fields has been increasingly challenging the substantive, contextual jurisprudence that had largely dominated the twentieth century. The study of legal standards versus rules in property law remains, however, quite limited, focusing mainly on specific aspects such as the remedy-based property rule/liability rule discourse, the debate whether the right to exclude represents the inherent “core�? of property rights, and the renewed interest in the structural numerus clausus principle. This Article offers an innovative, comprehensive analysis of the ways in which legal standards operate in property law. It identifies the distinctive manner in which the chief justifications for standards, i.e. incompleteness of rights and enhancement of substantive value-based design and interpretation of norms, play out in property law. Cutting across conventional public law / private law distinctions, by referring to various standards such as “trade usage,�? “custom,�? “reasonableness,�? “abuse of rights,�? or “public use,�? the Article shows that legal standards hinge prominently on the institutional mechanisms by which such norms are crafted and enforced, and identifies the conditions under which property standards may outperform hard-edged rules. Considering the unique trait of property rights as implicating numerous and often indefinite interest holders, and hence the need for broad-based coordination in designing the content of property legal standards over time, the Article looks at the ways in which such standards can be filled with content by either bottom-up norms such as group-based customs, values, and understandings, or rather by top-down bodies such as courts. In essence, in order for property legal standards to work effectively, bottom-up and top-down decisionmaking institutions, working exclusively or conjointly, must systemically guide actors through the often inevitable incompleteness of rights and the dynamic nature of value-based norm-setting, without bringing property to the brink of excessive instability and insecurity that have led to the backlash of new formalism.
最近,学术界对法律规范的最佳设计给予了大量关注,因为它既构成了明确的“规则”,又构成了“规则”。或者是开放式的“标准”。形式主义思想跨学派和意识形态的重新出现,呼吁在各个法律领域加强更加基于规则的制度,这日益挑战了在20世纪占据主导地位的实质性、情境法学。然而,对物权法中法律标准与规则的研究仍然相当有限,主要集中在具体方面,如基于救济的财产规则/责任规则话语,排他权是否代表固有的“核心”?财产权的问题,以及对物权法定数原则的重新关注。本文对物权法中法律标准的运作方式进行了创新的、全面的分析。它确定了标准的主要理由,即权利的不完整性和加强基于实质价值的设计和规范解释,在物权法中发挥作用的独特方式。跨越传统公法/私法的区别,通过参考各种标准,如“贸易使用”,“自定义,�?“合理性,�?“滥用权利”?或者“公共使用”?文章表明,法律标准在很大程度上取决于制定和执行这些规范的体制机制,并确定了财产标准可能优于强硬规则的条件。考虑到产权的独特特征,即涉及众多且往往是不确定的利益持有人,因此需要在设计财产法标准的内容时进行广泛的协调,本文着眼于通过自下而上的规范(如基于群体的习俗、价值观和理解)或自上而下的机构(如法院)来填充这些标准的方式。从本质上讲,为了使财产法标准有效地发挥作用,自下而上和自上而下的决策机构必须单独或联合工作,系统地指导行为者通过往往不可避免的权利不完整和基于价值的规范制定的动态性质,而不使财产处于过度不稳定和不安全的边缘,这种不稳定和不安全导致了新形式主义的反弹。
{"title":"The Standards of Property","authors":"Amnon Lehavi","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.1467087","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1467087","url":null,"abstract":"Much scholarly attention has been paid recently to the optimal design of legal norms as constituting either clear-cut “rules�? or open-ended “standards.�? The reemergence of formalist thought across schools and ideologies calling to reinforce a more rule-based regime in various legal fields has been increasingly challenging the substantive, contextual jurisprudence that had largely dominated the twentieth century. The study of legal standards versus rules in property law remains, however, quite limited, focusing mainly on specific aspects such as the remedy-based property rule/liability rule discourse, the debate whether the right to exclude represents the inherent “core�? of property rights, and the renewed interest in the structural numerus clausus principle. This Article offers an innovative, comprehensive analysis of the ways in which legal standards operate in property law. It identifies the distinctive manner in which the chief justifications for standards, i.e. incompleteness of rights and enhancement of substantive value-based design and interpretation of norms, play out in property law. Cutting across conventional public law / private law distinctions, by referring to various standards such as “trade usage,�? “custom,�? “reasonableness,�? “abuse of rights,�? or “public use,�? the Article shows that legal standards hinge prominently on the institutional mechanisms by which such norms are crafted and enforced, and identifies the conditions under which property standards may outperform hard-edged rules. Considering the unique trait of property rights as implicating numerous and often indefinite interest holders, and hence the need for broad-based coordination in designing the content of property legal standards over time, the Article looks at the ways in which such standards can be filled with content by either bottom-up norms such as group-based customs, values, and understandings, or rather by top-down bodies such as courts. In essence, in order for property legal standards to work effectively, bottom-up and top-down decisionmaking institutions, working exclusively or conjointly, must systemically guide actors through the often inevitable incompleteness of rights and the dynamic nature of value-based norm-setting, without bringing property to the brink of excessive instability and insecurity that have led to the backlash of new formalism.","PeriodicalId":431450,"journal":{"name":"Jurisprudence & Legal Philosophy","volume":"37 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2009-09-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"121284788","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
