革命不会被理论化:新自由主义思想和过渡问题

Thomas Biebricher
{"title":"革命不会被理论化:新自由主义思想和过渡问题","authors":"Thomas Biebricher","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12713","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Neoliberalism is a notoriously contested term, and even among those who principally subscribe to it, which is mostly its critics, fierce debates persist over its nature, how to study it properly—and whether it is still the appropriate conceptual armament to understand the contemporary world and an arguably emerging “post-neoliberalism” (Davies &amp; Gane, <span>2021</span>). Not only is it controversial how neoliberalism should be defined—a governing rationality in the spirit of Foucault's governmentality lectures (Foucault, <span>2008</span>), a portfolio of certain policies, or a strategy of transnational capital to restore and safeguard profit rates (Harvey, <span>2005</span>)—but also on what level to study it, either that of “actually existing neoliberalism” (Brenner &amp; Theodore, <span>2002</span>; Cahill, <span>2014</span>), a set of theories and arguments, or both.</p><p>My starting point and focus for most of this paper is neoliberal thought as it is represented by the writings of Friedrich Hayek, Milton Friedman, the German ordoliberals, and, importantly, James Buchanan. My aim is to develop a critical account of neoliberal thought that will abstain from explicitly normative criticisms and rather opt for a more indirect but effective and somewhat novel critique that holds neoliberalism to its own standards and shows how it fails to meet them or is pushed into adopting highly questionable positions in the attempt to do so. The argument proceeds as follows: As already suggested, the meaning of neoliberalism is heavily contested, so I will provide the basis of my argument by laying out a brief account of neoliberalism, which relies on a theoretical-historical reconstruction of its context of emergence around the middle of the 20th century. What I conclude from this reconstruction is that we are well-advised not to narrow down neoliberalism too much and not to downplay its internal heterogeneities. Therefore, rather than trying to isolate a number of doctrines or positions as quintessentially neoliberal or even considering them to be the “essence” of neoliberalism, I argue that what unites neoliberal discourse is not a set of positive convictions—although there is some significant overlap in certain areas—but rather a shared <i>problematic</i> that pertains to the preconditions of functioning markets.</p><p>Within that overall problematic, democracy is one of the most pressing problems according to neoliberal thinkers, because virtually all of them agree that it complicates the task of setting up and securing the workings of functioning markets significantly. Still, this basic agreement notwithstanding, neoliberal accounts of democracy display a considerable range of specific diagnoses as to the nature and source of its dysfunctionalities or even pathologies. Accordingly, the second step of the argument is a survey of some selected lines of critique of democracy as they are formulated by leading neoliberals. Among other things, this survey helps us appreciate the heterogeneities of neoliberal thought, but, more importantly for my purposes, it also gives us a sense of the deep reservations neoliberals have with regard to democracy and the trenchant nature of their critique.</p><p>As the specific critiques of democracy vary among neoliberals, so do the suggested remedies and reforms put forward. Accordingly, in the next step, several selected reform proposals are scrutinized that range from the vague call for a “strong state” to Hayek's “model constitution” and the much more specific argument for the introduction of a constitutional balanced-budget amendment, which is a signature demand of Buchanan. What this survey shows us, among other things, is the radical nature of the neoliberal reform proposals, which is important to my overall argument.</p><p>Despite the highly controversial implications of all of these reform proposals, I will deliberately forego engaging them directly based on normative arguments. Instead, my critique focuses on the missing analytical link between neoliberal diagnostics and respective remedies. In order to show this, the fourth and final part of the argument shifts attention to the politics of neoliberal transformation, that is, whether and how this kind of politics is theorized in neoliberal accounts. Again, there is a certain degree of variance between Hayek, Eucken and Buchanan, but the common denominator here is the inability to theorize such a politics without violating the respective assumptions underlying the critical diagnostics or moving beyond the confines of liberal democracy as a condition of implementing such reforms. Thus, the key thesis I wish to defend in the following contends that neoliberal thought lacks any plausible solution to the so-called problem of transition—if they care to reflect on it at all.<sup>1</sup></p><p>These findings lead to several different interpretations with more or less far-reaching implications that are discussed in the concluding section.</p><p>It is commonplace nowadays to note the contested nature and potential vacuity of the term neoliberalism. Faced with these allegations, scholars of neoliberalism often hasten to offer some kind of working definition of neoliberalism, lest they lend credence to suspicions that they are operating with an empty signifier carrying political rather than analytical meaning. Accordingly, a set of policies—typically centered around the agenda of the <i>Washington Consensus</i>—is identified as quintessentially neoliberal, certain ideas or principles are considered to make up its core or essence or, neoliberal is simply that, which members of the <i>Mont Pèlerin Society</i> promulgate, which is an elegant but, upon closer inspection, not entirely convincing way to circumvent the problem (Chomsky, <span>1999</span>; Crouch, <span>2011</span>; Mirowski &amp; Plehwe, <span>2009</span>). On the other hand, there are regular interventions by scholars who emphasize the enormous variability/transformability of neoliberalism and its characteristic ability to form more or less tension-laden amalgamations with other political-intellectual projects, which makes it seemingly impossible, or at least intellectually imprudent, to aim for some hard and fast definition that “fixes” neoliberalism and its meaning(s): “Crisply unambiguous, essentialist definitions of neoliberalism have proved to be incredibly elusive” (Peck, <span>2010</span>, p. 8).</p><p>My own account of neoliberalism will try to strike a balance between overly parsimonious definitional attempts that do not hold up under closer scrutiny and the analytically defeatist solution to dissolve neoliberalism into various neoliberalism<i>s</i> that allegedly share nothing but Wittgensteinian family resemblances. The starting point of my conceptual approach is the observation that neoliberalism has become a truly toxic label these days, and it might therefore be useful to begin with a look at those who did describe themselves, albeit fleetingly and reluctantly, as neoliberals at the time and clarify the intellectual and political agenda that they attached the label “neoliberal” to. In other words, it is necessary to reconstruct the intellectual and political context of neoliberalism's emergence.</p><p>Processes of emergence do not have a single origin but are dispersed, and the same goes for neoliberalism. Nevertheless, it is possible to identify the <i>Colloque Walter Lippmann</i> as the “birth” of neoliberalism in the sense of the first culmination point of these processes and the event at which, for the first time, the term was officially adopted, denoting a shared agenda of the participants, which included not just Hayek, Wilhelm Röpke, and Alexander Rüstow but also Jacques Rueff, Louis Rougier (the convener of the meeting) and, of course, Walter Lippmann himself. At this point, an impressive scholarship on the Colloque exists, so there is no need to go into the details of the proceedings (see instead Burgin, <span>2012</span>; Dardot &amp; Laval, <span>2013</span>; Innset, <span>2020</span>; Reinhoudt &amp; Audier, <span>2018</span>). The overall picture that emerges from them is a liberalism on the defensive that seeks to regain the status of a real contender against its main antagonists, collectivism and—to a lesser degree back then—Keynesianism. In the eyes of practically all of the participants except for Ludwig von Mises, this endeavor presupposed a critical revision of the classical liberal agenda, and, most notably, abandoning simplistic formulas such as “laissez-faire,” or, what some referred to as “Manchesterism.”<sup>2</sup> The neoliberal discourse in formation here was, thus, a far cry from the creed of “self-regulating markets.” Instead, the entire point of the neoliberal approach is to affirm the value of markets against collectivists and Keynesians while insisting that they are not nearly as robust and self-sustaining as large parts of the liberal tradition were inclined to believe up to that point. To put it more pointedly, the market per se was not the solution to all problems; rather, <i>the market itself turned into a problem for neoliberal thought</i> as it was seen as an entity in need of constant care and premised upon a number of preconditions. Therefore, what I call the <i>neoliberal problematic</i> pertains to the preconditions of functioning markets, that is, markets on which the price mechanism reigns as unperturbed as possible.<sup>3</sup></p><p>The irreducible heterogeneities that characterize neoliberal discourse are not the least due to the manifold and at times contradictory ways in which this problematic can be, and has been, spelled out and addressed. Still, what becomes clear is that neoliberal thought might be centered around the notion of markets, but the intellectual energies of those whose work is animated by this problematic, such as Buchanan, Hayek, or the German ordoliberals, inevitably gravitate toward the infrastructure that needs to be put in place and defended against changing adversaries for these markets to function. This is the realm of the social and the political, and therefore it is only stringent for the neoliberals to invest so much time into conceptualizing the state—and democracy.</p><p>When neoliberals talk about democracy, they typically refer to democracy in its existing form, that is, their discourse rarely ventures into philosophical inquiries into the nature and theory of democracy. The predominant form their discourse takes is that of a critique of the respective contemporary forms of representative democracy.</p><p>These respective contexts leave an imprint on the various accounts of democracy, but rather than probing the details of each, in this survey, I will highlight what I consider to be three types of arguments or varieties of the neoliberal critique of democracy that can be analytically distinguished.<sup>4</sup></p><p>The first set of arguments against democracy considered here is particularly prominent in ordoliberal discourse but not exclusive to it:<sup>5</sup> For Wilhelm Röpke and Walter Eucken, the main threat associated with democracy is due to the influence of a new phenomenon on the political scene, namely, the masses. With the rise of mass democracy, the latter have acquired a heretofore unknown leverage over political decisions, or at least this is the assumption under which the ordoliberals in particular are operating. Hence, the problem is not the existence of masses per se but rather their integration into the political process through mass democratic institutions as it unfolds unevenly but steadily over the course of the first half of the 20th century. While the aversion against the masses may seem no more than a variant on the venerable liberal-conservative <i>topos</i> of the tyranny of the majority, there is more to it. The masses are more than a majority. In a discourse crucially shaped by Gustave Le Bon's <i>Crowds</i>, Sigmund Freud's <i>Group Psychology and the Analysis of the Ego</i>, and Jose Ortega Y. Gasset's <i>Revolt of the Masses</i> (who was invited to the <i>Colloque</i> but did not participate), the concept of the masses is psychologically (and at times racially) charged. Masses are attributed with infantilism and general irrationality, which makes them the perfect molding material for demagogues who exploit their uncritical receptiveness and malleability to mobilize them for political projects—typically ones that involve state planning and collectivization from the perspective of the ordoliberals. There is ample textual evidence for this stance, so a few examples may suffice here as the basis of this interpretation. Eucken notes: “But while people can only live in certain orders, the mass tends towards destroying these exact orders” (Eucken, <span>1960</span>, p. 14), and in one of the classic texts inaugurating the ordoliberal tradition from 1932, he laments “that the simultaneous process of democratisation lent the parties, and the masses and interest groups that they organised, much greater influence over the management of the state, and so upon economic policy” (Eucken, 2017, [<span>1932</span>], p. 59). Röpke complements these views: “In all countries, in some less, in others more, society has been ground into a mass of individuals, who have never been so closely herded together and so dependent on each other and yet at the same time they are more rootless, more isolated and more like grains of sand than ever before … All the misery, all the problems of our time have their ultimate roots here…” (Röpke, 1950, [<span>1942</span>], p. 92). Elsewhere, he draws on the above-mentioned social psychological framing of the masses: “As a part of ‘mass’, we are different from what we normally are and should be in healthy circumstances; we are subhuman, herdlike, and the state of society dangerously corresponds to our own” (Röpke, <span>1960</span>, p. 53). And while the most extreme manifestations of what might be called the mass syndrome only occur in what Röpke terms mass in the “acute state,” massification as a permanent condition is hardly less alarming, since it heralds the reign of mediocre brutes at the expense of the “unalterable aristocracy of nature” Röpke hopes to defend (Röpke, <span>1960</span>, p. 55). To sum up this line of criticism, economic policy is simply too important and much too intricate to leave it to the wayward masses, who may not sit in parliaments and run governments in representative democracies, but are still too influential under the conditions of mass democracy, even if only as the object of demagogic agitation and mobilization. If the alliance of these forces had their way, democracy is bound to transform into collectivism, that is, the prime adversary of neoliberal thought: “There is no denying it: the collectivist state is rooted in the masses” (Röpke, <span>1950</span>, p. 86).</p><p>The second line of criticism also owes its classic formulation to another ordoliberal, namely, Alexander Rüstow. The target of this criticism, in addition to the mass dimension of contemporary democracy, is its alleged excessive “pluralism.” Rüstow succinctly sums up the respective core concern: “The democratic, parliamentary structure of some of the economically leading states caused the economic corruption to spread to the internal policy of the state, to the political parties, and to the [sic!] parliamentarism itself. The political parties were slowly transformed into parliamentary agencies of economic pressure groups and were financed by them. … The pathological form of government which developed this way was that of pluralism…” (Rüstow, 2017a, [<span>1942</span>], p. 159). Under conditions of mass democracy, (economic) pressure groups will gain such extraordinary influence that they can almost dictate their will to political parties; the result is marginalization of a vaguely defined common good, which is dissolved into what Eucken calls in no uncertain terms “group anarchy” (Eucken, <span>1960</span>, p. 171). The state, as the presumptive guardian of this common good, is undermined in this process of economic-political clientelism, and Rüstow echoes the scathing criticism of pluralism by Carl Schmitt in his conclusion: “What takes place here accords with the motto: ‘The state as prey’” (Rüstow, 2017b, [<span>1932</span>], p. 147). Under conditions of unchecked pluralism, the state is weakened continuously and the resulting centrifugal dynamics ultimately become unmanageable as the political community falls apart at the hands of particularistic actors emerging from every corner of society.