民主教育和好奇心

IF 0.7 Q3 EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH Ethics and Education Pub Date : 2023-10-05 DOI:10.1080/17449642.2023.2266978
Marianna Papastephanou
{"title":"民主教育和好奇心","authors":"Marianna Papastephanou","doi":"10.1080/17449642.2023.2266978","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTCuriosity is not prominent in investigations on democratic development. Nor is curiosity discussed in democratic education discourses. However, this article contributes to the present Special Issue the idea that the connection of curiosity and democracy should not be ignored. First, I show that curiosity’s connection with democracy has, regrettably, been largely bypassed in fields related to democratic theory and pedagogy. Then, I elaborate on how the emerging scholarship on curiosity’s intricacies makes it easier to perceive how fruitful the study of curiosity’s role in democratic theory and education would be. In light of this recent rethinking of curiosity, I claim that studying a complex and ambiguous notion of curiosity (along with an equally complex and ambiguous epistemic restraint) is important for studying and advancing democracy and for enriching democratic citizenship education.KEYWORDS: curiosity politicscitizenshiprestrainteducationpublic spacetotalitarianism Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. Thought through, this critical point also outlines how I mean democracy in this article.2. On the neglected significance of epistemic restraint and its connection with curiosity and education see Papastephanou (Citation2016).3. Methodologically, I would suggest that a conception of curiosity that would do justice to curiosity’s ambiguities and complexities be developed through an interplay of deconstructive and reconstructive as well as perspectival and stereoscopic techniques. Some indication of this will be given sporadically in this article, but any fuller unpacking of these techniques is beyond the article’s limits.4. The assumption of scientific disinterestedness had blocked the prospect of grasping the political operations of curiosity, some of which have been repugnantly colonial and anti-democratic all along, from antiquity to the present (Papastephanou Citation2019, Citation2022). The focus of theoretical accounts of curiosity on individuals had also blocked explicit theorizations of the possibility of curiosity being social, as we shall see later on.5. Cho’s critique of Freire’s ontology of curiosity (and Lewis’ endorsement of this critique) could be contested from Zurn’s (Citation2023a) perspective and alternative reading of that ontology, but this is beyond the scope of this paper.6. However, neither Huysmans (Citation2016) theorizes the connection of curiosity and democracy beyond issues of surveillance. Moreover, he uses the adjective ‘democratic’ to qualify curiosity somewhat axiomatically, and a risk in this is that premodifiers such as ‘democratic’ may sanitize curiosity and obscure some of its bad politics.7. For this point, I am indebted to the journal’s anonymous reviewers. On the prospect of a rethought curiosity becoming conducive to a rethought democratic education that will benefit from both disruptive and deliberative models of democracy, see also my comment on Leiviskä (Citation2020) in another section of this article.8. As I have discussed this point elsewhere (Papastephanou Citation2023a), here I will leave at that.9. Huysmans (Citation2016) uses ‘democratic curiosity’ as a good thing and, though he avoids turning into a slogan, the risk of other theories developing a hollow rhetoric around it remains, if the vigilance and caution that I am suggesting here is missing.10. On the meaning and theoretical significance of the extitutional in relation to ‘democratic curiosity’ see (Huysmans Citation2016).11. For more on how I define the stereoscopic in more detail and how I apply it to the complex notion of justice, see Papastephanou (Citation2021).12. Discursive justice denotes a proper provision of discursive space to all positions, that is, one’s giving attention to, and treating fairly, the claims of all people affected by an idea, a measure or a practice.13. Certain questions are not asked not quite because the questions are unworthy or show an idle or dubious curiosity but because asking them comes with a social and scholarly cost and unfair labelling or awkward silence that most researchers are not willing to shoulder.14. This comprises “questions such as: ‘What is the world?’ ‘What is the philosophical, theological, and political history of this concept of world”’ (Derrida Citation2005, 107–8).15. One such totalitarian risk is disturbingly also evident when Europe and its states now handle in a despicably punitive and unacceptably legalist way, not only preposterous or reactionary views, but even views that are progressive, rational and defend democratic human rights. Such a totalitarian attitude is noticeable in the decision of Cyprus to extradite the Kurdish activist and politician Kenan Ayaz to Germany. Germany has demanded (issuing a European warrant), again to totalitarian effect, this extradition on supposed terrorism charges, although Ayaz has only aired views in support of freedom and human rights against violations of them occurring in Turkey. Media all over Europe have met the event of his extradition with a most telling silence, and the whole issue has not managed to excite the curiosity of European ‘cosmopolitans,’ ‘progressives’ and activists of all kinds. Because there is no space here to argue out the case of Ayaz, see https://www.andrej-hunko.de/presse/pressespiegel/5545-europaabgeordnete-fordern-freilassung-von-kenan-ayaz.16. Kalli Drousioti (Citation2022b) provides an informative account of the Cyprus issue and its context as well as offers a pertinent critique of relativist and poly-prismatic arguments, hence I refer to this source and proceed with the illustration presently.17. In a democratic life, and from a psychological and ethical perspective, tolerance is also needed toward the ‘incurious,’ those who are indifferent to, unwilling to know about, a claim of justice.","PeriodicalId":45613,"journal":{"name":"Ethics and Education","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.7000,"publicationDate":"2023-10-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Democratic education and curiosity\",\"authors\":\"Marianna Papastephanou\",\"doi\":\"10.1080/17449642.2023.2266978\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"ABSTRACTCuriosity is not prominent in investigations on democratic development. Nor is curiosity discussed in democratic education discourses. However, this article contributes to the present Special Issue the idea that the connection of curiosity and democracy should not be ignored. First, I show that curiosity’s connection with democracy has, regrettably, been largely bypassed in fields related to democratic theory and pedagogy. Then, I elaborate on how the emerging scholarship on curiosity’s intricacies makes it easier to perceive how fruitful the study of curiosity’s role in democratic theory and education would be. In light of this recent rethinking of curiosity, I claim that studying a complex and ambiguous notion of curiosity (along with an equally complex and ambiguous epistemic restraint) is important for studying and advancing democracy and for enriching democratic citizenship education.KEYWORDS: curiosity politicscitizenshiprestrainteducationpublic spacetotalitarianism Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. Thought through, this critical point also outlines how I mean democracy in this article.2. On the neglected significance of epistemic restraint and its connection with curiosity and education see Papastephanou (Citation2016).3. Methodologically, I would suggest that a conception of curiosity that would do justice to curiosity’s ambiguities and complexities be developed through an interplay of deconstructive and reconstructive as well as perspectival and stereoscopic techniques. Some indication of this will be given sporadically in this article, but any fuller unpacking of these techniques is beyond the article’s limits.4. The assumption of scientific disinterestedness had blocked the prospect of grasping the political operations of curiosity, some of which have been repugnantly colonial and anti-democratic all along, from antiquity to the present (Papastephanou Citation2019, Citation2022). The focus of theoretical accounts of curiosity on individuals had also blocked explicit theorizations of the possibility of curiosity