England and the Rediscovery of Constitutional Faith 英格兰与宪政信仰的重新发现
Pub Date : 2009-07-30 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.1445138
Matthew Zagor
England is currently experiencing a widely recognised constitutional renaissance, with traditional English ‘liberties’ at its core: historic rights and liberty-affirming documents of the past are cited by counsel and judge alike, the Prime Minister waxes lyrical about constitutional values which define the British nation, scholars call for the revival of a purported rights-centric common law constitution, and a new breed of media-star historians are rediscovering English liberties in political institutions and re-imagined constitutional moments. Even the mythology of Magna Carta is resurfacing in the popular imagination, the date of its signing selected by public poll as ‘the best date to celebrate Britishness’. The rhetoric contrasts with the dominant popular trope for much of the twentieth century, which portrayed the English constitution as essentially clever politics. Today’s constitutional veneration, however, has a long and complex history. This paper charts the variety of constitutional veneration that arose in the post-reformation period, as well as its decline, and contemporary revival. Starting with an overview of the seventeenth century, it charts the emergence of a constitutional language arising out of the rich theological and philosophical tradition of the age, and the persuasive use by the principal judicial figures of the day of new forms of historiography, traditional natural law philosophy, and emerging ethnic nationalism. Underpinned by contended notions of liberty and religiosity, this potent mix ensured that the newly minted English constitution enjoyed a quasi-religious status, embracing divinely ordained values and institutional arrangements that at once defined what it was to be both English and Protestant, and therefore was worthy of veneration. The decline of this constitutional model in the 19th and 20th century is then considered against the backdrop of empiricism, utilitarianism, nationalism and the victory of a political understanding of the constitutional model. The purported disappearance of the ‘legal’ constitution in this period, however, was never to be consolidated, nor were the contradictions inherent in the new ‘sovereignist’ model reconcilable with the explosion of rights jurisprudence in the latter part of the twentieth century. The article therefore concludes with a brief overview of the re-emergence of the language of constitutional faith in the late twentieth and early twenty-first century, and the renewed reliance on this rhetoric of constitutional veneration by the judicial branch of government in an attempt to influence the development of a normative English constitutional and national identity.
英国目前正在经历一场广泛认可的宪法复兴,其核心是传统的英国“自由”:法律顾问和法官都引用了过去的历史权利和肯定自由的文件,首相对定义英国民族的宪法价值观充满了热情,学者们呼吁复兴所谓的以权利为中心的普通法宪法,新一代的媒体明星历史学家正在重新发现英国政治制度中的自由,并重新想象宪法时刻。就连《大宪章》(Magna Carta)的神话也重新出现在大众的想象中,《大宪章》签署的日期被公众投票选为“庆祝英国特色的最佳日期”。这种修辞与20世纪大部分时间的主流流行修辞形成鲜明对比,后者将英国宪法描绘为本质上聪明的政治。然而,今天的宪法崇拜有着漫长而复杂的历史。本文描绘了改革后时期宪法崇拜的多样性,以及它的衰落和当代复兴。从对17世纪的概述开始,它描绘了一种宪法语言的出现,它产生于那个时代丰富的神学和哲学传统,以及当时主要司法人物对新形式的史学、传统自然法哲学和新兴民族主义的有说服力的使用。在自由和宗教观念的支撑下,这种强有力的混合确保了新制定的英国宪法享有准宗教地位,包含了神圣的价值观和制度安排,这些价值观和制度安排立即定义了英国和新教的界限,因此值得尊敬。这种宪政模式在19世纪和20世纪的衰落是在经验主义、功利主义、民族主义和对宪政模式的政治理解的胜利的背景下进行的。然而,在这一时期,所谓的“法律”宪法的消失从未得到巩固,新“主权主义”模式中固有的矛盾与二十世纪后半叶权利法学的爆发也无法调和。因此,本文最后简要概述了20世纪末和21世纪初宪法信仰语言的重新出现,以及政府司法部门重新依赖这种宪法崇拜的修辞,试图影响规范的英国宪法和国家认同的发展。
{"title":"England and the Rediscovery of Constitutional Faith","authors":"Matthew Zagor","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.1445138","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1445138","url":null,"abstract":"England is currently experiencing a widely recognised constitutional renaissance, with traditional English ‘liberties’ at its core: historic rights and liberty-affirming documents of the past are cited by counsel and judge alike, the Prime Minister waxes lyrical about constitutional values which define the British nation, scholars call for the revival of a purported rights-centric common law constitution, and a new breed of media-star historians are rediscovering English liberties in political institutions and re-imagined constitutional moments. Even the mythology of Magna Carta is resurfacing in the popular imagination, the date of its signing selected by public poll as ‘the best date to celebrate Britishness’. The rhetoric contrasts with the dominant popular trope for much of the twentieth century, which portrayed the English constitution as essentially clever politics. Today’s constitutional veneration, however, has a long and complex history. This paper charts the variety of constitutional veneration that arose in the post-reformation period, as well as its decline, and contemporary revival. Starting with an overview of the seventeenth century, it charts the emergence of a constitutional language arising out of the rich theological and philosophical tradition of the age, and the persuasive use by the principal judicial figures of the day of new forms of historiography, traditional natural law philosophy, and emerging ethnic nationalism. Underpinned