</p><p>Thirdly, there is a strictly contemporary line of criticism that still exhibits some correspondence to the critique of pluralism just sketched. The central theorem underlying this critique is that of rent-seeking, which describes a behavior that seeks to gain some kind of advantage over others not through productive action and competition but rather by lobbying for some kind of special treatment, typically an exemption from certain rules. This idea builds on the insights of game theory and rational choice approaches, according to which individual utility is often maximized when (generally beneficial) rules apply to all but the individual in question, and much of the public choice critique of democracy is built around this basal notion: Under conditions of democracy, the constant demand for special treatment of societal/economic actors is met by an eager supplier in the form of political actors hoping thus to increase their chances of reelection. As one of the cofounders of the public choice tradition, it is a matter of course, that Buchanan puts the rent-seeking theorem at the center of his critique of representative democracy and he is not the only neoliberal who does so: Milton Friedman as well as the later Hayek would occasionally, albeit not systematically, draw on the basic logic of rent-seeking (see Friedman &amp; Friedman, <span>1984</span>). The fundamental problem that allegedly ensues from rent-seeking can be summed up in the following way: Assuming that everybody else engages in rent-seeking, individual rationality dictates that one does so as well because, otherwise, one would be indirectly disadvantaged to the degree that others gain exemptions from rules that still apply to oneself. This means that rent-seeking has an inherently expansive dynamic, and as a general practice, it backfires against the intent of its subjects because even if individual rent-seeking may be successful and provides an advantage, this is vastly outweighed by the multiple disadvantages one has to suffer due to all other rent-seeking activities, assuming they are successful as well. Thus, in pursuit of their individual utility, the actors in a society end up putting themselves at a disadvantage. Just as in the pluralist scenario, it is particularism that prevails here, albeit with a tragic twist. But not only does the “rent-seeking society” (Buchanan et al., <span>1980</span>) harm its current members: Exemptions and other special treatments typically come with some kind of price tag, and since financing through raising taxes is not a realistic option under public choice assumptions, and lawmakers, as well as government, have less and less control over inflation, the prime strategy to pay for rents is through deficits and debt—burdening the almost proverbial “future generations” with financial obligations that they had no say in—arguably a clear violation of the democratic principle of autonomy.</p><p>Finally, there is a line of critique that focuses on the decline of the rule of law in relation to democracy and problematizes the alleged unlimited nature of the latter. The prime exemplar of this line of argument is Friedrich August Hayek, who laid out the various aspects in numerous writings. To be sure, Hayek conceded that democracy, in principle, had its merits: “[I]t is the only convention we have yet discovered to make peaceful change possible” (Hayek, <span>2003</span>, III, p. 137) However, the ideal of democracy and its basic thrust of limiting power became disfigured over time. <i>The Constitution of Liberty</i> already contains the central point of Hayek's critique in a nutshell: “The crucial conception of the doctrinaire democrat is that of popular sovereignty. This means to him that Majority rule is unlimited and unlimitable. The ideal of democracy, originally intended to prevent all arbitrary power, thus becomes the justification for a new arbitrary power” (Hayek, <span>2006</span>, p. 93) The deeper reason for this, according to Hayek, is the erosion of the principle of the rule of law, which he chronicles in <i>the Constitution of Liberty</i> and that involves, prominently, the shedding of any formal prerequisites of what constitutes a genuine law. While in the heyday of liberalism, only those legal rules that were abstract, general, and directed at future behavior were considered to be law in the proper sense of the term, nowadays, Hayek claims, whatever emerges from a legislature is deemed to have the power of law, thus empowering parliaments to engage in the kind of discretionary planning activities that he considers to be harmful on any number of levels. And since there are no longer any formal restrictions on this unrestrained democracy, politicians have no instruments at their disposal to fend off the demands from societal interest groups. “The root of the trouble is, of course, to sum up, that in an unlimited democracy the holders of discretionary powers are forced to use them, whether they wish it or not, to favour particular groups on whose swing vote their powers depend” (Hayek, <span>2003</span>, III, p. 139), concludes Hayek, thus echoing in this regard the second and third lines of critique sketched out above. The main thrust of Hayek's argument, though, is a combination of the critique of democracy as majority rule—spelled out most prominently in <i>The Constitution of Liberty</i> (see Hayek, <span>2006</span>, pp. 90–102)—and the contention that this majority rule is no longer restrained in any meaningful way, thus giving rise to an almost dystopian “unlimited democracy,” which, Hayek thought, would ultimately lead toward totalitarianism: “[T]he whole work [Law, Legislation and Liberty] has been inspired by a growing apprehension about the direction in which the political order of what used to be regarded as the most advanced countries is tending. The growing conviction … that this threatening development towards a totalitarian state is made inevitable by certain deeply entrenched defects of construction of the generally accepted type of ‘democratic’ government has forced me to think through various alternative arrangements” (Hayek, <span>2003</span>, I, p. xx).</p><p>It is to these alternative arrangements in the works of the various neoliberals accounts discussed here that we now turn to.</p><p>It would exceed the scope of this paper to survey every reform proposal submitted by leading neoliberals, so I will merely focus on three more or less specific reform visions being put forward by Buchanan, Hayek as well as the ordoliberals Rüstow and Eucken, respectively, which are to deal with the various shortcomings or pathologies of democracy as they are pinpointed in the diagnoses sketched out in the preceding section.</p><p>Let us begin with what arguably is the most specific proposal to be found in the neoliberal reform portfolio and which came to be a signature demand raised by James Buchanan, although a slightly different version has also been promoted by Milton Friedman. The proposal seeks to address the proclivity to engage in rent-seeking behavior or rather to grant rents to interest groups on behalf of elected officials in order to improve chances at reelection. Buchanan became ever more pessimistic in his assessment of (American) democracy over the years, eventually claiming that “the appeal to the experience of history, and not least to recent events in the United States, does suggest that government, in its current institutional setting, is close to being out of the control of the electorate” (Brennan &amp; Buchanan, 1980, p. 25). In order to come to terms with this deteriorating situation, one of Buchanan's prime suggestions is to pursue the strategy of reining in democratic excesses through tighter controls of the way public expenditures are financed. What democracy requires is a rule that precludes the debt/deficit financing of these outlays, and it should preferably be instituted on the highest possible legal level: a constitutional balanced-budget amendment (Buchanan, <span>1997</span>). The amendment would stipulate rather that all current state expenditures must be financed through actual revenue, be it taxation or otherwise; it would be simply unconstitutional to accrue deficits and debt to finance state expenditures. Given such restrictions, politicians are expected to restrain runaway spending and curtail public expenditure, instead of attempting to rely on a low tax strategy to succeed at the polls. Whether this is a realistic scenario for the impact of such a proposal could be discussed in much greater detail as could be the normative questions related to it, but following the strategy of my critique laid out initially, I will confine myself to this quick exposition and move on to the second and much more elaborate reform proposal, which is Hayek's “model constitution” (Hayek, <span>2003</span>, pp. 105–127).</p><p>The major thrust of Hayek's proposal is a restoration of a strict separation of powers between government and legislature. His diagnosis problematizes the conflation of both, and therefore real bicameralism has to be reinstituted where legislatures only pass laws in the proper sense of the term that circumscribe the room for discretionary action the government enjoys. Of the many noteworthy aspects of this exercise in institutional design, I will only highlight one particularly intriguing aspect that has also drawn considerable criticism: In many respects, the governing assembly hardly differs in its main characteristics from empirically existing governments, although Hayek is seriously entertaining the disenfranchisement of anybody who receives transfers or salaries from the state in governmental elections (Hayek, <span>2003</span>, p. 120). Still, the major target of criticism is the election rules for the <i>legislature</i>, which is arguably the real locus of power in this new institutional set-up as the governmental assembly is to be strictly “bound by the rules of just conduct laid down by the Legislative Assembly” (Hayek, <span>2003</span>, p. 119). Members of the legislature are to be elected in the following way: Each year all citizens of the age of 45 choose their representatives out of the midst of their demographic cohort to replace the contingent of outgoing legislators at the end of their 15-year term. What Hayek has in mind is “an assembly of men and women elected at a relatively mature age for fairly long periods, such as fifteen years, so they would not be re-eligible nor forced to return to earning a living in the market but be assured of continued public employment in such honorific but neutral positions as lay judges, so that during their tenure as legislators they would be neither dependent on party support nor concerned about their personal future” (Hayek, <span>2003</span>, p. 113). The rationale behind this design is clear enough. The long tenure, ineligibility to be reelected, and guaranteed future employment seek to minimize the incentive to engage in rent-seeking behavior on behalf of legislators and, furthermore, the structuring principle of age groups allegedly would preclude the formation of political party affiliations within the legislatures. And even if they were to form, “those leaning towards different parties would be induced to discuss the issues together, and would become conscious that they had the common task of representing the outlook of their generation…” (Hayek, <span>2003</span>, p. 118). Obviously, this radical proposal is open to many criticisms from the perspective of democratic theory, but let us leave this aside and instead turn to the final proposal to be considered here, which is also the least specific, calling for the transformation of statehood into a “strong state” as its main proponents Alexander Rüstow and Walter Eucken refer to it.</p><p>This remedy manifests the stringent conclusion from the critical diagnosis of excessive pluralism, which is prevalent among most ordoliberals; even Röpke, who is less vocal on this theme, reminds his readers that “the immense danger of this unhealthy pluralism is that pressure groups covetously beset the state” and that “any responsible government must examine carefully all the possible means of resisting this pluralistic disintegration of the state” (Röpke, <span>1960</span>, pp. 144, 143). Still, the most vehement calls for a strong state come from his ordoliberal compatriots Rüstow and Eucken. The former concludes his lecture <i>State Policy and the Necessary Conditions for Economic Liberalism</i> from 1932 with the following remarks: “The new liberalism, which I and my friends promote, demands a strong state, a state that is positioned above the economy, above the interested parties, in the place where it belongs. And with this confession of faith in a strong state that promotes liberal economic policies and—because the two mutually condition each other—in liberal economic policies that promote a strong state, with this confession I should like to end” (Rüstow, <span>2017b</span>, p. 149). The state is thus to remove itself from the pluralistic rancor of political parties and interest groups and take up a position that enables it to fend off the demands coming from these actors. In the same year, Eucken published what will come to be considered a founding text of the ordoliberal tradition, entitled <i>Structural Transformation of the State and the Crisis of Capitalism</i>. In this far-ranging article, Eucken lays out his own version of the narrative of liberal decline, which, in his view, happens to coincide with that of Carl Schmitt in this respect and comes to the fore in “the transformation of the liberal state into an economic state” (Eucken, <span>2017</span>, p. 59). For Eucken, the merging of state, society, and economy encapsulated in the economic state is of the most serious consequence as it “has undermined independent decision-making on the part of the state, something upon which its very existence depends. … All recent economic policy clearly demonstrates this corrosive process: it amounts to a plethora of measures, each of which can be traced back to the wishes of different powerful economic groups but which, taken together, have no coherence and are entirely lacking in system” (Eucken, <span>2017</span>, pp. 59—60). The state, in short, “lacks the real independent power to make its own decisions” (p. 60).</p><p>Similar to Rüstow, Eucken thus demands that the state overcome its looming pluralistic dissolution and instead disentangle itself from the grip of particularistic actors in order to restore a unified and independent will formation of its own in order to become the true “guardian of the competitive order” (Eucken, <span>1960</span>, p. 327) and enforce it even against powerful economic actors. How this would reflect upon the system of (pluralist) democracy and to what extent it would decline as collateral damage of this operation, if not the actual target of it, is left unaddressed by Eucken—but this omission may in itself be considered rather telling.</p><p>These three proposals entail rather controversial ingredients, but, as noted before, I have not sketched them out here to scrutinize them critically, but rather to show that neoliberals invariantly responded to the diagnosed problems of democracy with rather ambitious reform proposals. Without exception, they presupposed that the time for a pragmatic muddling through had passed, and decisive, transformative action had to be taken. What is imagined here, even in the most specific and less far-reaching demand of the constitutional balanced-budget amendment, is more than a marginal policy adjustment but rather amounts to what Hall in his classic discussion refers to as second- or even third-order/paradigmatic change—with the more encompassing proposals from Hayek and the ordoliberals certainly qualifying as the latter (see Hall, <span>1993</span>). Given the large-scale and rather drastic transformations envisioned, it seems all the more important that there is some consideration given to the way these could be brought about and who the actors are that could plausibly be believed to pursue such strategies, in short, the problem of transformation. But this turns out to be more than a minor challenge for all the neoliberals discussed here.</p><p>What this section will show is that neoliberals invariably fail in theorizing a politics of neoliberal transformation, albeit in different and instructive ways. As established in the preceding section, neoliberal reforms are not designed as incremental processes of adjustment, rather they entail a decisive break with the status quo—which is only consequent, given the bleak picture that the diagnoses of contemporary democratic societies paint. But how should transformation be brought about and who are the actors that are to usher in this epochal process of change?</p><p>Let us begin with Eucken, whose position in these matters is arguably the weakest among the neoliberals considered here as his account of potential reform strategies amounts to the very absence of such an account. In some of his post-war writings and especially in the posthumously published <i>Principles of Economic Policy</i>, Eucken does indeed identify potential actors that are to enforce a competitive order as the crucial aspect of a broader, interlocking structure of societal orders. The state, churches, and science are thus characterized as “ordering potencies” (Eucken, <span>1960</span>, p. 325), but their respective potential lies dormant and so Eucken's exposition of the three potencies amounts in large parts to lamenting their respective inability to realize this potential. In other words, Eucken is at a loss as to how the state is to disentangle itself from the sway that interest groups and political parties have over it, or how churches and science could be restored to their former authority and influence. Especially with regard to the state, the task is a formidable one as truly ordoliberal economic policy presupposes the autonomy of the state, which it supposedly achieves, and thus Eucken finds himself in a logical circle: “Without a competitive order no state capable of action can emerge and, conversely, without a state capable of action no competitive order can emerge” (Eucken, 1960, p. 338).