being social, as we shall see later on.5. Cho’s critique of Freire’s ontology of curiosity (and Lewis’ endorsement of this critique) could be contested from Zurn’s (Citation2023a) perspective and alternative reading of that ontology, but this is beyond the scope of this paper.6. However, neither Huysmans (Citation2016) theorizes the connection of curiosity and democracy beyond issues of surveillance. Moreover, he uses the adjective ‘democratic’ to qualify curiosity somewhat axiomatically, and a risk in this is that premodifiers such as ‘democratic’ may sanitize curiosity and obscure some of its bad politics.7. For this point, I am indebted to the journal’s anonymous reviewers. On the prospect of a rethought curiosity becoming conducive to a rethought democratic education that will benefit from both disruptive and deliberative models of democracy, see also my comment on Leiviskä (Citation2020) in another section of this article.8. As I have discussed this point elsewhere (Papastephanou Citation2023a), here I will leave at that.9. Huysmans (Citation2016) uses ‘democratic curiosity’ as a good thing and, though he avoids turning into a slogan, the risk of other theories developing a hollow rhetoric around it remains, if the vigilance and caution that I am suggesting here is missing.10. On the meaning and theoretical significance of the extitutional in relation to ‘democratic curiosity’ see (Huysmans Citation2016).11. For more on how I define the stereoscopic in more detail and how I apply it to the complex notion of justice, see Papastephanou (Citation2021).12. Discursive justice denotes a proper provision of discursive space to all positions, that is, one’s giving attention to, and treating fairly, the claims of all people affected by an idea, a measure or a practice.13. Certain questions are not asked not quite because the questions are unworthy or show an idle or dubious curiosity but because asking them comes with a social and scholarly cost and unfair labelling or awkward silence that most researchers are not willing to shoulder.14. This comprises “questions such as: ‘What is the world?’ ‘What is the philosophical, theological, and political history of this concept of world”’ (Derrida Citation2005, 107–8).15. One such totalitarian risk is disturbingly also evident when Europe and its states now handle in a despicably punitive and unacceptably legalist way, not only preposterous or reactionary views, but even views that are progressive, rational and defend democratic human rights. Such a totalitarian attitude is noticeable in the decision of Cyprus to extradite the Kurdish activist and politician Kenan Ayaz to Germany. Germany has demanded (issuing a European warrant), again to totalitarian effect, this extradition on supposed terrorism charges, although Ayaz has only aired views in support of freedom and human rights against violations of them occurring in Turkey. Media all over Europe have met the event of his extradition with a most telling silence, and the whole issue has not managed to excite the curiosity of European ‘cosmopolitans,’ ‘progressives’ and activists of all kinds. Because there is no space here to argue out the case of Ayaz, see https://www.andrej-hunko.de/presse/pressespiegel/5545-europaabgeordnete-fordern-freilassung-von-kenan-ayaz.16. Kalli Drousioti (Citation2022b) provides an informative account of the Cyprus issue and its context as well as offers a pertinent critique of relativist and poly-prismatic arguments, hence I refer to this source and proceed with the illustration presently.17. In a democratic life, and from a psychological and ethical perspective, tolerance is also needed toward the ‘incurious,’ those who are indifferent to, unwilling to know about, a claim of justice.\",\"PeriodicalId\":45613,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Ethics and Education\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.7000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-10-05\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Ethics and Education\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1080/17449642.2023.2266978\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Ethics and Education","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17449642.2023.2266978","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