by contended notions of liberty and religiosity, this potent mix ensured that the newly minted English constitution enjoyed a quasi-religious status, embracing divinely ordained values and institutional arrangements that at once defined what it was to be both English and Protestant, and therefore was worthy of veneration. The decline of this constitutional model in the 19th and 20th century is then considered against the backdrop of empiricism, utilitarianism, nationalism and the victory of a political understanding of the constitutional model. The purported disappearance of the ‘legal’ constitution in this period, however, was never to be consolidated, nor were the contradictions inherent in the new ‘sovereignist’ model reconcilable with the explosion of rights jurisprudence in the latter part of the twentieth century. The article therefore concludes with a brief overview of the re-emergence of the language of constitutional faith in the late twentieth and early twenty-first century, and the renewed reliance on this rhetoric of constitutional veneration by the judicial branch of government in an attempt to influence the development of a normative English constitutional and national identity.","PeriodicalId":431450,"journal":{"name":"Jurisprudence & Legal Philosophy","volume":"9 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2009-07-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"134240081","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
The Indelible Science of Law 不可磨灭的法学
Pub Date : 2009-07-01 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.1394425
A. Somek
This short essay, which is essentially a comment on a recent article by Armin von Bogdandy (see footnote 5), discusses why the understanding of Public law qua "legal science" persists in mainland Europe. The essay argues that this is to be welcomed.
这篇短文实质上是对阿明·冯·博格丹迪(Armin von Bogdandy)最近的一篇文章的评论(见脚注5),讨论了为什么公法作为“法学”的理解在欧洲大陆持续存在。这篇文章认为这是值得欢迎的。
{"title":"The Indelible Science of Law","authors":"A. Somek","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.1394425","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1394425","url":null,"abstract":"This short essay, which is essentially a comment on a recent article by Armin von Bogdandy (see footnote 5), discusses why the understanding of Public law qua \"legal science\" persists in mainland Europe. The essay argues that this is to be welcomed.","PeriodicalId":431450,"journal":{"name":"Jurisprudence & Legal Philosophy","volume":"37 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2009-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"134380889","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 6
The Principle Theory: How Many Theories and What is Their Merit? 原则理论:有多少理论及其优点?
Pub Date : 2009-05-28 DOI: 10.1093/ACPROF:OSO/9780199582068.003.0010
Ralf Poscher
The work of Robert Alexy is closely associated with the “principle theory”. For Alexy himself, the principle theory represents the heart of his theoretical work, around which most of his publications are organized. In Alexy’s work, and in the work of his students, the label “principle theory” suggests theoretical unity. Despite this impression of unity, the principle theory is far more multilayered and multifaceted than the “unitary” label would suggest. The critique of Alexy’s principle theory, which is the topic of this article, has two objectives. First, I distinguish between the different types of theory which have found refuge under the unitary label. By clarifying the different theoretical aspirations pursued by proponents of the principle theory, I systematize these different theoretical and doctrinal efforts which are often not clearly separated in the debate. The critique aims to offer a framework within which to situate the different arguments and criticisms, so that it becomes clearer which type, level or aspect of principle theory the argument is about. This is the constructive part of the critique. Second, the critique aims to evaluate the theoretical and doctrinal positions and achievements of the various principle theories on each of the levels identified. This analysis is for the most part critical. The claim is that the principle theory is wrong on most counts and misunderstands itself by confusing the different levels of its theoretical and doctrinal aspirations. At its origins, as put forward by Josef Esser and Ronald Dworkin in the framework of a theory about the concept of law, it has its merit in rejecting the simplifications of positivist theories of adjudication. A defense of the role of specifically legal principles in the process of adjudication against arguments to the contrary from Larry Alexander and Ken Kress is offered. But the acceptance of legal principles does not entail a validity relation between the law and morality as supported by Alexy. As a theory of norms, the principle theory fails in its effort to claim a structural difference between rules and principles. It also fails as a methodological theory that reduces adjudication to subsumption under rules or the balancing of principles. It misunderstands itself when it is conceived as a doctrinal theory especially of fundamental rights as it is developed in Alexy’s main work “A Theory of Constitutional Rights”. The most promising aspect of Alexy’s principle theory could be its contribution to a more comprehensive theory of legal argumentation.