</p><p>While in Eucken's case, the matter of neoliberal strategy is not pursued any further, Röpke addresses the question of the actors who could bring about his particular ordoliberal vision of a decentralized and demassified society. “The conviction is rightly gaining ground that the important thing is that every society should have a small but influential group of leaders who feel themselves to be the whole community's guardians of inviolable norms and values and who strictly live up to this guardianship. What we need is true <i>nobilitas naturalis</i>” (Röpke, <span>1960</span>, p. 130). There is no need to go into the details of Röpke's extolling of a virtuous class of clerks benevolently guarding the political community, which draws on Plato's notion of a guardian class as well as classically conservative notions of natural(ized) social hierarchy. What deserves attention in our context is the already deeply pessimistic framing of Röpke's introduction of a <i>nobilitas naturalis</i>. “Evidently, many and sometimes difficult conditions must be fulfilled and endure if such a natural aristocracy is to develop and endure and if it is to discharge its tasks. It must grow and mature, and the slowness of its ripening is matched by the swiftness of its possible destruction” (Röpke, <span>1960</span>, p. 131). Thus, as soon as the actors of Röpke's reform agenda are introduced, they all but disappear again as it turns out that theirs is a profoundly fleeting existence that depends on a rather unlikely constellation of factors and conditions that all to easily evaporate, and with it the cherished “aristocrats of public spirit” (p. 131). And to be sure, this is not just rhetoric, considering Röpke's lengthy characterizations of these “clerks.” What is required among other things to qualify as one of society's guardians is a “life of dedicated endeavor on behalf of all, unimpeachable integrity, constant restraint of our common greed, proved soundness of judgment, a spotless private life, indomitable courage to stand up for truth and law, and generally the highest example” (Röpke, <span>1960</span>, pp. 130—131). Given this demanding profile, it is no surprise that the emergence and persistence of such a guardian class are characterized as exceedingly unlikely. After all, it seems as if it would take actors of almost otherworldly nature to satisfy Röpke's standards, and so it is only consequent for him to refer to them as “secularized saints,” and given the religious idiom into which these matters are transferred in Röpke's account, it seems appropriate to refer to this as a typical ‘deus-ex-machina’-motive, which reveals the lacunae in Röpke's thought.</p><p>With regard to Rüstow, we already know that the proposed remedy is the transformation of the current, weak state into a strong one. But how to bypass the entrenched networks of interested parties who are capable of whipping the masses into action against any kind of reform effort that threatens their access to the troughs of money and power? In an early intervention in the form of a lecture from 1929, Rüstow imagines a path toward a nonpluralist politics that can be referred to as transitional dictatorship without a stretch. After all, the title of the lecture is <i>Dictatorship within the Bounds of Democracy</i> (Rüstow, 1959, [<span>1929</span>]). According to his proposal, the government led by a chancellor would be granted the right to govern for a certain period of time, even if it lacks a parliamentary majority. The suspension of the possibility of being forced to resign or have bills and measures defeated in parliamentary votes is to give the government the leeway to pursue what Rüstow undoubtedly imagined to be the kind of politics that Röpke's aristocrats of the public spirit would have enacted. Once the granted time period is over, the suspension of parliamentary power and oversight ceases and the government has to face the respective scrutiny as well as the possibility of being voted out of office again. “This means the preservation of democracy because it is a time-limited dictatorship, not in the strict sense of the term, but, as it were, a dictatorship with a probational period” (Rüstow, <span>1959</span>, p. 99).</p><p>In Hayek's case, things are, unsurprisingly, more complex, but the thrust of his point is clear enough. Already in <i>Law, Legislation and Liberty</i>, he discusses emergency powers as potentially necessary to secure the long-term stability of a political community in the midst of a crisis and/or the verge of totalitarian collectivism (Hayek, <span>2003</span>, III, p. 124). This argument is located at a neuralgic point in Hayek's thought, systematically speaking, because just as in the case of other neoliberals, he faces the task of spelling out a plausible path toward a more neoliberal society amid a world that, according to his own analysis, has already begun its descent on the (in-)famous <i>Road to Serfdom</i>. Emergency powers and a state of exception in the form of a transitory dictatorship represent the theoretical bridge that connects the status quo with Hayek's neoliberal vision. This comes to the fore most clearly and also most controversially in Hayek's notorious comments on Chile after the coup of Augusto Pinochet, displaying his usual candor in an interview with <i>El Mercurio</i> in 1981: “As long-term institutions I am totally against dictatorships. But a dictatorship may be a necessary system for a transitional period. At times it is necessary for a country to have, for a time, some kind of dictatorial power. As you will understand, it is possible for a dictator to govern in a liberal way. … My personal impression … is that in Chile … we will witness the transition from a dictatorial to a liberal government…” (El Mercurio, <span>1981</span>, p. D9).</p><p>By the early 1980s, Hayek had obviously persuaded himself that a transitional dictatorship was a legitimate option to save political communities from succumbing to totalitarianism-cum-collectivism, and as we know from the quote in the preceding section, Hayek was also convinced that this was not just a matter pertaining to Chile or other “underdeveloped” countries but that the slide into totalitarianism was a tendency inherent to actually existing contemporary democracy.</p><p>What are we to make of these proposals? Starting with Rüstow, if the envisioned “dictatocracy” is really to remain within the boundaries of democracy, it would have to be established through a parliamentary vote changing the constitution. However, as he himself notes, “I am not enough of a utopian to assume that a proposition as I just sketched it would normally find a majority to change the constitution in the Reichstag today. … If we had a Reichstag where something like that was conceivable then the proposition would be unnecessary” (Rüstow, <span>1959</span>, p. 100). And given this “Catch 22,” which parallels the respective problems in Eucken, Rüstow must either bury his hopes for a truly transformative politics that walks the thin line between democracy and dictatorship, or he would have to discard his remnant democratic sensibilities and opt for dictatorial politics <i>sans phrase</i>.</p><p>Both Rüstow and Hayek face another more general problem, they leave largely unaddressed, namely, whether it is realistic to assume that transitional dictatorship remains transitional. To be sure, history knows instances where dictators or democratic leaders with de facto dictatorial powers quietly and dutifully stepped aside and thus enabled a return to normal conditions, but it was Hayek himself who had based his slippery slope argument in <i>The Road to Serfdom</i> on the notion that unchecked powers tend to become entrenched and engender a dynamic that tends toward the totalitarian. The plenitude of power required for comprehensive planning, as Hayek had argued back then, would even drag the most well-meaning socialists into the deadly politics of totalitarianism. Why would these mechanisms not apply to the transitional dictatorships that do not seek to pave the way toward socialism but liberal authoritarianism? A Hayekian line of defense may be to resort to a point contained in <i>The Road to Serfdom</i>, according to which such a dynamic is triggered only by economic interventionism and not political interventions, that is, if liberal authoritarianism abstained from economic interventions, it might arrest any potential totalitarian dynamic, but whether this differentiation is a convincing one is rather disputable. While Hayek at least has an argument, albeit a weak one, it remains a real mystery, why Rüstow never gave any explicit attention to this conundrum; all the more so, since he—and also Hayek—were acutely aware of the work of Carl Schmitt. And in his writings on the state of exception, one major and not entirely implausible point is that the liberal ambition of arresting the mercurial nature of a state of exception by codifying rules that govern its modalities and the emergency powers ensuing from it is ultimately futile. So if Rüstow's hope was that his version of a transitional dictatocracy would remain transitional because it was thus codified in the constitution—if there was ever a majority in favor of it—this is almost naïve from a Schmittian point of view. So we see that in both cases, the reform strategy proposed is incompatible with more or less explicit assumptions underlying the respective points of view.</p><p>Our final case study is the work of James Buchanan, who is also the most fascinating example because while Rüstow and Eucken mostly try to avoid the issue of strategy and implementation, he grapples with it directly over and over again.</p><p>Buchanan's specific challenge is not altogether different from the problems haunting the neoliberals we have already discussed. It can be stated quite succinctly in the form of a simple question that still proves to have rather devastating implications. If the assumptions of the public choice theory suggest that homo oeconomicus is a behavioral model appropriate for the analysis of political actors and rent-seeking is a practice not only rent seekers but also those who are in a position to grant rents, that is, politicians, benefit from, how can we assume that these actors will pass a constitutional balanced-budget amendment designed to curb among other things rent-seeking behavior?</p><p>Obviously, Buchanan was well aware of the problem he faced and undertook multiple unsuccessful attempts to deal with it, the chronicling of which would exceed the scope of the paper. Eventually, he found himself forced to rethink a crucial element in his own thought, namely, that of homo oeconomicus and how it was intertwined with rent-seeking behavior.</p><p>Over time he becomes more and more adamant that homo oeconomicus is just one of several personae that make up any actual person and at times suggests an almost dualist anthropology when he writes that there is “a struggle within each of us … between rent-seeker and the constitutionalists, and that almost all citizens will play, simultaneously, both roles” (Buchanan, <span>1991</span>, pp. 2, 10). This battle between normative orientations will become a site of major strategic importance for Buchanan because the conclusion he draws is that “the constitutionalist” in ourselves needs to be strengthened against the “rent-seeker” just as Rousseau thought the “citoyen” had to be strengthened vis-à-vis the “bourgeois.” It is only consequent, therefore, that Buchanan writes that “the reform that I seek lies first of all in attitudes” (Buchanan, <span>1975</span>, p. 176). This is noteworthy because it contradicts the claim routinely made by liberals or conservatives that they subscribe to a realist anthropology that “takes people as they are” and treats their preferences as “exogenous variables” refraining from any attempt to educate or change them but solely focus on social and political rules. Buchanan <i>does</i> want to change people, and he more and more explicitly embraces the notion that in this matter it is not enough to appeal to homo oeconomicus. In a paper titled “The Soul of Classical Liberalism,” Buchanan diagnoses the failure of liberalism to capture the hearts and minds of people because it lacks an appealing narrative: “Science and self-interest, especially as combined, do indeed lend force to any argument. But a vision of an ideal, over and beyond science and self-interest, is necessary, and those who profess membership in the club of classical liberals have failed singularly in their neglect of this requirement” (Buchanan, <span>2000</span>, p. 112). The constitutionalist in us cannot be strengthened through a “rational” argument appealing to the authority of science or self-interest alone, because what is at stake is an entire worldview that one comes to believe in. Only when attitudinal patterns have changed to a sufficient degree will it be possible to pursue the political project Buchanan continues to envision, which he describes as no less than a “constitutional revolution,” in sharp contrast to the incrementalism of “pragmatic reform” (Buchanan &amp; Di Pierro, <span>1969</span>, p. 95). However, this strategy entails a major concession that Buchanan himself spells out: “To hold out hope for reform in the basic rules describing the sociopolitical game, we must introduce elements that violate the self-interest postulate” (Brennan &amp; Buchanan, <span>1985</span>, p. 146). This is remarkable given that the entire critique of the rent-seeking society and actually existing democracy, of course, rests on the “self-interest postulate” of homo oeconomicus.</p><p>And so here we finally come to see that not only Buchanan had to attenuate his stance regarding the potential benevolence of actors, thus moving a little closer to the views of those who like Röpke place their hopes in a particular set of actors, but he also comes to commit himself not to a state of exception as a precondition of neoliberal reform but to what might be called a politics of the extraordinary with the radical connotations of a revolution. And so, in similarity to Hayek and Rüstow, Buchanan conceives of neoliberal reform politics as a caesura that can produce a real rupture of the iron cage of the ever same in which the entrenched rent-seeking networks are dismantled and the “basic rules of the sociopolitical rules” can finally be changed. Not only are these dreams of rupture shared by Buchanan and Hayek, but they are also expressed by Rüstow when he muses on “great politics, the politics that is the art of the impossible, that which wrongly was considered impossible” (Rüstow, <span>1963</span>, p. 117) and Friedman who envisions a political window of opportunity within which “what seemed impossible suddenly becomes possible” (Friedman &amp; Friedman, <span>1990</span>, p. xiv). What is on display here is an almost eschatological hope for the moment of the great rupture, the day of reckoning and of reversal, when the powers that be are unseated and a new kingdom will be erected—only here, it is not the kingdom of god but rather the realm of neoliberalism.</p><p>What I have developed in this paper is a critique of neoliberal thought that rests on the latter's inability to theorize in a consistent and plausible manner the problem of transition. The neoliberals in that sense are similar to those whom Marx described and derided as Utopian Socialists: bursting with visions about a better future but unable to develop strategies to realize these visions. Despite the variations described above, an overall pattern can still be detected: With their at times harsh criticisms of actually existing democracies, neoliberal thinkers back themselves into a theoretical corner because the more apocalyptic the critical diagnoses get, the more difficult it is to sketch a path out of the misery that is the status quo. Put differently, what the neoliberal critic gains in terms of the urgency of his diagnoses, the neoliberal reformer loses in terms of the viability of change. This confronts neoliberals with a dilemma encapsulated best in Buchanan's concession regarding the weakening of the self-interest postulate: Either neoliberals want to hold on to their trenchant critiques of democracy and the assumptions underlying them, but then they effectively forfeit the ability to also explain how conditions could possibly be changed and their accounts in effect turn into pessimistic conservatism. Or they want to be able to maintain the theoretical ability to capture the politics of neoliberal reform, but then they have to relax some of their assumptions and in effect scale back their critique of the democratic status quo significantly.