摘要好奇心在民主发展的研究中并不突出。在民主教育课程中也不讨论好奇心。然而,这篇文章为本期特刊提供了一个观点,即好奇心与民主的联系不应被忽视。首先,我指出,在与民主理论和教育学相关的领域中,好奇心与民主的联系很遗憾地在很大程度上被忽略了。然后,我详细阐述了关于好奇心的复杂性的新兴学术如何使人们更容易认识到好奇心在民主理论和教育中的作用的研究将是多么富有成效。鉴于最近对好奇心的重新思考,我认为研究一个复杂而模糊的好奇心概念(以及同样复杂而模糊的认知约束)对于研究和推进民主以及丰富民主公民教育非常重要。关键词:好奇心政治公民约束教育公共空间极权主义披露声明作者未报告潜在的利益冲突。经过深思熟虑,这一关键观点也概括了我在这篇文章中所说的民主。关于认知约束的被忽视的意义及其与好奇心和教育的联系,见Papastephanou (Citation2016)。在方法论上,我建议通过解构和重建以及透视和立体技术的相互作用来发展一种能够公正地对待好奇心的模糊性和复杂性的好奇心概念。这方面的一些指示将在本文中偶尔给出,但对这些技术的任何更全面的揭示都超出了本文的限制。科学无私的假设阻碍了对好奇心的政治操作的把握,其中一些从古代到现在一直是令人反感的殖民和反民主的(Papastephanou Citation2019, Citation2022)。正如我们将在后面看到的那样,对个人好奇心的理论描述也阻碍了对好奇心具有社会性可能性的明确理论。Cho对Freire好奇心本体论的批判(以及Lewis对这一批判的认可)可能会受到Zurn (Citation2023a)的观点和对该本体论的另一种解读的质疑,但这超出了本文的范围。然而,Huysmans (Citation2016)都没有将好奇心和民主的联系理论化,超越了监视问题。此外,他用“民主的”这个形容词来描述好奇心,这有点不证自明,这样做的一个风险是,像“民主的”这样的前缀可能会净化好奇心,掩盖它的一些不良政治。在这一点上,我感谢《华尔街日报》的匿名审稿人。关于重新思考的好奇心有助于重新思考的民主教育的前景,这种教育将受益于民主的破坏性和审议模式,参见本文另一部分中我对Leiviskä (Citation2020)的评论。正如我在其他地方(Papastephanou Citation2023a)讨论过的那样,这里我将就此打住。Huysmans (Citation2016)将“民主的好奇心”作为一件好事,尽管他避免把它变成一个口号,但如果我在这里建议的警惕和谨慎缺失,其他理论围绕它发展空洞修辞的风险仍然存在。关于与“民主好奇心”相关的extitution的意义和理论意义,见(Huysmans Citation2016)。有关我如何更详细地定义立体观以及如何将其应用于复杂的正义概念的更多信息,请参见Papastephanou (Citation2021)。13.话语正义指的是为所有立场提供适当的话语空间,也就是说,一个人要注意并公平地对待所有受一种观念、一项措施或一种实践影响的人的主张。有些问题不被问,并不完全是因为这些问题不值得问,或者表现出一种无聊或可疑的好奇心,而是因为问这些问题会带来社会和学术上的代价,还会被贴上不公平的标签,或者尴尬的沉默,这是大多数研究人员不愿承担的。这包括“这样的问题:‘世界是什么?“这个世界概念的哲学、神学和政治史是什么?”(Derrida citation2005,107 - 8)。令人不安的是,当欧洲及其国家现在以一种卑鄙的惩罚性和不可接受的法律主义方式处理问题时,这种极权主义的风险也很明显,不仅荒谬或反动的观点,而且甚至是进步的、理性的和捍卫民主人权的观点。这种极权主义的态度在塞浦路斯决定将库尔德活动家和政治家凯南·阿亚兹引渡到德国时是显而易见的。 德国以所谓的恐怖主义罪名要求引渡(签发欧洲逮捕令),这又是一种极权主义的效果,尽管阿亚兹只是发表了支持自由和人权的观点,反对土耳其发生的侵犯自由和人权的行为。整个欧洲的媒体都对他的引渡事件保持沉默,整个事件并没有激起欧洲“世界主义者”、“进步人士”和各种积极分子的好奇心。因为这里没有空间来讨论Ayaz的情况,请参阅https://www.andrej-hunko.de/presse/pressespiegel/5545-europaabgeordnete-fordern-freilassung-von-kenan-ayaz.16。Kalli Drousioti (Citation2022b)对塞浦路斯问题及其背景进行了翔实的描述,并对相对主义和多棱镜主义的论点进行了恰当的批评,因此我将参考这一来源,并在此继续说明。在民主的生活中,从心理和伦理的角度来看,对“不好奇”的人也需要宽容,这些人对正义的要求漠不关心,不愿了解。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Democratic education and curiosity
ABSTRACTCuriosity is not prominent in investigations on democratic development. Nor is curiosity discussed in democratic education discourses. However, this article contributes to the present Special Issue the idea that the connection of curiosity and democracy should not be ignored. First, I show that curiosity’s connection with democracy has, regrettably, been largely bypassed in fields related to democratic theory and pedagogy. Then, I elaborate on how the emerging scholarship on curiosity’s intricacies makes it easier to perceive how fruitful the study of curiosity’s role in democratic theory and education would be. In light of this recent rethinking of curiosity, I claim that studying a complex and ambiguous notion of curiosity (along with an equally complex and ambiguous epistemic restraint) is important for studying and advancing democracy and for enriching democratic citizenship education.KEYWORDS: curiosity politicscitizenshiprestrainteducationpublic spacetotalitarianism Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. Thought through, this critical point also outlines how I mean democracy in this article.2. On the neglected significance of epistemic restraint and its connection with curiosity and education see Papastephanou (Citation2016).3. Methodologically, I would suggest that a conception of curiosity that would do justice to curiosity’s ambiguities and complexities be developed through an interplay of deconstructive and reconstructive as well as perspectival and stereoscopic techniques. Some indication of this will be given sporadically in this article, but any fuller unpacking of these techniques is beyond the article’s limits.4. The assumption of scientific disinterestedness had blocked the prospect of grasping the political operations of curiosity, some of which have been repugnantly colonial and anti-democratic all along, from antiquity to the present (Papastephanou Citation2019, Citation2022). The focus of theoretical accounts of curiosity on individuals had also blocked explicit theorizations of the possibility of curiosity being social, as we shall see later on.5. Cho’s critique of Freire’s ontology of curiosity (and Lewis’ endorsement of this critique) could be contested from Zurn’s (Citation2023a) perspective and alternative reading of that ontology, but this is beyond the scope of this paper.6. However, neither Huysmans (Citation2016) theorizes the connection of curiosity and democracy beyond issues of surveillance. Moreover, he uses the adjective ‘democratic’ to qualify curiosity somewhat axiomatically, and a risk in this is that premodifiers such as ‘democratic’ may sanitize curiosity and obscure some of its bad politics.7. For this point, I am indebted to the journal’s anonymous reviewers. On the prospect of a rethought curiosity becoming conducive to a rethought democratic education that will benefit from both disruptive and deliberative models of democracy, see also my comment on Leiviskä (Citation2020) in another section of this article.8. As I have discussed this point elsewhere (Papastephanou Citation2023a), here I will leave at that.9. Huysmans (Citation2016) uses ‘democratic curiosity’ as a good thing and, though he avoids turning into a slogan, the risk of other theories developing a hollow rhetoric around it remains, if the vigilance and caution that I am suggesting here is missing.10. On the meaning and theoretical significance of the extitutional in relation to ‘democratic curiosity’ see (Huysmans Citation2016).11. For more on how I define the stereoscopic in more detail and how I apply it to the complex notion of justice, see Papastephanou (Citation2021).12. Discursive justice denotes a proper provision of discursive space to all positions, that is, one’s giving attention to, and treating fairly, the claims of all people affected by an idea, a measure or a practice.13. Certain questions are not asked not quite because the questions are unworthy or show an idle or dubious curiosity but because asking them comes with a social and scholarly cost and unfair labelling or awkward silence that most researchers are not willing to shoulder.14. This comprises “questions such as: ‘What is the world?’ ‘What is the philosophical, theological, and political history of this concept of world”’ (Derrida Citation2005, 107–8).15. One such totalitarian risk is disturbingly also evident when Europe and its states now handle in a despicably punitive and unacceptably legalist way, not only preposterous or reactionary views, but even views that are progressive, rational and defend democratic human rights. Such a totalitarian attitude is noticeable in the decision of Cyprus to extradite the Kurdish activist and politician Kenan Ayaz to Germany. Germany has demanded (issuing a European warrant), again to totalitarian effect, this extradition on supposed terrorism charges, although Ayaz has only aired views in support of freedom and human rights against violations of them occurring in Turkey. Media all over Europe have met the event of his extradition with a most telling silence, and the whole issue has not managed to excite the curiosity of European ‘cosmopolitans,’ ‘progressives’ and activists of all kinds. Because there is no space here to argue out the case of Ayaz, see https://www.andrej-hunko.de/presse/pressespiegel/5545-europaabgeordnete-fordern-freilassung-von-kenan-ayaz.16. Kalli Drousioti (Citation2022b) provides an informative account of the Cyprus issue and its context as well as offers a pertinent critique of relativist and poly-prismatic arguments, hence I refer to this source and proceed with the illustration presently.17. In a democratic life, and from a psychological and ethical perspective, tolerance is also needed toward the ‘incurious,’ those who are indifferent to, unwilling to know about, a claim of justice.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
Ethics and Education
Ethics and Education EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH-
CiteScore
1.70
自引率
11.10%
发文量
22
期刊最新文献
Transforming relationships. Pedagogical tact as a utopian figure of mediation Tactlessness as condition for teaching tact: educational reflections based on Adorno Theorising education from within pedagogical tact: a matter of singularity, attunement, and rules-as-not-rules Parents as psychological coaches Joint attention, the pedagogical relation and pedagogical tact in the age of digital education
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1