罗伯特·阿列克谢的工作与“原理理论”密切相关。对于阿列克谢本人来说,原理理论代表了他理论工作的核心,他的大部分出版物都围绕着它组织起来。在阿列克谢及其学生的著作中,“原理理论”这个标签暗示着理论的统一性。尽管有这种统一的印象,但原理理论远比“单一”标签所暗示的要多层次和多面性得多。本文的主题是对阿列克谢原理理论的批判,它有两个目的。首先,我区分了在统一标签下找到庇护的不同类型的理论。通过澄清原则理论的支持者所追求的不同理论诉求,我将这些不同的理论和教义努力系统化,这些努力在辩论中往往没有被清楚地分开。批判的目的是提供一个框架,在其中放置不同的论点和批评,以便它变得更加清晰的类型,层次或方面的原则理论的论点。这是批评的建设性部分。其次,批判的目的是评估理论和教义的立场和成就的各种原则理论在每一个层面确定。这种分析在很大程度上是至关重要的。这种说法认为,原则理论在大多数方面都是错误的,并且由于混淆了理论和教义的不同层次而误解了自己。正如约瑟夫·埃塞尔和罗纳德·德沃金在关于法律概念的理论框架中提出的那样,它的起源有其优点,即拒绝简化实证主义审判理论。针对拉里·亚历山大和肯·克雷斯的相反观点,对具体法律原则在裁决过程中的作用进行了辩护。但法律原则的接受并不意味着阿列克谢所支持的法律与道德之间的有效性关系。作为一种规范理论,原则理论未能在规则和原则之间提出结构上的区别。作为一种方法论理论,它也不能将裁决简化为规则的包容或原则的平衡。当它被认为是一种教义理论时,尤其是在阿列克谢的主要著作《宪法权利理论》中发展起来的基本权利理论时,它误解了自己。阿列克谢的原则理论最有希望的方面可能是它对更全面的法律论证理论的贡献。
{"title":"The Principle Theory: How Many Theories and What is Their Merit?","authors":"Ralf Poscher","doi":"10.1093/ACPROF:OSO/9780199582068.003.0010","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/ACPROF:OSO/9780199582068.003.0010","url":null,"abstract":"The work of Robert Alexy is closely associated with the “principle theory”. For Alexy himself, the principle theory represents the heart of his theoretical work, around which most of his publications are organized. In Alexy’s work, and in the work of his students, the label “principle theory” suggests theoretical unity. Despite this impression of unity, the principle theory is far more multilayered and multifaceted than the “unitary” label would suggest. The critique of Alexy’s principle theory, which is the topic of this article, has two objectives. First, I distinguish between the different types of theory which have found refuge under the unitary label. By clarifying the different theoretical aspirations pursued by proponents of the principle theory, I systematize these different theoretical and doctrinal efforts which are often not clearly separated in the debate. The critique aims to offer a framework within which to situate the different arguments and criticisms, so that it becomes clearer which type, level or aspect of principle theory the argument is about. This is the constructive part of the critique. Second, the critique aims to evaluate the theoretical and doctrinal positions and achievements of the various principle theories on each of the levels identified. This analysis is for the most part critical. The claim is that the principle theory is wrong on most counts and misunderstands itself by confusing the different levels of its theoretical and doctrinal aspirations. At its origins, as put forward by Josef Esser and Ronald Dworkin in the framework of a theory about the concept of law, it has its merit in rejecting the simplifications of positivist theories of adjudication. A defense of the role of specifically legal principles in the process of adjudication against arguments to the contrary from Larry Alexander and Ken Kress is offered. But the acceptance of legal principles does not entail a validity relation between the law and morality as supported by Alexy. As a theory of norms, the principle theory fails in its effort to claim a structural difference between rules and principles. It also fails as a methodological theory that reduces adjudication to subsumption under rules or the balancing of principles. It misunderstands itself when it is conceived as a doctrinal theory especially of fundamental rights as it is developed in Alexy’s main work “A Theory of Constitutional Rights”. The most promising aspect of Alexy’s principle theory could be its contribution to a more comprehensive theory of legal argumentation.","PeriodicalId":431450,"journal":{"name":"Jurisprudence & Legal Philosophy","volume":"59 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2009-05-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"114075827","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 17
Intention and Interpretation: Towards A Meta-Theory of Legal Hermenuetics 意图与解释:走向法律解释学的元理论
Pub Date : 2009-05-13 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.1404203
D. Green
This article addresses the terms under which discussions of legal (i.e. constitutional and statutory) interpretation take place, advocating a shift away from “originalism” as our axis of debate to “intentionalism.” I argue that originalism has far more in common with its foes than has been generally recognized, and that intentionalism better implicates the most fundamental aspect of such methods of interpretation, regarding the existence, nature, and importance of intentions. I assert that originalists, just as much as many traditionally considered opposed to them, are intentionalists because they rely on mental state theories of intention. Tracking debates in the philosophy of action and literary theory, I also suggest that it is helpful to talk of intentionalism because it more explicitly relates legal concerns to the interpretive concerns common to these other fields. My approach also engages the work of others who, in various ways, have earlier discussed in the legal literature the broader context and implications of intentionalism, and especially that of Heidi Hurd on the ubiquity of intentionalism in legal interpretation. Although I do not here limn or endorse a specific interpretive methodology, my conclusions do extend to asserting that originalism and textualism, instead of being complementary, are at direct odds with one another – with originalism being a form of intentionalism and textualism explicitly rejecting intentionalism.