</p><p>Describing this as a dilemma is the most modest version of this conclusion, which changes if we take the dimension of actually existing neoliberalism into account, which, after all, provides ample evidence for the possibility and factuality of neoliberal reform: The so-called debt brakes European countries have passed in response to the Eurozone Crisis is the equivalent of Buchanan's cherished balanced-budget amendment, and there are indeed such balanced-budget amendments on the state and municipal level in the United States (see Peck, <span>2014</span>). Furthermore, when it comes to actors sufficiently isolated from democratic pressures to make “rational” decisions, there are, prominently, central banks that have been granted independence with minimal accountability requirements across the OECD world, and there is the European Commission in charge of overseeing competition and deficit rules in the Eurozone, both of which can be considered to be part of what has been referred to as “the rise of the unelected” (Vibert, <span>2009</span>). Finally, one must not forget the international trade regimes, such as the WTO, free trade areas such as the European Union or Mercusor in South America, and free trade agreements such as CETA between Canada and the EU, all of which have effectively reined in the powers of sovereign nation-states in many trade-related areas and beyond (see Slobodian, <span>2018a</span>). Adding this aspect prompts several further questions. First, if there are clear examples of neoliberal reform, are the lacunae in neoliberal theory not essentially moot points, and is that not an indication of the insignificance of neoliberal theory in comparison with actually existing neoliberalism? Moreover, given the realization of neoliberal reforms, might there not be something like a performative theory of transition, which can be distilled from the nonacademic endeavors of someone like Buchanan? Finally, how does the conclusion regarding the dilemma referred to above change with this in mind? Let me begin with this last question: Old-fashioned falsificationism would tell us that if the conclusion of a theory is at odds with observed reality, this necessarily means that there is something wrong with the assumptions of the theory. Applied to the constellation at hand, this means: Neoliberal theory arrives at conclusions that are at odds with observed reality, that is, the facticity of neoliberal reform politics; therefore, there is something wrong with the assumptions of the theory, meaning that the neoliberal critiques of democracy, to the extent that they rest on these assumptions, have to be considered questionable. Regarding the second question, it is true that neoliberals such as Buchanan and Hayek had their ideas about how their ideas could have an impact, which, in Buchanan's case, is chronicled by Nancy Maclean in her controversial account of his nonacademic activities, including cooperation with various interest groups and shady donors (see MacLean, <span>2017</span>, pp. 199–204). Still, my point is that on the theoretical level, there are still lacunae that have repercussions for the plausibility of their critical analyses of democracy and this is what I am ultimately driving at with my argument.</p><p>Finally, Materialists will hasten to point out that identifying such lacunae will not make neoliberalism or its critique of democracy suddenly disappear and I agree. However, in order to be ultimately effective, the critique of neoliberalism must be conducted not only in the register of struggle and power politics, challenging actually existing neoliberalism but also in discursive contestation and the realm of theory on the basis of various kinds of critiques, including immanent ones pointing out inconsistencies, as I have tried to do here. Importantly, the argument contained in this paper is not supposed to “refute” neoliberal theory in its entirety, not the least because ideologies tend to contain contradictions, so identifying them does not necessarily deal a metaphorical death blow to them. My aim is a more specific one, namely, to highlight the dilemma that neoliberals face, which is most clearly on display in the case of Buchanan who openly concedes that the assumptions guiding his critique of democracy have to be relaxed in order to hold out hope for what he considers to be meaningful reforms, and thus undermine the plausibility of neoliberal arguments against democracy. There is no need to overstate the significance of such a critique, which is by no means sufficient, but, conversely, only focusing on the material level leaves to neoliberals the option of blaming unfaithful and incomplete implementation for any negative effect associated with, for example, introducing balanced-budget amendments, maintaining that their theoretical frameworks in themselves are not affected by this. It is such flaws in the framework that my critique aims to reveal.</p><p>Beyond this immediate conclusion, let me point out one more implication that appears to be worthy of more elaborate discussion in future research in light of what has been argued here:</p><p>Given the eschatological hopes neoliberals seem to harbor for a political rupture, this might also provide a link to the politics of what now is typically referred to as (right-wing) populism (but is de facto authoritarianism). After all, the self-portrayal of populist leaders who vow to “drain the swamp” and, generally, sweep aside decadent and corrupt establishments, corresponds to a considerable degree with what neoliberals apparently thought was necessary to overcome the gridlock and inertia of normal politics and implement neoliberal reforms. There can be little doubt that Hayek or Buchanan would have abhorred the notion of a Donald Trump as President of the United States or a Boris Johnson as Prime Minister of the UK—after all, they could not be any less “aristocrats of public spirit”; but still, the theoretical dilemmas their critiques of democracy create for them make the neoliberals inadvertently gravitate toward the kind of ruptural antiestablishment politics that populist movements and parties at least claim to represent. They are neoliberalism's “Frankenstein,” to borrow an expression from Wendy Brown (<span>2018</span>)—or its “bastards,” to borrow one from Quinn Slobodian (<span>2018b</span>). To be sure, one might argue that the Trump administration, to take a prominent example, attacked global regimes of economic multilateralism in the name of economic nationalism and would thus be in opposition to the kind of international free trade regimes, zones, and agreements cited above as manifestations of neoliberal reforms. However, upon closer inspection, the opposition to neoliberal designs turns out to be less than strict: The Trump administration indeed left NAFTA—but only to negotiate a new free trade zone called UMSCA with minimally better conditions for the United States. On the other hand, the tax reform under Trump could have just as well been passed under Reagan—in fact, Reagan's adviser from back then, Arthur Laffer, was also brought in as a consultant by the Trump administration. But while the opposition between them is overstated in many instances, my point is not that the substantive <i>policies</i> pursued by right-wing populists are all in congruence with neoliberal ideas. Rather, the major point of convergence between the two consists in their view of <i>politics</i> as necessarily disruptive in order to shake up the seemingly locked-in status quo dominated by mainstream political actors with no incentive to enact any real change to the “system.” By the same token, this is what turns both, neoliberals and right-wing populists, into antagonists of liberal democracy and its inertia, but while neoliberals dream of an ultra-stable world of almost self-enforcing rules to succeed in the moment of rupture, right-wing populists aim for the contrary: A world of rupture becoming permanent.</p>","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":"31 4","pages":"506-519"},"PeriodicalIF":1.2000,"publicationDate":"2023-09-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12713","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"The revolution will not be theorized: Neoliberal thought and the problem of transition\",\"authors\":\"Thomas Biebricher\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/1467-8675.12713\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>Neoliberalism is a notoriously contested term, and even among those who principally subscribe to it, which is mostly its critics, fierce debates persist over its nature, how to study it properly—and whether it is still the appropriate conceptual armament to understand the contemporary world and an arguably emerging “post-neoliberalism” (Davies &amp; Gane, <span>2021</span>). Not only is it controversial how neoliberalism should be defined—a governing rationality in the spirit of Foucault's governmentality lectures (Foucault, <span>2008</span>), a portfolio of certain policies, or a strategy of transnational capital to restore and safeguard profit rates (Harvey, <span>2005</span>)—but also on what level to study it, either that of “actually existing neoliberalism” (Brenner &amp; Theodore, <span>2002</span>; Cahill, <span>2014</span>), a set of theories and arguments, or both.</p><p>My starting point and focus for most of this paper is neoliberal thought as it is represented by the writings of Friedrich Hayek, Milton Friedman, the German ordoliberals, and, importantly, James Buchanan. My aim is to develop a critical account of neoliberal thought that will abstain from explicitly normative criticisms and rather opt for a more indirect but effective and somewhat novel critique that holds neoliberalism to its own standards and shows how it fails to meet them or is pushed into adopting highly questionable positions in the attempt to do so. The argument proceeds as follows: As already suggested, the meaning of neoliberalism is heavily contested, so I will provide the basis of my argument by laying out a brief account of neoliberalism, which relies on a theoretical-historical reconstruction of its context of emergence around the middle of the 20th century. What I conclude from this reconstruction is that we are well-advised not to narrow down neoliberalism too much and not to downplay its internal heterogeneities. Therefore, rather than trying to isolate a number of doctrines or positions as quintessentially neoliberal or even considering them to be the “essence” of neoliberalism, I argue that what unites neoliberal discourse is not a set of positive convictions—although there is some significant overlap in certain areas—but rather a shared <i>problematic</i> that pertains to the preconditions of functioning markets.</p><p>Within that overall problematic, democracy is one of the most pressing problems according to neoliberal thinkers, because virtually all of them agree that it complicates the task of setting up and securing the workings of functioning markets significantly. Still, this basic agreement notwithstanding, neoliberal accounts of democracy display a considerable range of specific diagnoses as to the nature and source of its dysfunctionalities or even pathologies. Accordingly, the second step of the argument is a survey of some selected lines of critique of democracy as they are formulated by leading neoliberals. Among other things, this survey helps us appreciate the heterogeneities of neoliberal thought, but, more importantly for my purposes, it also gives us a sense of the deep reservations neoliberals have with regard to democracy and the trenchant nature of their critique.</p><p>As the specific critiques of democracy vary among neoliberals, so do the suggested remedies and reforms put forward. Accordingly, in the next step, several selected reform proposals are scrutinized that range from the vague call for a “strong state” to Hayek's “model constitution” and the much more specific argument for the introduction of a constitutional balanced-budget amendment, which is a signature demand of Buchanan. What this survey shows us, among other things, is the radical nature of the neoliberal reform proposals, which is important to my overall argument.</p><p>Despite the highly controversial implications of all of these reform proposals, I will deliberately forego engaging them directly based on normative arguments. Instead, my critique focuses on the missing analytical link between neoliberal diagnostics and respective remedies. In order to show this, the fourth and final part of the argument shifts attention to the politics of neoliberal transformation, that is, whether and how this kind of politics is theorized in neoliberal accounts. Again, there is a certain degree of variance between Hayek, Eucken and Buchanan, but the common denominator here is the inability to theorize such a politics without violating the respective assumptions underlying the critical diagnostics or moving beyond the confines of liberal democracy as a condition of implementing such reforms. Thus, the key thesis I wish to defend in the following contends that neoliberal thought lacks any plausible solution to the so-called problem of transition—if they care to reflect on it at all.<sup>1</sup></p><p>These findings lead to several different interpretations with more or less far-reaching implications that are discussed in the concluding section.</p><p>It is commonplace nowadays to note the contested nature and potential vacuity of the term neoliberalism. Faced with these allegations, scholars of neoliberalism often hasten to offer some kind of working definition of neoliberalism, lest they lend credence to suspicions that they are operating with an empty signifier carrying political rather than analytical meaning. Accordingly, a set of policies—typically centered around the agenda of the <i>Washington Consensus</i>—is identified as quintessentially neoliberal, certain ideas or principles are considered to make up its core or essence or, neoliberal is simply that, which members of the <i>Mont Pèlerin Society</i> promulgate, which is an elegant but, upon closer inspection, not entirely convincing way to circumvent the problem (Chomsky, <span>1999</span>; Crouch, <span>2011</span>; Mirowski &amp; Plehwe, <span>2009</span>). On the other hand, there are regular interventions by scholars who emphasize the enormous variability/transformability of neoliberalism and its characteristic ability to form more or less tension-laden amalgamations with other political-intellectual projects, which makes it seemingly impossible, or at least intellectually imprudent, to aim for some hard and fast definition that “fixes” neoliberalism and its meaning(s): “Crisply unambiguous, essentialist definitions of neoliberalism have proved to be incredibly elusive” (Peck, <span>2010</span>, p. 8).</p><p>My own account of neoliberalism will try to strike a balance between overly parsimonious definitional attempts that do not hold up under closer scrutiny and the analytically defeatist solution to dissolve neoliberalism into various neoliberalism<i>s</i> that allegedly share nothing but Wittgensteinian family resemblances. The starting point of my conceptual approach is the observation that neoliberalism has become a truly toxic label these days, and it might therefore be useful to begin with a look at those who did describe themselves, albeit fleetingly and reluctantly, as neoliberals at the time and clarify the intellectual and political agenda that they attached the label “neoliberal” to. In other words, it is necessary to reconstruct the intellectual and political context of neoliberalism's emergence.</p><p>Processes of emergence do not have a single origin but are dispersed, and the same goes for neoliberalism. Nevertheless, it is possible to identify the <i>Colloque Walter Lippmann</i> as the “birth” of neoliberalism in the sense of the first culmination point of these processes and the event at which, for the first time, the term was officially adopted, denoting a shared agenda of the participants, which included not just Hayek, Wilhelm Röpke, and Alexander Rüstow but also Jacques Rueff, Louis Rougier (the convener of the meeting) and, of course, Walter Lippmann himself. At this point, an impressive scholarship on the Colloque exists, so there is no need to go into the details of the proceedings (see instead Burgin, <span>2012</span>; Dardot &amp; Laval, <span>2013</span>; Innset, <span>2020</span>; Reinhoudt &amp; Audier, <span>2018</span>). The overall picture that emerges from them is a liberalism on the defensive that seeks to regain the status of a real contender against its main antagonists, collectivism and—to a lesser degree back then—Keynesianism. In the eyes of practically all of the participants except for Ludwig von Mises, this endeavor presupposed a critical revision of the classical liberal agenda, and, most notably, abandoning simplistic formulas such as “laissez-faire,” or, what some referred to as “Manchesterism.”<sup>2</sup> The neoliberal discourse in formation here was, thus, a far cry from the creed of “self-regulating markets.” Instead, the entire point of the neoliberal approach is to affirm the value of markets against collectivists and Keynesians while insisting that they are not nearly as robust and self-sustaining as large parts of the liberal tradition were inclined to believe up to that point. To put it more pointedly, the market per se was not the solution to all problems; rather, <i>the market itself turned into a problem for neoliberal thought</i> as it was seen as an entity in need of constant care and premised upon a number of preconditions. Therefore, what I call the <i>neoliberal problematic</i> pertains to the preconditions of functioning markets, that is, markets on which the price mechanism reigns as unperturbed as possible.<sup>3</sup></p><p>The irreducible heterogeneities that characterize neoliberal discourse are not the least due to the manifold and at times contradictory ways in which this problematic can be, and has been, spelled out and addressed. Still, what becomes clear is that neoliberal thought might be centered around the notion of markets, but the intellectual energies of those whose work is animated by this problematic, such as Buchanan, Hayek, or the German ordoliberals, inevitably gravitate toward the infrastructure that needs to be put in place and defended against changing adversaries for these markets to function. This is the realm of the social and the political, and therefore it is only stringent for the neoliberals to invest so much time into conceptualizing the state—and democracy.</p><p>When neoliberals talk about democracy, they typically refer to democracy in its existing form, that is, their discourse rarely ventures into philosophical inquiries into the nature and theory of democracy. The predominant form their discourse takes is that of a critique of the respective contemporary forms of representative democracy.