本文讨论了法律(即宪法和成文法)解释的讨论所依据的术语,主张从“原旨主义”转向“意旨主义”。我认为,原旨主义与其敌人的共同之处远比人们普遍认识到的要多,而意旨主义更好地暗示了这种解释方法的最基本方面,即关于意图的存在、性质和重要性。我断言,原旨主义者,就像许多传统上被认为反对他们的人一样,都是意图主义者,因为他们依赖于意图的心理状态理论。通过追踪行动哲学和文学理论中的辩论,我还建议,讨论意图主义是有帮助的,因为它更明确地将法律问题与这些其他领域共同的解释问题联系起来。我的方法也涉及其他人的工作,他们以不同的方式,在早期的法律文献中讨论了意图主义的更广泛的背景和含义,特别是海蒂·赫德(Heidi Hurd)关于意图主义在法律解释中的普遍性的研究。虽然我在这里没有描述或赞同一种特定的解释方法,但我的结论确实延伸到断言原旨主义和文本主义,而不是互补,是彼此直接矛盾的——原旨主义是意旨主义的一种形式,而文本主义明确地拒绝意旨主义。
{"title":"Intention and Interpretation: Towards A Meta-Theory of Legal Hermenuetics","authors":"D. Green","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.1404203","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1404203","url":null,"abstract":"This article addresses the terms under which discussions of legal (i.e. constitutional and statutory) interpretation take place, advocating a shift away from “originalism” as our axis of debate to “intentionalism.” I argue that originalism has far more in common with its foes than has been generally recognized, and that intentionalism better implicates the most fundamental aspect of such methods of interpretation, regarding the existence, nature, and importance of intentions. I assert that originalists, just as much as many traditionally considered opposed to them, are intentionalists because they rely on mental state theories of intention. Tracking debates in the philosophy of action and literary theory, I also suggest that it is helpful to talk of intentionalism because it more explicitly relates legal concerns to the interpretive concerns common to these other fields. My approach also engages the work of others who, in various ways, have earlier discussed in the legal literature the broader context and implications of intentionalism, and especially that of Heidi Hurd on the ubiquity of intentionalism in legal interpretation. Although I do not here limn or endorse a specific interpretive methodology, my conclusions do extend to asserting that originalism and textualism, instead of being complementary, are at direct odds with one another – with originalism being a form of intentionalism and textualism explicitly rejecting intentionalism.","PeriodicalId":431450,"journal":{"name":"Jurisprudence & Legal Philosophy","volume":"133 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2009-05-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"132692959","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
From the Rule of Law to the Constitutionalist Makeover: Changing European Conceptions of Public International Law 从法治到宪政转型:欧洲国际公法观念的变迁
Pub Date : 2009-05-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1397249
A. Somek
The article identifies major characteristics of how public international law has been endorsed by European legal scholars. Prominent among these is the repeated effort to pinpoint the deficiency of public international law as it stands and to suggest improvements. The article tries to identify a chain of substitutions with regard to what is taken to be the core problem. It can be shown how attempts to overcome one reveal another. The chain of substitution, reconstructed in this article, begins with decentralization and results in the realization that public international law is inadequate from a constitutional point of view. Not surprisingly, the constitutionalization of public international law becomes an issue. However, it turns out that some current ideas regarding the constitutionalization of public international law, rather than taking constitution-making seriously, appear to be idealistic refractions of the real absorption of legality by administrative processes. Rather than offering a solution, they may very well be part of the constitutional deficiency that they claim to resolve.
本文确定了欧洲法律学者支持国际公法的主要特征。其中最突出的是一再努力查明目前国际公法的不足之处并提出改进建议。本文试图找出一个关于什么是核心问题的替代链。我们可以看到,试图克服一个会暴露另一个。本文重构的替代链始于权力下放,并导致人们认识到,从宪法的角度来看,国际公法是不充分的。毫不奇怪,国际公法的宪法化成为一个问题。然而,目前关于国际公法宪法化的一些观点,与其说是认真对待宪法的制定,不如说是对行政程序真正吸收合法性的理想主义折射。他们不是提供解决方案,而是很可能成为他们声称要解决的宪法缺陷的一部分。
{"title":"From the Rule of Law to the Constitutionalist Makeover: Changing European Conceptions of Public International Law","authors":"A. Somek","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1397249","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1397249","url":null,"abstract":"The article identifies major characteristics of how public international law has been endorsed by European legal scholars. Prominent among these is the repeated effort to pinpoint the deficiency of public international law as it stands and to suggest improvements. The article tries to identify a chain of substitutions with regard to what is taken to be the core problem. It can be shown how attempts to overcome one reveal another. The chain of substitution, reconstructed in this article, begins with decentralization and results in the realization that public international law is inadequate from a constitutional point of view. Not surprisingly, the constitutionalization of public international law becomes an issue. However, it turns out that some current ideas regarding the constitutionalization of public international law, rather than taking constitution-making seriously, appear to be idealistic refractions of the real absorption of legality by administrative processes. Rather than offering a solution, they may very well be part of the constitutional deficiency that they claim to resolve.","PeriodicalId":431450,"journal":{"name":"Jurisprudence & Legal Philosophy","volume":"266 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2009-05-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"122932875","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 6
Warrantless Wiretapping, FISA Reform, and the Lessons of Public Liberty: A Comment on Holmes' Jorde Lecture 无证窃听、FISA改革和公共自由的教训:霍尔姆斯的Jorde演讲评析
Pub Date : 2009-04-23 DOI: 10.15779/Z389D80
P. Schwartz
This Essay responds to Stephen Holmes’ Jorde Lecture, which was delivered at Boalt Hall on November 5, 2007. It builds on his model of “public liberty” by discussing how private liberty, and information privacy in particular, is a precondition for public liberty. For Holmes, private liberty is largely a negative right - a right to be free from governmental interference. In contrast, this Essay considers privacy to be an element of public rights. Participation in a democracy requires individuals to have an underlying capacity for self-determination, which requires some personal privacy.This Essay analyzes a number of Holmesian concepts through the lens of the recent amendment of the Foreign Intelligence Surveillance Act (FISA). In Part I, I describe the background of FISA, the National Security Agency’s (NSA) warrantless surveillance program in violation of this statute, and the amendments to this law in the Protect America Act of 2007, a short term statutory “fix” that has expired, and the FISA Amendments Act of 2008, which remains in effect. In Part II, I turn to an analysis of the challenges to private and public liberty posed by the NSA’s surveillance. I organize this Part around three topics: (1) past wisdom as codified in law; (2) the impact of secrecy on government behavior; and (3) institutional lessons. As we shall see, a Holmesian search for the wisdom previously collected in law proves quite difficult. FISA regulated some aspects of intelligence gathering and left the intelligence community entirely free to engage in others. Over time, moreover, technological innovations and altered national security concerns transformed the implications of the past policy landscape. As a result, the toughest questions, which concern surveillance of foreign-to-domestic communications, do not receive an easy answer from the past. Regarding the impact of secrecy on government behavior, the analysis is, at least initially, more straightforward. As Holmes discusses, the Bush administration was adept at keeping secrets not only from the public and other branches of government, but from itself. It is also striking how little Congress knew about NSA activities while amending FISA. The larger lessons, however, prove yet more complicated: strong structural and political factors are likely to limit the involvement of Congress and courts in this area. This Essay concludes by confronting these institutional lessons and evaluating elements of a response that would improve the government’s performance by crafting new informational and deliberative structures for it.
这篇文章是对Stephen Holmes于2007年11月5日在Boalt Hall发表的Jorde演讲的回应。该书以他的“公共自由”模型为基础,讨论了私人自由,尤其是信息隐私,是公共自由的先决条件。对霍姆斯来说,私人自由在很大程度上是一种消极权利——一种不受政府干预的权利。与此相反,本文认为隐私权是公共权利的一个要素。参与民主需要个人具有潜在的自决能力,这需要一些个人隐私。本文通过最近修订的《外国情报监视法》(FISA)来分析霍尔姆斯的一些概念。在第一部分中,我描述了FISA的背景,国家安全局(NSA)违反本法规的未经授权的监视项目,以及2007年《保护美国法》(一个已过期的短期法定“修复”)和2008年《FISA修正案法》(仍然有效)对该法的修订。在第二部分,我转而分析国家安全局的监视对私人和公共自由构成的挑战。我将围绕三个主题来组织这一部分:(1)成文法律的过去智慧;(2)保密对政府行为的影响;(3)制度教训。正如我们将看到的那样,福尔摩斯式地寻找先前收集在法律中的智慧被证明是相当困难的。FISA规范了情报收集的某些方面,并让情报界完全自由地从事其他方面的工作。此外,随着时间的推移,技术创新和国家安全关切的改变改变了过去政策格局的含义。因此,最棘手的问题——涉及监控外国与国内的通信——从过去得不到一个简单的答案。关于保密对政府行为的影响,至少在一开始,分析更为直接。正如霍尔姆斯所讨论的,布什政府不仅善于对公众和其他政府部门保密,而且善于对自己保密。同样令人吃惊的是,国会在修改FISA时对NSA的活动知之甚少。然而,更大的教训证明更为复杂:强大的结构和政治因素可能会限制国会和法院在这一领域的参与。本文的结论是面对这些制度教训,并评估应对措施的要素,通过为政府制定新的信息和审议结构来改善政府的表现。
{"title":"Warrantless Wiretapping, FISA Reform, and the Lessons of Public Liberty: A Comment on Holmes' Jorde Lecture","authors":"P. Schwartz","doi":"10.15779/Z389D80","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.15779/Z389D80","url":null,"abstract":"This Essay responds to Stephen Holmes’ Jorde Lecture, which was delivered at Boalt Hall on November 5, 2007. It builds on his model of “public liberty” by discussing how private liberty, and information privacy in particular, is a precondition for public liberty. For Holmes, private liberty is largely a negative right - a right to be free from governmental interference. In contrast, this Essay considers privacy to be an element of public rights. Participation in a democracy requires individuals to have an underlying capacity for self-determination, which requires some personal privacy.This Essay analyzes