</p><p>These respective contexts leave an imprint on the various accounts of democracy, but rather than probing the details of each, in this survey, I will highlight what I consider to be three types of arguments or varieties of the neoliberal critique of democracy that can be analytically distinguished.<sup>4</sup></p><p>The first set of arguments against democracy considered here is particularly prominent in ordoliberal discourse but not exclusive to it:<sup>5</sup> For Wilhelm Röpke and Walter Eucken, the main threat associated with democracy is due to the influence of a new phenomenon on the political scene, namely, the masses. With the rise of mass democracy, the latter have acquired a heretofore unknown leverage over political decisions, or at least this is the assumption under which the ordoliberals in particular are operating. Hence, the problem is not the existence of masses per se but rather their integration into the political process through mass democratic institutions as it unfolds unevenly but steadily over the course of the first half of the 20th century. While the aversion against the masses may seem no more than a variant on the venerable liberal-conservative <i>topos</i> of the tyranny of the majority, there is more to it. The masses are more than a majority. In a discourse crucially shaped by Gustave Le Bon's <i>Crowds</i>, Sigmund Freud's <i>Group Psychology and the Analysis of the Ego</i>, and Jose Ortega Y. Gasset's <i>Revolt of the Masses</i> (who was invited to the <i>Colloque</i> but did not participate), the concept of the masses is psychologically (and at times racially) charged. Masses are attributed with infantilism and general irrationality, which makes them the perfect molding material for demagogues who exploit their uncritical receptiveness and malleability to mobilize them for political projects—typically ones that involve state planning and collectivization from the perspective of the ordoliberals. There is ample textual evidence for this stance, so a few examples may suffice here as the basis of this interpretation. Eucken notes: “But while people can only live in certain orders, the mass tends towards destroying these exact orders” (Eucken, <span>1960</span>, p. 14), and in one of the classic texts inaugurating the ordoliberal tradition from 1932, he laments “that the simultaneous process of democratisation lent the parties, and the masses and interest groups that they organised, much greater influence over the management of the state, and so upon economic policy” (Eucken, 2017, [<span>1932</span>], p. 59). Röpke complements these views: “In all countries, in some less, in others more, society has been ground into a mass of individuals, who have never been so closely herded together and so dependent on each other and yet at the same time they are more rootless, more isolated and more like grains of sand than ever before … All the misery, all the problems of our time have their ultimate roots here…” (Röpke, 1950, [<span>1942</span>], p. 92). Elsewhere, he draws on the above-mentioned social psychological framing of the masses: “As a part of ‘mass’, we are different from what we normally are and should be in healthy circumstances; we are subhuman, herdlike, and the state of society dangerously corresponds to our own” (Röpke, <span>1960</span>, p. 53). And while the most extreme manifestations of what might be called the mass syndrome only occur in what Röpke terms mass in the “acute state,” massification as a permanent condition is hardly less alarming, since it heralds the reign of mediocre brutes at the expense of the “unalterable aristocracy of nature” Röpke hopes to defend (Röpke, <span>1960</span>, p. 55). To sum up this line of criticism, economic policy is simply too important and much too intricate to leave it to the wayward masses, who may not sit in parliaments and run governments in representative democracies, but are still too influential under the conditions of mass democracy, even if only as the object of demagogic agitation and mobilization. If the alliance of these forces had their way, democracy is bound to transform into collectivism, that is, the prime adversary of neoliberal thought: “There is no denying it: the collectivist state is rooted in the masses” (Röpke, <span>1950</span>, p. 86).</p><p>The second line of criticism also owes its classic formulation to another ordoliberal, namely, Alexander Rüstow. The target of this criticism, in addition to the mass dimension of contemporary democracy, is its alleged excessive “pluralism.” Rüstow succinctly sums up the respective core concern: “The democratic, parliamentary structure of some of the economically leading states caused the economic corruption to spread to the internal policy of the state, to the political parties, and to the [sic!] parliamentarism itself. The political parties were slowly transformed into parliamentary agencies of economic pressure groups and were financed by them. … The pathological form of government which developed this way was that of pluralism…” (Rüstow, 2017a, [<span>1942</span>], p. 159). Under conditions of mass democracy, (economic) pressure groups will gain such extraordinary influence that they can almost dictate their will to political parties; the result is marginalization of a vaguely defined common good, which is dissolved into what Eucken calls in no uncertain terms “group anarchy” (Eucken, <span>1960</span>, p. 171). The state, as the presumptive guardian of this common good, is undermined in this process of economic-political clientelism, and Rüstow echoes the scathing criticism of pluralism by Carl Schmitt in his conclusion: “What takes place here accords with the motto: ‘The state as prey’” (Rüstow, 2017b, [<span>1932</span>], p. 147). Under conditions of unchecked pluralism, the state is weakened continuously and the resulting centrifugal dynamics ultimately become unmanageable as the political community falls apart at the hands of particularistic actors emerging from every corner of society.</p><p>Thirdly, there is a strictly contemporary line of criticism that still exhibits some correspondence to the critique of pluralism just sketched. The central theorem underlying this critique is that of rent-seeking, which describes a behavior that seeks to gain some kind of advantage over others not through productive action and competition but rather by lobbying for some kind of special treatment, typically an exemption from certain rules. This idea builds on the insights of game theory and rational choice approaches, according to which individual utility is often maximized when (generally beneficial) rules apply to all but the individual in question, and much of the public choice critique of democracy is built around this basal notion: Under conditions of democracy, the constant demand for special treatment of societal/economic actors is met by an eager supplier in the form of political actors hoping thus to increase their chances of reelection. As one of the cofounders of the public choice tradition, it is a matter of course, that Buchanan puts the rent-seeking theorem at the center of his critique of representative democracy and he is not the only neoliberal who does so: Milton Friedman as well as the later Hayek would occasionally, albeit not systematically, draw on the basic logic of rent-seeking (see Friedman &amp; Friedman, <span>1984</span>). The fundamental problem that allegedly ensues from rent-seeking can be summed up in the following way: Assuming that everybody else engages in rent-seeking, individual rationality dictates that one does so as well because, otherwise, one would be indirectly disadvantaged to the degree that others gain exemptions from rules that still apply to oneself. This means that rent-seeking has an inherently expansive dynamic, and as a general practice, it backfires against the intent of its subjects because even if individual rent-seeking may be successful and provides an advantage, this is vastly outweighed by the multiple disadvantages one has to suffer due to all other rent-seeking activities, assuming they are successful as well. Thus, in pursuit of their individual utility, the actors in a society end up putting themselves at a disadvantage. Just as in the pluralist scenario, it is particularism that prevails here, albeit with a tragic twist. But not only does the “rent-seeking society” (Buchanan et al., <span>1980</span>) harm its current members: Exemptions and other special treatments typically come with some kind of price tag, and since financing through raising taxes is not a realistic option under public choice assumptions, and lawmakers, as well as government, have less and less control over inflation, the prime strategy to pay for rents is through deficits and debt—burdening the almost proverbial “future generations” with financial obligations that they had no say in—arguably a clear violation of the democratic principle of autonomy.</p><p>Finally, there is a line of critique that focuses on the decline of the rule of law in relation to democracy and problematizes the alleged unlimited nature of the latter. The prime exemplar of this line of argument is Friedrich August Hayek, who laid out the various aspects in numerous writings. To be sure, Hayek conceded that democracy, in principle, had its merits: “[I]t is the only convention we have yet discovered to make peaceful change possible” (Hayek, <span>2003</span>, III, p. 137) However, the ideal of democracy and its basic thrust of limiting power became disfigured over time. <i>The Constitution of Liberty</i> already contains the central point of Hayek's critique in a nutshell: “The crucial conception of the doctrinaire democrat is that of popular sovereignty. This means to him that Majority rule is unlimited and unlimitable. The ideal of democracy, originally intended to prevent all arbitrary power, thus becomes the justification for a new arbitrary power” (Hayek, <span>2006</span>, p. 93) The deeper reason for this, according to Hayek, is the erosion of the principle of the rule of law, which he chronicles in <i>the Constitution of Liberty</i> and that involves, prominently, the shedding of any formal prerequisites of what constitutes a genuine law. While in the heyday of liberalism, only those legal rules that were abstract, general, and directed at future behavior were considered to be law in the proper sense of the term, nowadays, Hayek claims, whatever emerges from a legislature is deemed to have the power of law, thus empowering parliaments to engage in the kind of discretionary planning activities that he considers to be harmful on any number of levels. And since there are no longer any formal restrictions on this unrestrained democracy, politicians have no instruments at their disposal to fend off the demands from societal interest groups. “The root of the trouble is, of course, to sum up, that in an unlimited democracy the holders of discretionary powers are forced to use them, whether they wish it or not, to favour particular groups on whose swing vote their powers depend” (Hayek, <span>2003</span>, III, p. 139), concludes Hayek, thus echoing in this regard the second and third lines of critique sketched out above. The main thrust of Hayek's argument, though, is a combination of the critique of democracy as majority rule—spelled out most prominently in <i>The Constitution of Liberty</i> (see Hayek, <span>2006</span>, pp. 90–102)—and the contention that this majority rule is no longer restrained in any meaningful way, thus giving rise to an almost dystopian “unlimited democracy,” which, Hayek thought, would ultimately lead toward totalitarianism: “[T]he whole work [Law, Legislation and Liberty] has been inspired by a growing apprehension about the direction in which the political order of what used to be regarded as the most advanced countries is tending. The growing conviction … that this threatening development towards a totalitarian state is made inevitable by certain deeply entrenched defects of construction of the generally accepted type of ‘democratic’ government has forced me to think through various alternative arrangements” (Hayek, <span>2003</span>, I, p. xx).</p><p>It is to these alternative arrangements in the works of the various neoliberals accounts discussed here that we now turn to.</p><p>It would exceed the scope of this paper to survey every reform proposal submitted by leading neoliberals, so I will merely focus on three more or less specific reform visions being put forward by Buchanan, Hayek as well as the ordoliberals Rüstow and Eucken, respectively, which are to deal with the various shortcomings or pathologies of democracy as they are pinpointed in the diagnoses sketched out in the preceding section.</p><p>Let us begin with what arguably is the most specific proposal to be found in the neoliberal reform portfolio and which came to be a signature demand raised by James Buchanan, although a slightly different version has also been promoted by Milton Friedman. The proposal seeks to address the proclivity to engage in rent-seeking behavior or rather to grant rents to interest groups on behalf of elected officials in order to improve chances at reelection. Buchanan became ever more pessimistic in his assessment of (American) democracy over the years, eventually claiming that “the appeal to the experience of history, and not least to recent events in the United States, does suggest that government, in its current institutional setting, is close to being out of the control of the electorate” (Brennan &amp; Buchanan, 1980, p. 25). In order to come to terms with this deteriorating situation, one of Buchanan's prime suggestions is to pursue the strategy of reining in democratic excesses through tighter controls of the way public expenditures are financed. What democracy requires is a rule that precludes the debt/deficit financing of these outlays, and it should preferably be instituted on the highest possible legal level: a constitutional balanced-budget amendment (Buchanan, <span>1997</span>). The amendment would stipulate rather that all current state expenditures must be financed through actual revenue, be it taxation or otherwise; it would be simply unconstitutional to accrue deficits and debt to finance state expenditures. Given such restrictions, politicians are expected to restrain runaway spending and curtail public expenditure, instead of attempting to rely on a low tax strategy to succeed at the polls. Whether this is a realistic scenario for the impact of such a proposal could be discussed in much greater detail as could be the normative questions related to it, but following the strategy of my critique laid out initially, I will confine myself to this quick exposition and move on to the second and much more elaborate reform proposal, which is Hayek's “model constitution” (Hayek, <span>2003</span>, pp. 105–127).</p><p>The major thrust of Hayek's proposal is a restoration of a strict separation of powers between government and legislature. His diagnosis problematizes the conflation of both, and therefore real bicameralism has to be reinstituted where legislatures only pass laws in the proper sense of the term that circumscribe the room for discretionary action the government enjoys. Of the many noteworthy aspects of this exercise in institutional design, I will only highlight one particularly intriguing aspect that has also drawn considerable criticism: In many respects, the governing assembly hardly differs in its main characteristics from empirically existing governments, although Hayek is seriously entertaining the disenfranchisement of anybody who receives transfers or salaries from the state in governmental elections (Hayek, <span>2003</span>, p. 120). Still, the major target of criticism is the election rules for the <i>legislature</i>, which is arguably the real locus of power in this new institutional set-up as the governmental assembly is to be strictly “bound by the rules of just conduct laid down by the Legislative Assembly” (Hayek, <span>2003</span>, p. 119). Members of the legislature are to be elected in the following way: Each year all citizens of the age of 45 choose their representatives out of the midst of their demographic cohort to replace the contingent of outgoing legislators at the end of their 15-year term. What Hayek has in mind is “an assembly of men and women elected at a relatively mature age for fairly long periods, such as fifteen years, so they would not be re-eligible nor forced to return to earning a living in the market but be assured of continued public employment in such honorific but neutral positions as lay judges, so that during their tenure as legislators they would be neither dependent on party support nor concerned about their personal future” (Hayek, <span>2003</span>, p. 113). The rationale behind this design is clear enough. The long tenure, ineligibility to be reelected, and guaranteed future employment seek to minimize the incentive to engage in rent-seeking behavior on behalf of legislators and, furthermore, the structuring principle of age groups allegedly would preclude the formation of political party affiliations within the legislatures. And even if they were to form, “those leaning towards different parties would be induced to discuss the issues together, and would become conscious that they had the common task of representing the outlook of their generation…” (Hayek, <span>2003</span>, p. 118). Obviously, this radical proposal is open to many criticisms from the perspective of democratic theory, but let us leave this aside and instead turn to the final proposal to be considered here, which is also the least specific, calling for the transformation of statehood into a “strong state” as its main proponents Alexander Rüstow and Walter Eucken refer to it.