a number of Holmesian concepts through the lens of the recent amendment of the Foreign Intelligence Surveillance Act (FISA). In Part I, I describe the background of FISA, the National Security Agency’s (NSA) warrantless surveillance program in violation of this statute, and the amendments to this law in the Protect America Act of 2007, a short term statutory “fix” that has expired, and the FISA Amendments Act of 2008, which remains in effect. In Part II, I turn to an analysis of the challenges to private and public liberty posed by the NSA’s surveillance. I organize this Part around three topics: (1) past wisdom as codified in law; (2) the impact of secrecy on government behavior; and (3) institutional lessons. As we shall see, a Holmesian search for the wisdom previously collected in law proves quite difficult. FISA regulated some aspects of intelligence gathering and left the intelligence community entirely free to engage in others. Over time, moreover, technological innovations and altered national security concerns transformed the implications of the past policy landscape. As a result, the toughest questions, which concern surveillance of foreign-to-domestic communications, do not receive an easy answer from the past. Regarding the impact of secrecy on government behavior, the analysis is, at least initially, more straightforward. As Holmes discusses, the Bush administration was adept at keeping secrets not only from the public and other branches of government, but from itself. It is also striking how little Congress knew about NSA activities while amending FISA. The larger lessons, however, prove yet more complicated: strong structural and political factors are likely to limit the involvement of Congress and courts in this area. This Essay concludes by confronting these institutional lessons and evaluating elements of a response that would improve the government’s performance by crafting new informational and deliberative structures for it.","PeriodicalId":431450,"journal":{"name":"Jurisprudence & Legal Philosophy","volume":"23 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2009-04-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"115336615","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Theorizing the Charitable Tax Subsidies: The Role of Distributive Justice 慈善税收补贴的理论化:分配正义的作用
Pub Date : 2009-02-24 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.1348772
M. Fleischer
Distributive justice plays a starring role in many fundamental tax policy debates, from the marginal rate structure to the choice of base to the propriety of wealth transfer taxes. In contrast, current tax scholarship on the charitable tax subsidies generally either ignores or explicitly disavows distributive justice concerns. Instead, it focuses on the efficiency and pluralism-enhancing advantages of having charities provide public goods instead of or in addition to the government. While identifying these advantages is a necessary and important contribution to our understanding of charitable giving policy, avoidance of distributive justice concerns ignores the very purpose of charity: voluntary redistribution. After all, it's called the charitable deduction, not the public goods deduction. As a result, the current body of work on the charitable tax subsidies is incomplete: It purposely under-theorizes "the good" in order to avoid making value judgments about which projects should be subsidized. Although this sounds appealing, completely avoiding such judgments is both impossible and counter-productive. Current scholarship thus over under-theorizes the good, creating confusion about the charitable tax subsidies in both theory and practice. Explicitly addressing distributive justice - in addition to pluralism and efficiency - will enhance our understanding of the subsidies for three reasons. First, existing scholarship - which generally ignores distributive justice issues - is incomplete and inconsistent for so doing. It is incomplete because it does not adequately identify which projects deserve a subsidy; it is inconsistent because it implicitly contains value judgments that have distributive justice implications but that are unacknowledged (and often disavowed) by their proponents. Second, popular criticisms of the charitable tax subsidies raise distributive justice issues that have not been adequately addressed. And lastly, the law governing the charitable tax subsidies is itself confused on the role of distributive justice. Extending our understanding of the subsidies in this manner has three benefits. First, it will help the efficiency- and pluralism-minded scholars better address how to structure the tax subsidies to best promote those benefits. Second, a better understanding of distributive justice will help us assess existing justice-related criticisms of the subsidies. And lastly, because our society currently spends a great deal of resources subsidizing charity, such a discussion will help us allocate our resources in a more systematic fashion.
从边际税率结构到税基选择,再到财富转移税的适当性,分配公正在许多基本税收政策辩论中扮演着重要角色。相比之下,目前关于慈善性税收补贴的税收学术研究普遍忽视或明确否认分配正义问题。相反,它关注的是由慈善机构代替政府或在政府之外提供公共产品的效率和促进多元化的优势。虽然认识到这些优势对我们理解慈善捐赠政策有必要和重要的贡献,但回避分配正义问题忽视了慈善的真正目的:自愿再分配。毕竟,这被称为慈善扣除,而不是公共物品扣除。因此,目前关于慈善税收补贴的工作是不完整的:它故意低估了“好”的理论化,以避免对哪些项目应该得到补贴做出价值判断。虽然这听起来很吸引人,但完全避免这样的判断既不可能,也会适得其反。因此,目前的学术研究对善的理论化程度过低,在理论和实践上都造成了对慈善税收补贴的困惑。除了多元主义和效率之外,明确解决分配正义问题将增进我们对补贴的理解,原因有三。首先,现有的学术研究——通常忽略了分配正义问题——在这方面是不完整和不一致的。它是不完整的,因为它没有充分确定哪些项目值得补贴;它是不一致的,因为它隐含地包含了价值判断,这些价值判断具有分配正义的含义,但它们的支持者不承认(通常是否认)。其次,对慈善性税收补贴的普遍批评引发了分配正义问题,而这些问题尚未得到充分解决。最后,管理慈善税收补贴的法律本身就对分配正义的作用感到困惑。以这种方式扩大我们对补贴的理解有三个好处。首先,它将有助于效率和多元化思想的学者更好地解决如何构建税收补贴以最好地促进这些利益。其次,更好地理解分配正义将有助于我们评估现有的与补贴正义相关的批评。最后,因为我们的社会目前花费了大量的资源来资助慈善事业,这样的讨论将有助于我们更系统地分配我们的资源。
{"title":"Theorizing the Charitable Tax Subsidies: The Role of Distributive Justice","authors":"M. Fleischer","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.1348772","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1348772","url":null,"abstract":"Distributive justice plays a starring role in many fundamental tax policy debates, from the marginal rate structure to the choice of base to the propriety of wealth transfer taxes. In contrast, current tax scholarship on the charitable tax subsidies generally either ignores or explicitly disavows distributive justice concerns. Instead, it focuses on the efficiency and pluralism-enhancing advantages of having charities provide public goods instead of or in addition to the government. While identifying these advantages is a necessary and important contribution to our understanding of charitable giving policy, avoidance of distributive justice concerns ignores the very purpose of charity: voluntary redistribution. After all, it's called the charitable deduction, not the public goods deduction. As a result, the current body of work on the charitable tax subsidies is incomplete: It purposely under-theorizes \"the good\" in order to avoid making value judgments about which projects should be subsidized. Although this sounds appealing, completely avoiding such judgments is both impossible and counter-productive. Current scholarship thus over under-theorizes the good, creating confusion about the charitable tax subsidies in both theory and practice. Explicitly addressing distributive justice - in addition to pluralism and efficiency - will enhance our understanding of the subsidies for three reasons. First, existing scholarship - which generally ignores distributive justice issues - is incomplete and inconsistent for so doing. It is incomplete because it does not adequately identify which projects deserve a subsidy; it is inconsistent because it implicitly contains value judgments that have distributive justice implications but that are unacknowledged (and often disavowed) by their proponents. Second, popular criticisms of the charitable tax subsidies raise distributive justice issues that have not been adequately addressed. And lastly, the law governing the charitable tax subsidies is itself confused on the role of distributive justice. Extending our understanding of the subsidies in this manner has three benefits. First, it will help the efficiency- and pluralism-minded scholars better address how to structure the tax subsidies to best promote those benefits. Second, a better understanding of distributive justice will help us assess existing justice-related criticisms of the subsidies. And lastly, because our society currently spends a great deal of resources subsidizing charity, such a discussion will help us allocate our resources in a more systematic fashion.","PeriodicalId":431450,"journal":{"name":"Jurisprudence & Legal Philosophy","volume":"64 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2009-02-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"127540582","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 15
Locke for the Masses: Property Rights and the Products of Collective Creativity 洛克为大众服务:产权与集体创造的产物
Pub Date : 2008-12-12 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1323408
R. Merges
In this brief Idea piece, I describe how the labor theory of property rights associated with John Locke might apply to projects such as WikiPedia, which aggregate many small contributions by dispersed contributors. These works of "collaborative creativity" represent very significant investments of time and resources, yet do not fit comfortably within the individually-oriented framework of traditional Lockean analysis. Locke's central insight - that laboring on unowned resources ought (with exceptions and qualifications) to justify appropriation - suggests the desirability of granting some form of property interest over the products of collaborative creativity. I also explore a few practical issues that would have to be resolved to implement such a right.
在这篇简短的思想文章中,我描述了与约翰·洛克相关的产权劳动理论如何应用于维基百科等项目,这些项目汇集了分散贡献者的许多小贡献。这些“协作创造力”的作品代表了大量的时间和资源投入,但并不适合传统洛克分析的个人导向框架。洛克的核心见解——对无主资源的劳动应该(除了例外和限定条件)证明占有是合理的——表明了对合作创造的产品授予某种形式的财产利益的可取之处。我还探讨了实施这一权利必须解决的几个实际问题。
{"title":"Locke for the Masses: Property Rights and the Products of Collective Creativity","authors":"R. Merges","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1323408","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1323408","url":null,"abstract":"In this brief Idea piece, I describe how the labor theory of property rights associated with John Locke might apply to projects such as WikiPedia, which aggregate many small contributions by dispersed contributors. These works of \"collaborative creativity\" represent very significant investments of time and resources, yet do not fit comfortably within the individually-oriented framework of traditional Lockean analysis. Locke's central insight - that laboring on unowned resources ought (with exceptions and qualifications) to justify appropriation - suggests the desirability of granting some form of property interest over the products of collaborative creativity. I also explore a few practical issues that would have to be resolved to implement such a right.","PeriodicalId":431450,"journal":{"name":"Jurisprudence & Legal Philosophy","volume":"7 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2008-12-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"116843256","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 23
期刊
Jurisprudence & Legal Philosophy
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1