</p><p>This remedy manifests the stringent conclusion from the critical diagnosis of excessive pluralism, which is prevalent among most ordoliberals; even Röpke, who is less vocal on this theme, reminds his readers that “the immense danger of this unhealthy pluralism is that pressure groups covetously beset the state” and that “any responsible government must examine carefully all the possible means of resisting this pluralistic disintegration of the state” (Röpke, <span>1960</span>, pp. 144, 143). Still, the most vehement calls for a strong state come from his ordoliberal compatriots Rüstow and Eucken. The former concludes his lecture <i>State Policy and the Necessary Conditions for Economic Liberalism</i> from 1932 with the following remarks: “The new liberalism, which I and my friends promote, demands a strong state, a state that is positioned above the economy, above the interested parties, in the place where it belongs. And with this confession of faith in a strong state that promotes liberal economic policies and—because the two mutually condition each other—in liberal economic policies that promote a strong state, with this confession I should like to end” (Rüstow, <span>2017b</span>, p. 149). The state is thus to remove itself from the pluralistic rancor of political parties and interest groups and take up a position that enables it to fend off the demands coming from these actors. In the same year, Eucken published what will come to be considered a founding text of the ordoliberal tradition, entitled <i>Structural Transformation of the State and the Crisis of Capitalism</i>. In this far-ranging article, Eucken lays out his own version of the narrative of liberal decline, which, in his view, happens to coincide with that of Carl Schmitt in this respect and comes to the fore in “the transformation of the liberal state into an economic state” (Eucken, <span>2017</span>, p. 59). For Eucken, the merging of state, society, and economy encapsulated in the economic state is of the most serious consequence as it “has undermined independent decision-making on the part of the state, something upon which its very existence depends. … All recent economic policy clearly demonstrates this corrosive process: it amounts to a plethora of measures, each of which can be traced back to the wishes of different powerful economic groups but which, taken together, have no coherence and are entirely lacking in system” (Eucken, <span>2017</span>, pp. 59—60). The state, in short, “lacks the real independent power to make its own decisions” (p. 60).</p><p>Similar to Rüstow, Eucken thus demands that the state overcome its looming pluralistic dissolution and instead disentangle itself from the grip of particularistic actors in order to restore a unified and independent will formation of its own in order to become the true “guardian of the competitive order” (Eucken, <span>1960</span>, p. 327) and enforce it even against powerful economic actors. How this would reflect upon the system of (pluralist) democracy and to what extent it would decline as collateral damage of this operation, if not the actual target of it, is left unaddressed by Eucken—but this omission may in itself be considered rather telling.</p><p>These three proposals entail rather controversial ingredients, but, as noted before, I have not sketched them out here to scrutinize them critically, but rather to show that neoliberals invariantly responded to the diagnosed problems of democracy with rather ambitious reform proposals. Without exception, they presupposed that the time for a pragmatic muddling through had passed, and decisive, transformative action had to be taken. What is imagined here, even in the most specific and less far-reaching demand of the constitutional balanced-budget amendment, is more than a marginal policy adjustment but rather amounts to what Hall in his classic discussion refers to as second- or even third-order/paradigmatic change—with the more encompassing proposals from Hayek and the ordoliberals certainly qualifying as the latter (see Hall, <span>1993</span>). Given the large-scale and rather drastic transformations envisioned, it seems all the more important that there is some consideration given to the way these could be brought about and who the actors are that could plausibly be believed to pursue such strategies, in short, the problem of transformation. But this turns out to be more than a minor challenge for all the neoliberals discussed here.</p><p>What this section will show is that neoliberals invariably fail in theorizing a politics of neoliberal transformation, albeit in different and instructive ways. As established in the preceding section, neoliberal reforms are not designed as incremental processes of adjustment, rather they entail a decisive break with the status quo—which is only consequent, given the bleak picture that the diagnoses of contemporary democratic societies paint. But how should transformation be brought about and who are the actors that are to usher in this epochal process of change?</p><p>Let us begin with Eucken, whose position in these matters is arguably the weakest among the neoliberals considered here as his account of potential reform strategies amounts to the very absence of such an account. In some of his post-war writings and especially in the posthumously published <i>Principles of Economic Policy</i>, Eucken does indeed identify potential actors that are to enforce a competitive order as the crucial aspect of a broader, interlocking structure of societal orders. The state, churches, and science are thus characterized as “ordering potencies” (Eucken, <span>1960</span>, p. 325), but their respective potential lies dormant and so Eucken's exposition of the three potencies amounts in large parts to lamenting their respective inability to realize this potential. In other words, Eucken is at a loss as to how the state is to disentangle itself from the sway that interest groups and political parties have over it, or how churches and science could be restored to their former authority and influence. Especially with regard to the state, the task is a formidable one as truly ordoliberal economic policy presupposes the autonomy of the state, which it supposedly achieves, and thus Eucken finds himself in a logical circle: “Without a competitive order no state capable of action can emerge and, conversely, without a state capable of action no competitive order can emerge” (Eucken, 1960, p. 338).</p><p>While in Eucken's case, the matter of neoliberal strategy is not pursued any further, Röpke addresses the question of the actors who could bring about his particular ordoliberal vision of a decentralized and demassified society. “The conviction is rightly gaining ground that the important thing is that every society should have a small but influential group of leaders who feel themselves to be the whole community's guardians of inviolable norms and values and who strictly live up to this guardianship. What we need is true <i>nobilitas naturalis</i>” (Röpke, <span>1960</span>, p. 130). There is no need to go into the details of Röpke's extolling of a virtuous class of clerks benevolently guarding the political community, which draws on Plato's notion of a guardian class as well as classically conservative notions of natural(ized) social hierarchy. What deserves attention in our context is the already deeply pessimistic framing of Röpke's introduction of a <i>nobilitas naturalis</i>. “Evidently, many and sometimes difficult conditions must be fulfilled and endure if such a natural aristocracy is to develop and endure and if it is to discharge its tasks. It must grow and mature, and the slowness of its ripening is matched by the swiftness of its possible destruction” (Röpke, <span>1960</span>, p. 131). Thus, as soon as the actors of Röpke's reform agenda are introduced, they all but disappear again as it turns out that theirs is a profoundly fleeting existence that depends on a rather unlikely constellation of factors and conditions that all to easily evaporate, and with it the cherished “aristocrats of public spirit” (p. 131). And to be sure, this is not just rhetoric, considering Röpke's lengthy characterizations of these “clerks.” What is required among other things to qualify as one of society's guardians is a “life of dedicated endeavor on behalf of all, unimpeachable integrity, constant restraint of our common greed, proved soundness of judgment, a spotless private life, indomitable courage to stand up for truth and law, and generally the highest example” (Röpke, <span>1960</span>, pp. 130—131). Given this demanding profile, it is no surprise that the emergence and persistence of such a guardian class are characterized as exceedingly unlikely. After all, it seems as if it would take actors of almost otherworldly nature to satisfy Röpke's standards, and so it is only consequent for him to refer to them as “secularized saints,” and given the religious idiom into which these matters are transferred in Röpke's account, it seems appropriate to refer to this as a typical ‘deus-ex-machina’-motive, which reveals the lacunae in Röpke's thought.</p><p>With regard to Rüstow, we already know that the proposed remedy is the transformation of the current, weak state into a strong one. But how to bypass the entrenched networks of interested parties who are capable of whipping the masses into action against any kind of reform effort that threatens their access to the troughs of money and power? In an early intervention in the form of a lecture from 1929, Rüstow imagines a path toward a nonpluralist politics that can be referred to as transitional dictatorship without a stretch. After all, the title of the lecture is <i>Dictatorship within the Bounds of Democracy</i> (Rüstow, 1959, [<span>1929</span>]). According to his proposal, the government led by a chancellor would be granted the right to govern for a certain period of time, even if it lacks a parliamentary majority. The suspension of the possibility of being forced to resign or have bills and measures defeated in parliamentary votes is to give the government the leeway to pursue what Rüstow undoubtedly imagined to be the kind of politics that Röpke's aristocrats of the public spirit would have enacted. Once the granted time period is over, the suspension of parliamentary power and oversight ceases and the government has to face the respective scrutiny as well as the possibility of being voted out of office again. “This means the preservation of democracy because it is a time-limited dictatorship, not in the strict sense of the term, but, as it were, a dictatorship with a probational period” (Rüstow, <span>1959</span>, p. 99).</p><p>In Hayek's case, things are, unsurprisingly, more complex, but the thrust of his point is clear enough. Already in <i>Law, Legislation and Liberty</i>, he discusses emergency powers as potentially necessary to secure the long-term stability of a political community in the midst of a crisis and/or the verge of totalitarian collectivism (Hayek, <span>2003</span>, III, p. 124). This argument is located at a neuralgic point in Hayek's thought, systematically speaking, because just as in the case of other neoliberals, he faces the task of spelling out a plausible path toward a more neoliberal society amid a world that, according to his own analysis, has already begun its descent on the (in-)famous <i>Road to Serfdom</i>. Emergency powers and a state of exception in the form of a transitory dictatorship represent the theoretical bridge that connects the status quo with Hayek's neoliberal vision. This comes to the fore most clearly and also most controversially in Hayek's notorious comments on Chile after the coup of Augusto Pinochet, displaying his usual candor in an interview with <i>El Mercurio</i> in 1981: “As long-term institutions I am totally against dictatorships. But a dictatorship may be a necessary system for a transitional period. At times it is necessary for a country to have, for a time, some kind of dictatorial power. As you will understand, it is possible for a dictator to govern in a liberal way. … My personal impression … is that in Chile … we will witness the transition from a dictatorial to a liberal government…” (El Mercurio, <span>1981</span>, p. D9).</p><p>By the early 1980s, Hayek had obviously persuaded himself that a transitional dictatorship was a legitimate option to save political communities from succumbing to totalitarianism-cum-collectivism, and as we know from the quote in the preceding section, Hayek was also convinced that this was not just a matter pertaining to Chile or other “underdeveloped” countries but that the slide into totalitarianism was a tendency inherent to actually existing contemporary democracy.</p><p>What are we to make of these proposals? Starting with Rüstow, if the envisioned “dictatocracy” is really to remain within the boundaries of democracy, it would have to be established through a parliamentary vote changing the constitution. However, as he himself notes, “I am not enough of a utopian to assume that a proposition as I just sketched it would normally find a majority to change the constitution in the Reichstag today. … If we had a Reichstag where something like that was conceivable then the proposition would be unnecessary” (Rüstow, <span>1959</span>, p. 100). And given this “Catch 22,” which parallels the respective problems in Eucken, Rüstow must either bury his hopes for a truly transformative politics that walks the thin line between democracy and dictatorship, or he would have to discard his remnant democratic sensibilities and opt for dictatorial politics <i>sans phrase</i>.</p><p>Both Rüstow and Hayek face another more general problem, they leave largely unaddressed, namely, whether it is realistic to assume that transitional dictatorship remains transitional. To be sure, history knows instances where dictators or democratic leaders with de facto dictatorial powers quietly and dutifully stepped aside and thus enabled a return to normal conditions, but it was Hayek himself who had based his slippery slope argument in <i>The Road to Serfdom</i> on the notion that unchecked powers tend to become entrenched and engender a dynamic that tends toward the totalitarian. The plenitude of power required for comprehensive planning, as Hayek had argued back then, would even drag the most well-meaning socialists into the deadly politics of totalitarianism. Why would these mechanisms not apply to the transitional dictatorships that do not seek to pave the way toward socialism but liberal authoritarianism? A Hayekian line of defense may be to resort to a point contained in <i>The Road to Serfdom</i>, according to which such a dynamic is triggered only by economic interventionism and not political interventions, that is, if liberal authoritarianism abstained from economic interventions, it might arrest any potential totalitarian dynamic, but whether this differentiation is a convincing one is rather disputable. While Hayek at least has an argument, albeit a weak one, it remains a real mystery, why Rüstow never gave any explicit attention to this conundrum; all the more so, since he—and also Hayek—were acutely aware of the work of Carl Schmitt. And in his writings on the state of exception, one major and not entirely implausible point is that the liberal ambition of arresting the mercurial nature of a state of exception by codifying rules that govern its modalities and the emergency powers ensuing from it is ultimately futile. So if Rüstow's hope was that his version of a transitional dictatocracy would remain transitional because it was thus codified in the constitution—if there was ever a majority in favor of it—this is almost naïve from a Schmittian point of view. So we see that in both cases, the reform strategy proposed is incompatible with more or less explicit assumptions underlying the respective points of view.</p><p>Our final case study is the work of James Buchanan, who is also the most fascinating example because while Rüstow and Eucken mostly try to avoid the issue of strategy and implementation, he grapples with it directly over and over again.</p><p>Buchanan's specific challenge is not altogether different from the problems haunting the neoliberals we have already discussed. It can be stated quite succinctly in the form of a simple question that still proves to have rather devastating implications. If the assumptions of the public choice theory suggest that homo oeconomicus is a behavioral model appropriate for the analysis of political actors and rent-seeking is a practice not only rent seekers but also those who are in a position to grant rents, that is, politicians, benefit from, how can we assume that these actors will pass a constitutional balanced-budget amendment designed to curb among other things rent-seeking behavior?</p><p>Obviously, Buchanan was well aware of the problem he faced and undertook multiple unsuccessful attempts to deal with it, the chronicling of which would exceed the scope of the paper. Eventually, he found himself forced to rethink a crucial element in his own thought, namely, that of homo oeconomicus and how it was intertwined with rent-seeking behavior.</p><p>Over time he becomes more and more adamant that homo oeconomicus is just one of several personae that make up any actual person and at times suggests an almost dualist anthropology when he writes that there is “a struggle within each of us … between rent-seeker and the constitutionalists, and that almost all citizens will play, simultaneously, both roles” (Buchanan, <span>1991</span>, pp. 2, 10). This battle between normative orientations will become a site of major strategic importance for Buchanan because the conclusion he draws is that “the constitutionalist” in ourselves needs to be strengthened against the “rent-seeker” just as Rousseau thought the “citoyen” had to be strengthened vis-à-vis the “bourgeois.” It is only consequent, therefore, that Buchanan writes that “the reform that I seek lies first of all in attitudes” (Buchanan, <span>1975</span>, p. 176). This is noteworthy because it contradicts the claim routinely made by liberals or conservatives that they subscribe to a realist anthropology that “takes people as they are” and treats their preferences as “exogenous variables” refraining from any attempt to educate or change them but solely focus on social and political rules. Buchanan <i>does</i> want to change people, and he more and more explicitly embraces the notion that in this matter it is not enough to appeal to homo oeconomicus. In a paper titled “The Soul of Classical Liberalism,” Buchanan diagnoses the failure of liberalism to capture the hearts and minds of people because it lacks an appealing narrative: “Science and self-interest, especially as combined, do indeed lend force to any argument. But a vision of an ideal, over and beyond science and self-interest, is necessary, and those who profess membership in the club of classical liberals have failed singularly in their neglect of this requirement” (Buchanan, <span>2000</span>, p. 112). The constitutionalist in us cannot be strengthened through a “rational” argument appealing to the authority of science or self-interest alone, because what is at stake is an entire worldview that one comes to believe in. Only when attitudinal patterns have changed to a sufficient degree will it be possible to pursue the political project Buchanan continues to envision, which he describes as no less than a “constitutional revolution,” in sharp contrast to the incrementalism of “pragmatic reform” (Buchanan &amp; Di Pierro, <span>1969</span>, p. 95). However, this strategy entails a major concession that Buchanan himself spells out: “To hold out hope for reform in the basic rules describing the sociopolitical game, we must introduce elements that violate the self-interest postulate” (Brennan &amp; Buchanan, <span>1985</span>, p. 146). This is remarkable given that the entire critique of the rent-seeking society and actually existing democracy, of course, rests on the “self-interest postulate” of homo oeconomicus.</p><p>And so here we finally come to see that not only Buchanan had to attenuate his stance regarding the potential benevolence of actors, thus moving a little closer to the views of those who like Röpke place their hopes in a particular set of actors, but he also comes to commit himself not to a state of exception as a precondition of neoliberal reform but to what might be called a politics of the extraordinary with the radical connotations of a revolution. And so, in similarity to Hayek and Rüstow, Buchanan conceives of neoliberal reform politics as a caesura that can produce a real rupture of the iron cage of the ever same in which the entrenched rent-seeking networks are dismantled and the “basic rules of the sociopolitical rules” can finally be changed. Not only are these dreams of rupture shared by Buchanan and Hayek, but they are also expressed by Rüstow when he muses on “great politics, the politics that is the art of the impossible, that which wrongly was considered impossible” (Rüstow, <span>1963</span>, p. 117) and Friedman who envisions a political window of opportunity within which “what seemed impossible suddenly becomes possible” (Friedman &amp; Friedman, <span>1990</span>, p. xiv). What is on display here is an almost eschatological hope for the moment of the great rupture, the day of reckoning and of reversal, when the powers that be are unseated and a new kingdom will be erected—only here, it is not the kingdom of god but rather the realm of neoliberalism.</p><p>What I have developed in this paper is a critique of neoliberal thought that rests on the latter's inability to theorize in a consistent and plausible manner the problem of transition. The neoliberals in that sense are similar to those whom Marx described and derided as Utopian Socialists: bursting with visions about a better future but unable to develop strategies to realize these visions. Despite the variations described above, an overall pattern can still be detected: With their at times harsh criticisms of actually existing democracies, neoliberal thinkers back themselves into a theoretical corner because the more apocalyptic the critical diagnoses get, the more difficult it is to sketch a path out of the misery that is the status quo. Put differently, what the neoliberal critic gains in terms of the urgency of his diagnoses, the neoliberal reformer loses in terms of the viability of change. This confronts neoliberals with a dilemma encapsulated best in Buchanan's concession regarding the weakening of the self-interest postulate: Either neoliberals want to hold on to their trenchant critiques of democracy and the assumptions underlying them, but then they effectively forfeit the ability to also explain how conditions could possibly be changed and their accounts in effect turn into pessimistic conservatism. Or they want to be able to maintain the theoretical ability to capture the politics of neoliberal reform, but then they have to relax some of their assumptions and in effect scale back their critique of the democratic status quo significantly.</p><p>Describing this as a dilemma is the most modest version of this conclusion, which changes if we take the dimension of actually existing neoliberalism into account, which, after all, provides ample evidence for the possibility and factuality of neoliberal reform: The so-called debt brakes European countries have passed in response to the Eurozone Crisis is the equivalent of Buchanan's cherished balanced-budget amendment, and there are indeed such balanced-budget amendments on the state and municipal level in the United States (see Peck, <span>2014</span>). Furthermore, when it comes to actors sufficiently isolated from democratic pressures to make “rational” decisions, there are, prominently, central banks that have been granted independence with minimal accountability requirements across the OECD world, and there is the European Commission in charge of overseeing competition and deficit rules in the Eurozone, both of which can be considered to be part of what has been referred to as “the rise of the unelected” (Vibert, <span>2009</span>). Finally, one must not forget the international trade regimes, such as the WTO, free trade areas such as the European Union or Mercusor in South America, and free trade agreements such as CETA between Canada and the EU, all of which have effectively reined in the powers of sovereign nation-states in many trade-related areas and beyond (see Slobodian, <span>2018a</span>). Adding this aspect prompts several further questions. First, if there are clear examples of neoliberal reform, are the lacunae in neoliberal theory not essentially moot points, and is that not an indication of the insignificance of neoliberal theory in comparison with actually existing neoliberalism? Moreover, given the realization of neoliberal reforms, might there not be something like a performative theory of transition, which can be distilled from the nonacademic endeavors of someone like Buchanan? Finally, how does the conclusion regarding the dilemma referred to above change with this in mind? Let me begin with this last question: Old-fashioned falsificationism would tell us that if the conclusion of a theory is at odds with observed reality, this necessarily means that there is something wrong with the assumptions of the theory. Applied to the constellation at hand, this means: Neoliberal theory arrives at conclusions that are at odds with observed reality, that is, the facticity of neoliberal reform politics; therefore, there is something wrong with the assumptions of the theory, meaning that the neoliberal critiques of democracy, to the extent that they rest on these assumptions, have to be considered questionable. Regarding the second question, it is true that neoliberals such as Buchanan and Hayek had their ideas about how their ideas could have an impact, which, in Buchanan's case, is chronicled by Nancy Maclean in her controversial account of his nonacademic activities, including cooperation with various interest groups and shady donors (see MacLean, <span>2017</span>, pp. 199–204). Still, my point is that on the theoretical level, there are still lacunae that have repercussions for the plausibility of their critical analyses of democracy and this is what I am ultimately driving at with my argument.</p><p>Finally, Materialists will hasten to point out that identifying such lacunae will not make neoliberalism or its critique of democracy suddenly disappear and I agree. However, in order to be ultimately effective, the critique of neoliberalism must be conducted not only in the register of struggle and power politics, challenging actually existing neoliberalism but also in discursive contestation and the realm of theory on the basis of various kinds of critiques, including immanent ones pointing out inconsistencies, as I have tried to do here. Importantly, the argument contained in this paper is not supposed to “refute” neoliberal theory in its entirety, not the least because ideologies tend to contain contradictions, so identifying them does not necessarily deal a metaphorical death blow to them. My aim is a more specific one, namely, to highlight the dilemma that neoliberals face, which is most clearly on display in the case of Buchanan who openly concedes that the assumptions guiding his critique of democracy have to be relaxed in order to hold out hope for what he considers to be meaningful reforms, and thus undermine the plausibility of neoliberal arguments against democracy. There is no need to overstate the significance of such a critique, which is by no means sufficient, but, conversely, only focusing on the material level leaves to neoliberals the option of blaming unfaithful and incomplete implementation for any negative effect associated with, for example, introducing balanced-budget amendments, maintaining that their theoretical frameworks in themselves are not affected by this. It is such flaws in the framework that my critique aims to reveal.</p><p>Beyond this immediate conclusion, let me point out one more implication that appears to be worthy of more elaborate discussion in future research in light of what has been argued here:</p><p>Given the eschatological hopes neoliberals seem to harbor for a political rupture, this might also provide a link to the politics of what now is typically referred to as (right-wing) populism (but is de facto authoritarianism). After all, the self-portrayal of populist leaders who vow to “drain the swamp” and, generally, sweep aside decadent and corrupt establishments, corresponds to a considerable degree with what neoliberals apparently thought was necessary to overcome the gridlock and inertia of normal politics and implement neoliberal reforms. There can be little doubt that Hayek or Buchanan would have abhorred the notion of a Donald Trump as President of the United States or a Boris Johnson as Prime Minister of the UK—after all, they could not be any less “aristocrats of public spirit”; but still, the theoretical dilemmas their critiques of democracy create for them make the neoliberals inadvertently gravitate toward the kind of ruptural antiestablishment politics that populist movements and parties at least claim to represent. They are neoliberalism's “Frankenstein,” to borrow an expression from Wendy Brown (<span>2018</span>)—or its “bastards,” to borrow one from Quinn Slobodian (<span>2018b</span>). To be sure, one might argue that the Trump administration, to take a prominent example, attacked global regimes of economic multilateralism in the name of economic nationalism and would thus be in opposition to the kind of international free trade regimes, zones, and agreements cited above as manifestations of neoliberal reforms. However, upon closer inspection, the opposition to neoliberal designs turns out to be less than strict: The Trump administration indeed left NAFTA—but only to negotiate a new free trade zone called UMSCA with minimally better conditions for the United States. On the other hand, the tax reform under Trump could have just as well been passed under Reagan—in fact, Reagan's adviser from back then, Arthur Laffer, was also brought in as a consultant by the Trump administration. But while the opposition between them is overstated in many instances, my point is not that the substantive <i>policies</i> pursued by right-wing populists are all in congruence with neoliberal ideas. Rather, the major point of convergence between the two consists in their view of <i>politics</i> as necessarily disruptive in order to shake up the seemingly locked-in status quo dominated by mainstream political actors with no incentive to enact any real change to the “system.” By the same token, this is what turns both, neoliberals and right-wing populists, into antagonists of liberal democracy and its inertia, but while neoliberals dream of an ultra-stable world of almost self-enforcing rules to succeed in the moment of rupture, right-wing populists aim for the contrary: A world of rupture becoming permanent.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":51578,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory\",\"volume\":\"31 4\",\"pages\":\"506-519\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":1.2000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-09-25\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12713\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12713\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"POLITICAL SCIENCE\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12713","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"POLITICAL SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

新自由主义是一个众所周知的有争议的术语,甚至在那些主要赞同它的人(主要是它的批评者)中,激烈的争论持续存在于它的性质,如何正确地研究它,以及它是否仍然是理解当代世界和可能出现的“后新自由主义”的适当概念武器(Davies & Gane, 2021)。新自由主义应该如何定义——一种符合福柯治理学讲座精神的治理理性(福柯,2008),一种特定政策的组合,或者一种跨国资本恢复和保护利润率的战略(哈维,2005)——不仅存在争议,而且在什么层面上研究它,要么是“实际存在的新自由主义”(布伦纳和西奥多,2002;Cahill, 2014),一套理论和论点,或两者兼而有之。我这篇论文的出发点和重点是新自由主义思想,它以弗里德里希·哈耶克、米尔顿·弗里德曼、德国自由主义者以及詹姆斯·布坎南(James Buchanan)的著作为代表。我的目标是发展一种对新自由主义思想的批判性描述,这种描述将避免明确的规范性批评,而是选择一种更间接但更有效的、有点新颖的批评,这种批评将新自由主义坚持到自己的标准,并展示它是如何无法满足这些标准的,或者在试图这样做的过程中被推入高度可疑的立场。论点如下:如前所述,新自由主义的意义备受争议,因此我将通过对新自由主义的简要描述来提供我的论点的基础,新自由主义依赖于对其在20世纪中叶左右出现的背景的理论-历史重建。我从这种重构中得出的结论是,我们最好不要过分缩小新自由主义的范围,也不要淡化其内部的异质性。因此,与其试图将一些理论或立场作为典型的新自由主义,甚至认为它们是新自由主义的“本质”,我认为,统一新自由主义话语的不是一套积极的信念——尽管在某些领域有一些重大的重叠——而是一个与功能市场的先决条件有关的共同问题。根据新自由主义思想家的观点,在所有问题中,民主是最紧迫的问题之一,因为几乎所有人都同意,民主使建立和确保市场运作的任务变得复杂。然而,尽管有这种基本的共识,新自由主义对民主的描述显示出相当大范围的关于其功能失调甚至病态的性质和来源的具体诊断。因此,本文的第二步是对一些由新自由主义者领导的民主批判路线的调查。除其他事项外,这项调查有助于我们欣赏新自由主义思想的异质性,但更重要的是,就我的目的而言,它还让我们了解到新自由主义者对民主的深刻保留以及他们批判的尖锐本质。由于新自由主义者对民主的具体批评各不相同,因此提出的补救措施和改革建议也各不相同。因此,在接下来的步骤中,我们将仔细审查几个选定的改革建议,从含糊的呼吁“强大的国家”到哈耶克的“模范宪法”,以及更具体的关于引入宪法平衡预算修正案的论点,这是布坎南的标志性要求。这项调查向我们展示了新自由主义改革建议的激进本质,这对我的整体论点很重要。尽管所有这些改革建议都具有高度争议性的含义,但我将故意放弃直接基于规范性论点进行讨论。相反,我的批评集中在新自由主义诊断和各自补救措施之间缺失的分析联系上。为了说明这一点,本文的第四部分也是最后一部分将注意力转移到新自由主义转型的政治上,也就是说,这种政治是否以及如何在新自由主义的描述中理论化。再一次,哈耶克、欧肯和布坎南之间存在一定程度的差异,但这里的共同点是无法在不违反各自的批判性诊断假设的情况下将这种政治理论化,或者超越自由民主的范围作为实施这种改革的条件。因此,我想在下文中捍卫的关键论点是,新自由主义思想对所谓的过渡问题缺乏任何合理的解决方案——如果他们愿意对此进行反思的话这些发现导致了几种不同的解释,或多或少具有深远的影响,将在结论部分讨论。如今,注意到新自由主义一词的争议性和潜在的空洞性是司空见惯的。 新自由主义是一个众所周知的有争议的术语,即使在那些主要赞同它的人(主要是它的批评者)之间,激烈的争论也在继续,关于它的本质,如何正确地研究它,以及它是否仍然是理解当代世界和一个可能出现的“后新自由主义”的适当概念武器。Gane, 2021)。新自由主义应该如何定义——一种符合福柯治理学讲座精神的治理理性(Foucault, 2008),一种特定政策的组合,或者一种跨国资本恢复和保护利润率的战略(Harvey, 2005)——不仅存在争议,而且在什么层面上研究它,要么是“实际存在的新自由主义”(Brenner &amp;西奥多,2002;Cahill, 2014),一套理论和论点,或两者兼而有之。我这篇论文的出发点和重点是新自由主义思想,它以弗里德里希·哈耶克、米尔顿·弗里德曼、德国自由主义者以及詹姆斯·布坎南(James Buchanan)的著作为代表。我的目标是发展一种对新自由主义思想的批判性描述,这种描述将避免明确的规范性批评,而是选择一种更间接但更有效的、有点新颖的批评,这种批评将新自由主义坚持到自己的标准,并展示它是如何无法满足这些标准的,或者在试图这样做的过程中被推入高度可疑的立场。论点如下:如前所述,新自由主义的意义备受争议,因此我将通过对新自由主义的简要描述来提供我的论点的基础,新自由主义依赖于对其在20世纪中叶左右出现的背景的理论-历史重建。我从这种重构中得出的结论是,我们最好不要过分缩小新自由主义的范围,也不要淡化其内部的异质性。因此,与其试图将一些理论或立场作为典型的新自由主义,甚至认为它们是新自由主义的“本质”,我认为,统一新自由主义话语的不是一套积极的信念——尽管在某些领域有一些重大的重叠——而是一个与功能市场的先决条件有关的共同问题。根据新自由主义思想家的观点,在所有问题中,民主是最紧迫的问题之一,因为几乎所有人都同意,民主使建立和确保市场运作的任务变得复杂。然而,尽管有这种基本的共识,新自由主义对民主的描述显示出相当大范围的关于其功能失调甚至病态的性质和来源的具体诊断。因此,本文的第二步是对一些由新自由主义者领导的民主批判路线的调查。除其他事项外,这项调查有助于我们欣赏新自由主义思想的异质性,但更重要的是,就我的目的而言,它还让我们了解到新自由主义者对民主的深刻保留以及他们批判的尖锐本质。由于新自由主义者对民主的具体批评各不相同,因此提出的补救措施和改革建议也各不相同。因此,在接下来的步骤中,我们将仔细审查几个选定的改革建议,从含糊的呼吁“强大的国家”到哈耶克的“模范宪法”,以及更具体的关于引入宪法平衡预算修正案的论点,这是布坎南的标志性要求。这项调查向我们展示了新自由主义改革建议的激进本质,这对我的整体论点很重要。尽管所有这些改革建议都具有高度争议性的含义,但我将故意放弃直接基于规范性论点进行讨论。相反,我的批评集中在新自由主义诊断和各自补救措施之间缺失的分析联系上。为了说明这一点,本文的第四部分也是最后一部分将注意力转移到新自由主义转型的政治上,也就是说,这种政治是否以及如何在新自由主义的描述中理论化。再一次,哈耶克、欧肯和布坎南之间存在一定程度的差异,但这里的共同点是无法在不违反各自的批判性诊断假设的情况下将这种政治理论化,或者超越自由民主的范围作为实施这种改革的条件。因此,我想在下文中捍卫的关键论点是,新自由主义思想对所谓的过渡问题缺乏任何合理的解决方案——如果他们愿意对此进行反思的话。这些发现导致了几种不同的解释,这些解释或多或少具有深远的影响,将在结论部分讨论。如今,注意到新自由主义一词的争议性和潜在的空洞性是司空见惯的。 如果公共选择理论的假设表明,经济人是一种适用于分析政治行为者的行为模型,而寻租不仅是寻租者的一种行为,而且是那些能够给予租金的人(即政治家)的一种行为,那么我们怎么能假设这些行为者会通过一项旨在遏制寻租行为的宪法平衡预算修正案呢?显然,布坎南很清楚他所面临的问题,并进行了多次不成功的尝试来处理它,其中的编年史将超出本文的范围。最终,他发现自己不得不重新思考自己思想中的一个关键因素,即经济人,以及它是如何与寻租行为交织在一起的。随着时间的推移,他越来越坚定地认为,经济人只是构成任何实际人物的几个人格之一,有时他写道,“我们每个人内部……在寻租者和立宪主义者之间存在着一场斗争,几乎所有公民都将同时扮演这两个角色”,这几乎暗示了一种二元人类学。对布坎南来说,这种规范取向之间的斗争将成为一个具有重大战略意义的地方,因为他得出的结论是,我们内心的“宪政主义者”需要加强,以对抗“寻租者”,就像卢梭认为“公民”必须加强,以对抗-à-vis“资产阶级”一样。因此,布坎南写道:“我所寻求的改革首先在于态度”(布坎南,1975年,第176页)。这是值得注意的,因为它与自由派或保守派的常规说法相矛盾,他们赞同现实主义人类学,即“接受人的本来面貌”,并将他们的偏好视为“外生变量”,避免任何教育或改变他们的企图,而只关注社会和政治规则。布坎南确实想改变人们,而且他越来越明确地接受这样一种观点,即在这个问题上,仅仅诉诸经济人是不够的。在一篇名为《古典自由主义的灵魂》的论文中,布坎南指出,自由主义未能抓住人们的心灵和思想,因为它缺乏一种吸引人的叙述:“科学和自身利益,尤其是结合起来,确实会给任何论点带来力量。但是,超越科学和自身利益的理想愿景是必要的,那些自称是古典自由主义者俱乐部成员的人在忽视这一要求方面失败了。”(布坎南,2000,第112页)。我们内心的立宪主义者不能仅仅通过诉诸科学权威或自身利益的“理性”论证来加强,因为岌岌可危的是我们逐渐相信的整个世界观。只有当态度模式改变到足够的程度时,才有可能追求布坎南继续设想的政治计划,他将其描述为不亚于“宪法革命”,与“实用主义改革”的渐进主义形成鲜明对比。Di Pierro, 1969, p. 95)。然而,这一策略需要布坎南自己阐明的一个重大让步:“为了在描述社会政治游戏的基本规则中保持改革的希望,我们必须引入违反自利假设的元素”(布伦南& &;布坎南,1985,第146页)。考虑到对寻租社会和实际存在的民主的整个批判,当然是建立在经济人的“自利假设”之上,这一点是值得注意的。这里我们终于来看,不仅布坎南不得不减弱他的立场对于演员的潜在仁慈,因此更靠近了一点的观点那些喜欢Ropke希望寄托在一个特定的演员,但他也提交不例外状态为前提的新自由主义改革,但可能是所谓的政治的激进革命的内涵。因此,与哈耶克和赖斯托相似,布坎南认为新自由主义改革政治是一种停顿,它可以真正打破一成不变的铁笼,在这个铁笼中,根深蒂固的寻租网络被拆除,“社会政治规则的基本规则”最终可以改变。布坎南和哈耶克不仅分享了这些破裂的梦想,而且当r<e:1>斯托沉思“伟大的政治,政治是不可能的艺术,错误地认为不可能”(r<e:1>斯托,1963,第117页)和弗里德曼设想一个政治机会之窗时,他们也表达了这些梦想,在这个机会之窗内,“似乎不可能的突然变得可能”(弗里德曼&;弗里德曼,1990,第14页)。 这里所展示的几乎是对大决裂时刻的末世论的希望,清算和逆转的那一天,当他的权力被推翻,一个新的王国将被建立起来——只是在这里,它不是上帝的王国,而是新自由主义的王国。我在这篇论文中发展的是对新自由主义思想的批判,这种批判基于后者无法以一致和合理的方式将过渡问题理论化。在这个意义上,新自由主义者与那些被马克思描述并嘲笑为乌托邦社会主义者的人相似:对更美好的未来充满憧憬,但却无法制定实现这些愿景的战略。尽管有以上描述的变化,一个整体的模式仍然可以被发现:随着他们对实际存在的民主国家的有时严厉的批评,新自由主义思想家把自己退到一个理论的角落,因为批评性的诊断越具有启示性,就越难以描绘出一条摆脱现状的痛苦之路。换句话说,新自由主义批评家在诊断的紧迫性方面有所收获,而新自由主义改革者在变革的可行性方面则有所损失。这让新自由主义者面临着一个两难的困境,布坎南对自身利益假设的削弱做出了最好的让步:要么新自由主义者想要坚持他们对民主及其基础假设的尖锐批评,但随后他们实际上丧失了解释条件如何可能改变的能力,他们的描述实际上变成了悲观的保守主义。或者,他们希望能够保持捕捉新自由主义改革政治的理论能力,但随后他们必须放松一些假设,实际上大大减少对民主现状的批评。将此描述为一个困境是这个结论的最温和的版本,如果我们考虑到实际存在的新自由主义的维度,这个结论就会改变,毕竟,这为新自由主义改革的可能性和事实性提供了充分的证据:欧洲国家为应对欧元区危机而通过的所谓“债务刹车”相当于布坎南所珍视的平衡预算修正案,美国确实存在州和市一级的平衡预算修正案(见Peck, 2014)。此外,当涉及到充分孤立于民主压力而做出“理性”决定的行为者时,在经合组织世界中,有一些中央银行被授予独立性,责任要求最低,还有欧盟委员会负责监督欧元区的竞争和赤字规则,这两者都可以被认为是“非选举的崛起”的一部分(Vibert, 2009)。最后,我们不能忘记国际贸易制度,如世界贸易组织,自由贸易区,如欧盟或南美的Mercusor,以及自由贸易协定,如加拿大和欧盟之间的CETA,所有这些都有效地控制了主权民族国家在许多与贸易相关的领域和其他领域的权力(见Slobodian, 2018a)。添加这个方面会引发几个进一步的问题。首先,如果有明确的新自由主义改革的例子,那么新自由主义理论中的空白不是本质上没有意义的问题吗?这不是新自由主义理论与实际存在的新自由主义相比无足轻重的迹象吗?此外,考虑到新自由主义改革的实现,是否可能存在某种类似于行为转型理论的东西,它可以从布坎南等人的非学术努力中提炼出来?最后,考虑到这一点,关于上述困境的结论是如何变化的?让我以最后一个问题开始:老式的证伪主义会告诉我们,如果一个理论的结论与观察到的现实不一致,这必然意味着该理论的假设有问题。应用于手头的星座,这意味着:新自由主义理论得出的结论与观察到的现实不一致,即新自由主义改革政治的真实性;因此,该理论的假设是错误的,这意味着新自由主义对民主的批评,就其基于这些假设的程度而言,必须被认为是有问题的。关于第二个问题,像布坎南和哈耶克这样的新自由主义者确实有他们的想法,关于他们的想法如何产生影响,在布坎南的情况下,南希·麦克林在她对布坎南的非学术活动的有争议的描述中记录了这一点,包括与各种利益集团和可疑捐助者的合作(见麦克林,2017,第199-204页)。 不过,我的观点是,在理论层面上,他们对民主的批判性分析的合理性仍然存在一些影响,这就是我在我的论点中最终想要表达的。最后,唯物主义者会迅速指出,识别这样的漏洞不会使新自由主义或其对民主的批评突然消失,我同意这一点。然而,为了最终有效,对新自由主义的批评不仅必须在斗争和权力政治的范围内进行,挑战实际存在的新自由主义,而且必须在话语争论和基于各种批评的理论领域中进行,包括指出不一致的内在批评,正如我在这里试图做的那样。重要的是,本文所包含的论点不应该完全“反驳”新自由主义理论,尤其是因为意识形态往往包含矛盾,因此识别它们并不一定会对它们造成隐喻性的致命打击。我的目标是一个更具体的目标,即强调新自由主义者面临的困境,这在布坎南的案例中表现得最为明显,他公开承认,指导他对民主的批判的假设必须放宽,以便对他认为有意义的改革抱有希望,从而削弱新自由主义反对民主的论点的合理性。没有必要夸大这种批评的重要性,这绝不是充分的,但是,相反,只关注物质层面,新自由主义者可以选择将任何负面影响归咎于不忠实和不完整的实施,例如,引入平衡预算修正案,坚持他们的理论框架本身不受此影响。我的批评旨在揭示的正是这个框架中的这些缺陷。除了这个直接的结论之外,让我指出另一个似乎值得在未来的研究中根据这里的争论进行更详细讨论的含义:鉴于新自由主义者似乎对政治破裂的末世论希望,这也可能与现在通常被称为(右翼)民粹主义(但实际上是威权主义)的政治联系起来。毕竟,民粹主义领导人誓言“抽干沼泽”,一般来说,扫除腐朽和腐败的机构,在很大程度上符合新自由主义者显然认为克服常规政治的僵局和惰性并实施新自由主义改革所必需的东西。毫无疑问,哈耶克或布坎南会厌恶唐纳德·特朗普(Donald Trump)当美国总统或鲍里斯·约翰逊(Boris Johnson)当英国首相——毕竟,他们都是“具有公共精神的贵族”;但是,他们对民主的批判给他们带来的理论困境,使新自由主义者无意中倾向于民粹主义运动和政党至少声称代表的那种破裂的反建制政治。借用Wendy Brown(2018)的说法,他们是新自由主义的“弗兰肯斯坦”——或者借用Quinn Slobodian (2018b)的说法,他们是新自由主义的“混蛋”。可以肯定的是,有人可能会说,举一个突出的例子,特朗普政府以经济民族主义的名义攻击全球经济多边主义制度,因此反对上述国际自由贸易制度、区域和协议,这些都是新自由主义改革的表现。然而,仔细观察就会发现,对新自由主义设计的反对并不严格:特朗普政府确实离开了nafta,但只是为了谈判一个名为UMSCA的新自由贸易区,对美国的条件只有最低限度的改善。另一方面,特朗普领导下的税收改革也可以在里根领导下通过——事实上,里根当时的顾问阿瑟·拉弗(Arthur Laffer)也是特朗普政府聘请的顾问。但是,虽然他们之间的对立在许多情况下被夸大了,但我的观点并不是说右翼民粹主义者所追求的实质性政策都与新自由主义思想一致。更确切地说,两者之间的主要共同点在于,他们认为政治必须具有破坏性,以便动摇看似锁定的现状,这些现状由主流政治行动者主导,没有动力对“系统”进行任何真正的改变。出于同样的原因,新自由主义者和右翼民粹主义者都成了自由民主及其惰性的对手,但新自由主义者梦想着一个超稳定的世界,这个世界几乎是自我执行的规则,可以在破裂的时刻取得成功,而右翼民粹主义者的目标恰恰相反:一个破裂的世界成为永久性的。 面对这些指控,研究新自由主义的学者往往急于对新自由主义给出某种可行的定义,以免人们怀疑他们是在用一个带有政治意义而非分析意义的空洞能指来操作。因此,一套政策——通常以华盛顿共识的议程为中心——被认为是典型的新自由主义,某些想法或原则被认为构成了其核心或本质,或者,新自由主义仅仅是蒙特·普勒林协会成员颁布的,这是一种优雅的,但经过仔细检查,并不是完全令人信服的方式来规避问题(乔姆斯基,1999;克劳奇,2011;米卢斯基,Plehwe, 2009)。另一方面,学者们经常介入,强调新自由主义的巨大可变性/可转化性,以及它与其他政治-智力项目形成或多或少充满紧张的融合的特征能力,这使得似乎不可能,或者至少在智力上是不谨慎的,旨在“固定”新自由主义及其含义的一些硬性和快速的定义:“新自由主义的清晰、明确的本质主义定义已被证明是难以捉摸的”(Peck, 2010,第8页)。我自己对新自由主义的描述将试图在过于简约的定义尝试(在更仔细的审查下无法维持)和分析失败主义的解决方案之间取得平衡,将新自由主义分解为各种各样的新自由主义,据称这些新自由主义除了维特根斯坦家族的相似性之外没有任何共同点。我的概念方法的出发点是观察到新自由主义如今已经成为一个真正有害的标签,因此,首先看看那些在当时将自己描述为新自由主义者的人(尽管是短暂而不情愿的),并澄清他们贴上“新自由主义”标签的知识和政治议程,可能会有所帮助。换句话说,有必要重建新自由主义出现的知识和政治背景。出现的过程不是单一的起源,而是分散的,新自由主义也是如此。然而,我们有可能将Walter Lippmann会议确定为新自由主义的“诞生”,因为它是这些过程的第一个顶点,也是这个术语第一次被正式采用的事件,它表示参与者的共同议程,其中不仅包括Hayek, Wilhelm Röpke和Alexander r<e:1> stow,还包括Jacques Rueff, Louis Rougier(会议召集人),当然还有Walter Lippmann本人。在这一点上,关于Colloque的一个令人印象深刻的奖学金存在,所以没有必要进入程序的细节(见Burgin, 2012;Dardot,赖伐尔2013;Innset, 2020;Reinhoudt,Audier, 2018)。从他们身上浮现出的整体图景是一种处于防御状态的自由主义,它试图重新获得真正竞争者的地位,以对抗其主要对手集体主义和当时的凯恩斯主义(程度较低)。在除了路德维希·冯·米塞斯之外的几乎所有参与者的眼中,这一努力的前提是对古典自由主义议程进行批判性的修订,而且,最值得注意的是,放弃简单的公式,如“自由放任”,或者一些人所说的“曼彻斯特主义”。因此,这里形成的新自由主义话语与“自我调节市场”的信条相去甚远。相反,新自由主义方法的全部要点是,肯定市场的价值,反对集体主义者和凯恩斯主义者,同时坚持认为,它们远不如自由主义传统的大部分人在这一点上倾向于相信的那样强大和自我维持。更明确地说,市场本身并不是解决所有问题的办法;相反,市场本身变成了新自由主义思想的一个问题,因为它被视为一个需要持续关注的实体,并以许多先决条件为前提。因此,我所说的新自由主义问题与功能市场的先决条件有关,即价格机制尽可能不受干扰地支配的市场。新自由主义话语的不可简化的异质性不仅仅是由于这个问题可以被阐明和解决的多种多样的,有时是相互矛盾的方式。然而,显而易见的是,新自由主义思想可能以市场概念为中心,但那些工作被这个问题所激发的人的智力能量,如布坎南、哈耶克或德国的自由主义者,不可避免地被吸引到需要到位的基础设施上,并为这些市场的运作抵御不断变化的对手。这是社会和政治的领域,因此,对新自由主义者来说,投入如此多的时间来概念化国家和民主是严格的。 面对这些指控,研究新自由主义的学者往往急于对新自由主义给出某种可行的定义,以免人们怀疑他们是在用一个带有政治意义而非分析意义的空洞能指来操作。因此,一套政策——通常以华盛顿共识的议程为中心——被认为是典型的新自由主义,某些想法或原则被认为构成了其核心或本质,或者,新自由主义仅仅是蒙特·普勒林协会成员颁布的,这是一种优雅的,但经过仔细检查,并不是完全令人信服的方式来规避问题(乔姆斯基,1999;克劳奇,2011;Mirowski & Plehwe, 2009)。另一方面,学者们经常介入,强调新自由主义的巨大可变性/可转化性,以及它与其他政治-智力项目形成或多或少充满紧张的融合的特征能力,这使得似乎不可能,或者至少在智力上是不谨慎的,旨在“固定”新自由主义及其含义的一些硬性和快速的定义:“新自由主义的清晰、明确的本质主义定义已被证明是难以捉摸的”(Peck, 2010,第8页)。我自己对新自由主义的描述将试图在过于简约的定义尝试(在更仔细的审查下无法维持)和分析失败主义的解决方案之间取得平衡,将新自由主义分解为各种各样的新自由主义,据称这些新自由主义除了维特根斯坦家族的相似性之外没有任何共同点。我的概念方法的出发点是观察到新自由主义如今已经成为一个真正有害的标签,因此,首先看看那些在当时将自己描述为新自由主义者的人(尽管是短暂而不情愿的),并澄清他们贴上“新自由主义”标签的知识和政治议程,可能会有所帮助。换句话说,有必要重建新自由主义出现的知识和政治背景。出现的过程不是单一的起源,而是分散的,新自由主义也是如此。然而,我们有可能将Walter Lippmann会议确定为新自由主义的“诞生”,因为它是这些过程的第一个顶点,也是这个术语第一次被正式采用的事件,它表示参与者的共同议程,其中不仅包括Hayek, Wilhelm Röpke和Alexander r<e:1> stow,还包括Jacques Rueff, Louis Rougier(会议召集人),当然还有Walter Lippmann本人。在这一点上,关于Colloque的一个令人印象深刻的奖学金存在,所以没有必要进入程序的细节(见Burgin, 2012;Dardot & Laval, 2013;Innset, 2020;Reinhoudt & Audier, 2018)。从他们身上浮现出的整体图景是一种处于防御状态的自由主义,它试图重新获得真正竞争者的地位,以对抗其主要对手集体主义和当时的凯恩斯主义(程度较低)。在除了路德维希·冯·米塞斯之外的几乎所有参与者的眼中,这一努力的前提是对古典自由主义议程进行批判性的修订,而且,最值得注意的是,放弃简单的公式,如“自由放任”,或者一些人所说的“曼彻斯特主义”。因此,这里形成的新自由主义话语与“自我调节市场”的信条相去甚远。相反,新自由主义方法的全部要点是,肯定市场的价值,反对集体主义者和凯恩斯主义者,同时坚持认为,它们远不如自由主义传统的大部分人在这一点上倾向于相信的那样强大和自我维持。更明确地说,市场本身并不是解决所有问题的办法;相反,市场本身变成了新自由主义思想的一个问题,因为它被视为一个需要持续关注的实体,并以许多先决条件为前提。因此,我所说的新自由主义的问题与功能市场的先决条件有关,也就是说,价格机制尽可能不受干扰地支配的市场新自由主义话语的不可简化的异质性不仅仅是由于这个问题可以被阐明和解决的多种多样的,有时是相互矛盾的方式。然而,显而易见的是,新自由主义思想可能以市场概念为中心,但那些工作被这个问题所激发的人的智力能量,如布坎南、哈耶克或德国的自由主义者,不可避免地被吸引到需要到位的基础设施上,并为这些市场的运作抵御不断变化的对手。这是社会和政治的领域,因此,对新自由主义者来说,投入如此多的时间来概念化国家和民主是严格的。 当新自由主义者谈论民主时,他们通常指的是现有形式的民主,也就是说,他们的话语很少冒险对民主的本质和理论进行哲学探索。他们论述的主要形式是对各自当代代议制民主形式的批判。这些各自的背景在民主的各种描述上留下了印记,但在本调查中,我将重点介绍我认为可以分析区分的新自由主义民主批判的三种类型的论点或变体,而不是探究每一种的细节。4这里讨论的第一组反对民主的论点在自由主义论述中特别突出,但并非是自由主义所独有的:5对于Wilhelm Röpke和Walter Eucken来说,与民主相关的主要威胁是由于政治舞台上一种新现象的影响,即群众。随着大众民主的兴起,后者在政治决策方面获得了前所未有的影响力,或者至少这是自由主义者(尤其是自由主义者)运作的假设。因此,问题不在于群众本身的存在,而在于他们通过群众民主制度融入政治进程,因为它在20世纪上半叶不均匀但稳定地展开。虽然对大众的厌恶似乎只不过是对多数人暴政的自由-保守主义主题的一种变体,但它还有更多的含义。群众不仅仅是多数。在古斯塔夫·勒邦的《人群》、西格蒙德·弗洛伊德的《群体心理学和自我分析》以及何塞·奥尔特加·y·加塞特的《群众的反抗》(他被邀请参加座谈会,但没有参加)的话语中,群众的概念在心理上(有时是种族上)充满了色彩。大众被认为具有幼稚和普遍的非理性,这使他们成为煽动者的完美塑造材料,这些煽动者利用他们不加批判的接受能力和可塑性来动员他们参与政治项目——从世界自由主义者的角度来看,通常涉及国家计划和集体化。这一立场有充足的文本证据,所以这里举几个例子就足够作为这种解释的基础。Eucken指出:“但是,虽然人们只能生活在某些秩序中,但群众倾向于摧毁这些确切的秩序”(Eucken, 1960,第14页),并且在1932年开创自由主义传统的经典文本之一中,他哀叹“民主化的同时进程赋予了政党,以及他们组织的群众和利益集团对国家管理的更大影响力,从而影响了经济政策”(Eucken, 2017,[1932],第59页)。Röpke补充了这些观点:“在所有国家,在一些国家,在另一些国家,社会已经被磨成一群个人,他们从未如此紧密地聚集在一起,如此相互依赖,但同时他们比以往任何时候都更无根,更孤立,更像沙粒……我们时代所有的苦难,所有的问题最终都植根于这里……”(Röpke, 1950,[1942],第92页)。在其他地方,他引用了上述大众的社会心理框架:“作为‘大众’的一部分,我们不同于正常情况下的我们,也不同于健康情况下的我们;我们是次等人类,像群氓一样,社会状态危险地与我们自己的状态相对应”(Röpke, 1960, p. 53)。虽然可能被称为质量综合症的最极端的表现只发生在Röpke所称的“急性状态”的质量中,但作为一种永久状态的质量化几乎不那么令人担忧,因为它预示着以Röpke希望捍卫的“不可改变的自然贵族”为代价的平庸野兽的统治(Röpke, 1960,第55页)。总结这一批评路线,经济政策太重要、太复杂了,不能把它交给任性的群众,在代议制民主国家,他们可能不会进入议会,也不会管理政府,但在大众民主的条件下,即使只是作为蛊惑人心的鼓动和动员的对象,他们仍然具有太大的影响力。如果这些力量的联盟有他们的方式,民主必然会转变为集体主义,即新自由主义思想的主要对手:“不可否认的是:集体主义国家植根于群众”(Röpke, 1950, p. 86)。第二种批评的经典表述也要归功于另一位自由主义者,即亚历山大·赖斯托。除了当代民主的群众层面之外,这种批评的目标是所谓的过度“多元主义”。 r<e:1>斯托简洁地总结了各自的核心关切:“一些经济领先国家的民主议会制结构导致经济腐败蔓延到国家的内部政策、政党和[sic!议会制度本身。政党慢慢转变为经济压力集团的议会机构,并由它们提供资金。……以这种方式发展的病态政府形式是多元化的……”(r<e:1>斯托,2017a,[1942],第159页)。在大众民主的条件下,(经济)压力集团将获得非凡的影响力,他们几乎可以把自己的意志强加给政党;其结果是模糊定义的共同利益被边缘化,被溶解在欧肯毫不含糊地称之为“群体无政府状态”(Eucken, 1960, p. 171)。国家,作为这种共同利益的假定守护者,在经济政治庇护主义的过程中被削弱了,r<e:1>斯托在他的结论中呼应了卡尔·施密特对多元主义的严厉批评:“这里发生的事情符合座右铭:‘国家作为猎物’”(r<e:1>斯托,2017b,[1932],第147页)。在不受约束的多元主义条件下,国家不断被削弱,由此产生的离心动力最终变得难以管理,因为政治共同体在社会各个角落出现的特殊行为者手中分崩离析。第三,有一条严格的当代批评路线,仍然显示出与刚才概述的多元主义批判的一些对应关系。这一批判的核心定理是寻租,它描述了一种寻求获得某种优势的行为,这种行为不是通过生产行动和竞争,而是通过游说获得某种特殊待遇,通常是豁免某些规则。这一观点建立在博弈论和理性选择方法的见解之上,根据这一观点,当(通常有益的)规则适用于除个人之外的所有人时,个人效用通常会最大化,而对民主的公共选择批评大多是围绕这一基本概念建立的:在民主条件下,对社会/经济行为者的特殊待遇的不断要求,以政治行为者的形式得到了热切的满足,希望以此增加他们再次当选的机会。作为公共选择传统的共同创始人之一,布坎南理所当然地将寻租定理置于他对代议制民主的批判的中心,他并不是唯一这样做的新自由主义者:米尔顿·弗里德曼以及后来的哈耶克偶尔(尽管不是系统地)借鉴寻租的基本逻辑(见弗里德曼和哈耶克)。弗里德曼,1984)。据称,寻租所带来的根本问题可以用以下方式总结:假设每个人都参与寻租,个人理性决定了一个人也这样做,因为否则,他将间接处于不利地位,因为其他人获得豁免,而这些规则仍然适用于他。这意味着寻租具有内在的扩张性动态,作为一种一般做法,它违背了其主体的意图,因为即使个人寻租可能成功并提供了优势,这也远远超过了所有其他寻租活动(假设它们也成功)所带来的多重劣势。因此,在追求个人效用的过程中,社会中的行动者最终将自己置于不利地位。就像在多元主义的场景中一样,这里盛行的是特殊主义,尽管带有悲剧性的转折。但是,“寻租社会”(Buchanan et al., 1980)不仅伤害其现有成员:豁免和其他特殊待遇通常是有一定代价的,由于在公共选择假设下,通过增税融资不是一个现实的选择,而且立法者和政府对通货膨胀的控制越来越少,支付租金的主要策略是通过赤字和债务负担,让几乎众所周知的“后代”承担他们没有发言权的财务义务——可以说,这明显违反了自治的民主原则。最后,还有一条批判路线,聚焦于与民主相关的法治的衰落,并对后者所谓的不受限制的本质提出质疑。这一论点的主要范例是弗里德里希·奥古斯特·哈耶克,他在许多著作中阐述了这一观点的各个方面。可以肯定的是,哈耶克承认民主在原则上有其优点:“这是我们迄今为止发现的使和平变革成为可能的唯一公约”(哈耶克,2003,III,第137页)。然而,民主的理想及其限制权力的基本推动力随着时间的推移而变得丑陋。 简而言之,《自由宪法》已经包含了哈耶克批判的中心点:“教条民主派的关键概念是人民主权。对他来说,这意味着多数决定原则是不受限制的。民主的理想,原本旨在防止所有的专断权力,因此成为一个新的专断权力的理由”(哈耶克,2006,第93页)。根据哈耶克的说法,更深层次的原因是法治原则的侵蚀,他在《自由宪法》中记录了这一点,其中包括,突出地,任何构成真正法律的正式先决条件的丧失。在自由主义的全盛时期,只有那些抽象的、一般性的、针对未来行为的法律规则才被认为是正确意义上的法律,而如今,哈耶克声称,立法机关产生的任何东西都被认为具有法律的权力,从而赋予议会参与他认为在任何层面上都有害的那种自由裁量的计划活动的权力。由于对这种不受约束的民主不再有任何正式的限制,政治家们没有任何工具可以用来抵御社会利益集团的要求。“问题的根源当然是,总结起来,在一个无限制的民主中,自由裁量权的持有者被迫使用它们,无论他们希望与否,以支持他们的权力所依赖的摇摆投票的特定群体”(哈耶克,2003,III, p. 139),哈耶克总结道,因此在这方面呼应了上面概述的第二和第三行批评。哈耶克的主要论点,是对多数人统治的民主的批判——这在《自由宪法》(见哈耶克,2006年,第90-102页)中得到了最突出的阐述——和多数人统治不再以任何有意义的方式受到限制的争论,从而产生了一种几乎反乌托邦的“无限民主”,哈耶克认为,这最终将导致极权主义:“《法律、立法与自由》这部著作的灵感来自于人们对过去被视为最先进国家的政治秩序走向的日益担忧。由于普遍接受的“民主”政府的某些根深蒂固的建设缺陷,这种向极权主义国家发展的威胁性发展是不可避免的,这迫使我思考各种替代安排”(哈耶克,2003,I, p. xx)。我们现在转向这里讨论的各种新自由主义著作中的这些替代安排。调查新自由主义领袖们提出的每一项改革建议将超出本文的范围,因此我将只关注布坎南、哈耶克以及自由主义学者<s:1>斯托夫和欧肯分别提出的三种或多或少具体的改革愿景,它们将处理民主的各种缺陷或病态,因为它们在前一节概述的诊断中被精确地指出。让我们从可以说是新自由主义改革组合中最具体的建议开始,这是詹姆斯·布坎南提出的一个标志性要求,尽管米尔顿·弗里德曼也提出了一个略有不同的版本。该提案旨在解决从事寻租行为的倾向,或者更确切地说,是代表当选官员向利益集团支付租金,以提高连任的机会。多年来,布坎南对(美国)民主的评价变得越来越悲观,最终声称“对历史经验的吸引力,尤其是对美国最近发生的事件的吸引力,确实表明,在目前的制度设置下,政府接近于脱离选民的控制”(布伦南&安培;布坎南,1980年,第25页)。为了应对这种日益恶化的形势,布坎南的主要建议之一是,通过更严格地控制公共支出的融资方式,采取遏制过度民主的策略。民主所需要的是一种规则,可以排除这些支出的债务/赤字融资,最好是在尽可能高的法律层面上制定:宪法平衡预算修正案(Buchanan, 1997)。修正案将规定,所有当前的国家支出必须通过实际收入提供资金,无论是税收还是其他;增加赤字和债务来为国家支出提供资金,这将是完全违宪的。考虑到这些限制,政治家们应该控制失控的支出并削减公共支出,而不是试图依靠低税收策略来赢得选举。 对于这样一个提议的影响,这是否是一个现实的场景,可以更详细地讨论,就像与之相关的规范性问题一样,但根据我最初提出的批评策略,我将把自己限制在这个快速的阐述中,然后继续讨论第二个更详细的改革提议,即哈耶克的“模范宪法”(哈耶克,2003,第105-127页)。哈耶克建议的主要内容是恢复政府和立法机构之间严格的权力分离。他的诊断对两者的合并提出了问题,因此,真正的两院制必须重新建立,立法机关只通过适当意义上的法律,限制政府享有的自由裁量行动的空间。在这种制度设计实践的许多值得注意的方面中,我将只强调一个特别有趣的方面,它也引起了相当多的批评:在许多方面,管理大会在其主要特征上与经验上存在的政府几乎没有什么不同,尽管哈耶克在政府选举中认真地考虑剥夺任何从国家获得转移或工资的人的公民权(哈耶克,2003年,第120页)。尽管如此,批评的主要目标是立法机关的选举规则,这可以说是在这个新的制度设置中真正的权力所在地,因为政府议会将严格“受立法议会制定的公正行为规则的约束”(哈耶克,2003,第119页)。立法机关的议员按下列方式选举:每年,全体年满45岁的公民在其人口群体中选出自己的代表,以代替任期满15年的即将离任的立法委员。哈耶克所记住是“一个组装在一个相对成熟的年龄的男性和女性当选相当长的时间,如十五年,所以他们不会re-eligible也被迫回到谋生的市场,但保证持续公共就业等敬语但中立的立场躺法官,这期间担任议员他们会依赖政党支持和关心他们的个人的未来”(哈耶克2003,p . 113)。这种设计背后的基本原理非常清楚。长期任期、不能连任和保证未来就业,都是为了尽量减少代表立法者从事寻租行为的动机,此外,据称年龄群体的结构原则将排除在立法机构内形成政党关系。即使他们形成了,“那些倾向于不同党派的人将被诱导一起讨论问题,并将意识到他们有代表他们这一代人的观点的共同任务……”(哈耶克,2003年,第118页)。显然,从民主理论的角度来看,这一激进的提议会受到许多批评,但让我们把它放在一边,转而考虑这里要考虑的最后一个提议,这也是最不具体的,它呼吁将国家地位转变为其主要支持者亚历山大·<s:1>斯托(Alexander rstow)和沃尔特·欧肯(Walter Eucken)所说的“强国家”。这种补救措施体现了对过度多元化的批判性诊断的严格结论,这种诊断在大多数世界自由主义者中普遍存在;甚至在这个主题上较少发声的Röpke也提醒他的读者,“这种不健康的多元主义的巨大危险是压力集团贪婪地包围国家”,“任何负责任的政府都必须仔细检查所有可能的手段,以抵制这种多元化的国家解体”(Röpke, 1960, pp. 144, 143)。尽管如此,最强烈的要求强大国家的呼声还是来自他的自由主义同胞<s:1>斯托夫和欧肯。前者在1932年的演讲《国家政策与经济自由主义的必要条件》中总结道:“我和我的朋友们所提倡的新自由主义要求一个强大的国家,一个凌驾于经济之上、凌驾于利益团体之上、在其所属之地的国家。以这种对促进自由主义经济政策的强大国家的信仰忏悔和-因为两者相互制约-促进强大国家的自由主义经济政策,我想以这种忏悔结束”(r<e:1>斯托,2017b,第149页)。因此,国家要把自己从政党和利益集团的多元仇恨中解脱出来,并采取一种立场,使它能够抵御来自这些行动者的要求。同年,欧肯出版了《国家的结构转型与资本主义的危机》,这本书后来被认为是世界自由主义传统的奠基之作。 对于这样一个提议的影响,这是否是一个现实的场景,可以更详细地讨论,就像与之相关的规范性问题一样,但根据我最初提出的批评策略,我将把自己限制在这个快速的阐述中,然后继续讨论第二个更详细的改革提议,即哈耶克的“模范宪法”(哈耶克,2003,第105-127页)。哈耶克建议的主要内容是恢复政府和立法机构之间严格的权力分离。他的诊断对两者的合并提出了问题,因此,真正的两院制必须重新建立,立法机关只通过适当意义上的法律,限制政府享有的自由裁量行动的空间。在这种制度设计实践的许多值得注意的方面中,我将只强调一个特别有趣的方面,它也引起了相当多的批评:在许多方面,管理大会在其主要特征上与经验上存在的政府几乎没有什么不同,尽管哈耶克在政府选举中认真地考虑剥夺任何从国家获得转移或工资的人的公民权(哈耶克,2003年,第120页)。尽管如此,批评的主要目标是立法机关的选举规则,这可以说是在这个新的制度设置中真正的权力所在地,因为政府议会将严格“受立法议会制定的公正行为规则的约束”(哈耶克,2003,第119页)。立法机关的议员按下列方式选举:每年,全体年满45岁的公民在其人口群体中选出自己的代表,以代替任期满15年的即将离任的立法委员。哈耶克所记住的是“一个组装在一个相对成熟的年龄的男性和女性当选相当长的时间,如十五年,所以他们不会re-eligible也被迫回到谋生的市场,但保证持续公共就业等敬语但中立的立场躺法官,这期间担任议员他们会依赖政党支持和关心他们的个人的未来”(哈耶克2003,p . 113)。这种设计背后的基本原理非常清楚。长期任期、不能连任和保证未来就业,都是为了尽量减少代表立法者从事寻租行为的动机,此外,据称年龄群体的结构原则将排除在立法机构内形成政党关系。即使他们形成了,“那些倾向于不同党派的人将被诱导一起讨论问题,并将意识到他们有代表他们这一代人的观点的共同任务……”(哈耶克,2003年,第118页)。显然,从民主理论的角度来看,这一激进的提议会受到许多批评,但让我们把它放在一边,转而考虑这里要考虑的最后一个提议,这也是最不具体的,它呼吁将国家地位转变为其主要支持者亚历山大·<s:1>斯托(Alexander rstow)和沃尔特·欧肯(Walter Eucken)所说的“强国家”。这种补救措施体现了对过度多元化的批判性诊断的严格结论,这种诊断在大多数世界自由主义者中普遍存在;甚至在这个主题上较少发声的Röpke也提醒他的读者,“这种不健康的多元主义的巨大危险是压力集团贪婪地包围国家”,“任何负责任的政府都必须仔细检查所有可能的手段,以抵制这种多元化的国家解体”(Röpke, 1960, pp. 144, 143)。尽管如此,最强烈的要求强大国家的呼声还是来自他的自由主义同胞<s:1>斯托夫和欧肯。前者在1932年的演讲《国家政策与经济自由主义的必要条件》中总结道:“我和我的朋友们所提倡的新自由主义要求一个强大的国家,一个凌驾于经济之上、凌驾于利益团体之上、在其所属之地的国家。以这种对促进自由主义经济政策的强大国家的信仰忏悔和-因为两者相互制约-促进强大国家的自由主义经济政策,我想以这种忏悔结束”(r<e:1>斯托,2017b,第149页)。因此,国家要把自己从政党和利益集团的多元仇恨中解脱出来,并采取一种立场,使它能够抵御来自这些行动者的要求。同年,欧肯出版了《国家的结构转型与资本主义的危机》,这本书后来被认为是世界自由主义传统的奠基之作。 在这篇内容广泛的文章中,Eucken提出了他自己版本的自由主义衰落叙事,在他看来,这恰好与卡尔·施密特(Carl Schmitt)在这方面的观点相吻合,并在“自由国家向经济国家的转变”中脱颖而出(Eucken, 2017,第59页)。在欧肯看来,经济国家中国家、社会和经济的融合是最严重的后果,因为它“破坏了国家的独立决策,而这正是国家存在所依赖的。”最近所有的经济政策都清楚地表明了这一有害的过程:它相当于过度的自我 在这篇内容广泛的文章中,Eucken提出了他自己版本的自由主义衰落叙事,在他看来,这恰好与卡尔·施密特(Carl Schmitt)在这方面的观点相吻合,并在“自由国家向经济国家的转变”中脱颖而出(Eucken, 2017,第59页)。在欧肯看来,经济国家中国家、社会和经济的融合是最严重的后果,因为它“破坏了国家的独立决策,而这正是国家存在所依赖的。”……所有最近的经济政策都清楚地表明了这一腐蚀过程:它相当于过多的措施,每一项措施都可以追溯到不同强大的经济集团的愿望,但这些措施加在一起,没有连贯性,完全缺乏系统”(Eucken, 2017, pp. 59-60)。简而言之,国家“缺乏真正独立的权力来做出自己的决定”(第60页)。与r<s:1>斯托相似,欧肯因此要求国家克服其即将到来的多元化解体,而是将自己从特殊行为者的控制中解脱出来,以恢复自己的统一和独立的意志形成,从而成为真正的“竞争秩序的守护者”(欧肯,1960,第327页),并强制执行它,甚至反对强大的经济行为者。这将如何反映(多元)民主制度,以及它将在多大程度上作为这一行动的附带损害而衰落,如果不是它的实际目标,欧几肯没有解决,但这种遗漏本身可能被认为是相当说明问题的。这三个建议包含了相当有争议的成分,但是,如前所述,我在这里概述它们并不是为了批判性地仔细审查它们,而是为了表明,新自由主义者总是用相当雄心勃勃的改革建议来回应民主的诊断问题。无一例外,他们都认为务实的混日子已经过去,必须采取果断的变革行动。这里所设想的,即使是在宪法平衡预算修正案的最具体和不那么深远的要求中,也不仅仅是一种边际政策调整,而是相当于霍尔在他的经典讨论中所说的二阶甚至三阶/范式变化——哈耶克和自由主义的更广泛的建议当然是后者(见霍尔,1993)。考虑到所设想的大规模和相当激烈的变革,似乎更重要的是要考虑到实现这些变革的方式,以及谁是可以被合理地认为是在追求这些战略的行动者,简而言之,就是变革的问题。但事实证明,对于这里讨论的所有新自由主义者来说,这不仅仅是一个小挑战。本节将展示的是,新自由主义者在理论化新自由主义转型的政治方面总是失败的,尽管是以不同的和有益的方式。正如前一节所建立的,新自由主义改革不是被设计为渐进的调整过程,而是需要与现状进行决定性的决裂——鉴于当代民主社会的诊断所描绘的黯淡图景,这只是结果。但是,应该如何实现变革,谁将引领这一划时代的变革进程?让我们从欧肯开始,他在这些问题上的立场可以说是这里考虑的新自由主义者中最弱的,因为他对潜在改革策略的描述相当于缺乏这样的描述。在他战后的一些著作中,特别是在他死后出版的《经济政策原则》中,尤肯确实把执行竞争秩序的潜在行为者确定为一个更广泛的、连锁的社会秩序结构的关键方面。因此,国家、教会和科学被定性为“有秩序的潜能”(Eucken, 1960, p. 325),但它们各自的潜能处于休眠状态,因此,Eucken对这三种潜能的阐述在很大程度上是在哀叹它们各自无法实现这种潜能。换句话说,对于国家如何摆脱利益集团和政党对其的影响,或者如何恢复教会和科学的权威和影响力,欧肯感到困惑。特别是就国家而言,这是一项艰巨的任务,因为真正的世界自由主义经济政策以国家的自治为前提,而国家的自治被认为是可以实现的,因此欧肯发现自己处于一个逻辑循环中:“没有竞争秩序,就不会出现能够采取行动的国家,反过来,没有能够采取行动的国家,就不会出现竞争秩序”(欧肯,1960,第338页)。 虽然在欧肯的案例中,新自由主义策略的问题没有得到进一步的探讨,但Röpke解决了能够实现他对一个分散和非分类社会的特殊的自由主义愿景的行动者的问题。“重要的是,每个社会都应该有一小群有影响力的领导人,他们觉得自己是整个社会不可侵犯的规范和价值观的守护者,并严格履行这种守护者的职责,这种信念正在逐渐得到认可。我们需要的是真正的自然贵族”(Röpke, 1960,第130页)。我们不需要深入研究Röpke对一个善良的文员阶级的赞美,这个文员阶级仁慈地守护着政治共同体,它借鉴了柏拉图的守护阶级的概念,以及古典保守的自然(化)社会等级的概念。在我们的背景下,值得注意的是Röpke引入自然贵族的已经非常悲观的框架。显然,如果这样一个自然贵族要发展和维持下去,如果它要完成它的任务,就必须满足和忍受许多条件,有时是困难的条件。它必须成长和成熟,它成熟的缓慢与它可能毁灭的迅速相匹配”(Röpke, 1960, p. 131)。因此,一旦引入Röpke改革议程的参与者,他们几乎又消失了,因为事实证明,他们的存在是极其短暂的,依赖于一个相当不可能的因素和条件的组合,所有这些都很容易蒸发,随之而来的是珍视的“公共精神的贵族”(第131页)。可以肯定的是,考虑到Röpke对这些“职员”的冗长描述,这不仅仅是花言巧语。要想成为社会的守护者,除了其他条件之外,还需要“为所有人奉献努力的生活,无可指责的正直,对我们共同的贪婪的不断克制,被证明是正确的判断,一尘不染的私人生活,为真理和法律挺身而出的不屈不挠的勇气,通常是最高的榜样”(Röpke, 1960, pp. 130-131)。考虑到这种苛刻的形象,这样一个守护阶级的出现和持续存在被认为极不可能就不足为奇了。毕竟,似乎只有具有超凡脱俗性质的演员才能满足Röpke的标准,所以他才会把他们称为“世俗化的圣徒”,并且考虑到这些事情在Röpke的叙述中被转移到宗教习语中,将其称为典型的“上帝的机器”动机似乎是合适的,这揭示了Röpke思想中的空白。关于<s:1> stow,我们已经知道,拟议的补救措施是将当前的弱状态转变为强状态。但是,如何绕过利益相关方的根深蒂固的网络,这些利益相关方有能力煽动群众采取行动,反对任何威胁到他们进入金钱和权力渠道的改革努力?在早期1929年的一次演讲中,r<e:1>斯托设想了一条通往非多元化政治的道路,这种政治可以被称为过渡时期的独裁统治。毕竟,讲座的题目是《民主范围内的独裁》(r<e:1>斯托,1959,[1929])。根据他的提议,由总理领导的政府将被授予一段时间的统治权,即使它没有议会多数。暂停被迫辞职或法案和措施在议会投票中被否决的可能性,是为了让政府有回旋余地,去追求毫无疑问是<s:1>斯托夫想象中的那种政治,Röpke的公共精神贵族会制定这种政治。一旦规定的时间结束,议会权力和监督的暂停就会停止,政府必须面临各自的审查,并有可能再次被选举下台。“这意味着维护民主,因为这是一个有时间限制的独裁,不是严格意义上的独裁,而是一个有试用期的独裁”(r<e:1>斯托,1959,第99页)。不出所料,在哈耶克的例子中,事情要复杂得多,但他的观点的主旨是足够清楚的。在《法律、立法和自由》一书中,他已经讨论了紧急权力作为在危机中和/或极权主义集体主义边缘确保政治共同体长期稳定的潜在必要条件(哈耶克,2003,III,第124页)。系统地说,这个论点位于哈耶克思想中的一个神经痛点,因为就像其他新自由主义者的情况一样,他面临着在一个世界中阐明一条通向更自由主义社会的合理道路的任务,根据他自己的分析,这个世界已经开始走下坡路(不)著名的农奴制之路。 紧急权力和临时独裁形式的例外状态代表了连接现状与哈耶克新自由主义愿景的理论桥梁。在1981年接受El Mercurio采访时,哈耶克对奥古斯托•皮诺切特(Augusto Pinochet)政变后的智利发表了臭名昭著的评论。他一如既往地直言不讳:“作为长期机构,我完全反对独裁统治。但是,在过渡时期,独裁可能是必要的制度。有时,一个国家有必要在一段时间内拥有某种独裁权力。正如你所理解的,独裁者有可能以自由的方式执政。…我个人的印象…是在智利…我们将见证从独裁政府到自由政府的过渡…”(El Mercurio, 1981, p. D9)。到20世纪80年代初,哈耶克显然已经说服自己,过渡时期的独裁统治是拯救政治共同体免于屈服于极权主义和集体主义的合法选择,正如我们从前面部分的引用中知道的那样,哈耶克也确信,这不仅仅是智利或其他“不发达”国家的问题,而是滑向极权主义的趋势,实际上是当代民主固有的。我们如何看待这些建议?​然而,正如他自己所指出的,“我不是一个足够的乌托邦主义者,不会认为我刚刚概述的提议通常会在今天的国会中找到多数人来修改宪法。”如果我们有一个可以想象的国会,那么这个命题就没有必要了”(r<e:1>斯托,1959,第100页)。考虑到这种“第22条军规”(Catch 22),它与欧肯(Eucken)各自的问题相似,赖斯托必须要么埋葬他对游走在民主与独裁之间的真正变革政治的希望,要么他必须放弃他残余的民主情感,选择毫无意义的独裁政治。赖斯托和哈耶克都面临着另一个更普遍的问题,他们在很大程度上没有解决,即,假设过渡时期的独裁统治仍然是过渡时期的,这是否现实。可以肯定的是,历史上有这样的例子,独裁者或拥有事实上的独裁权力的民主领导人安静地、忠实地靠边站,从而使社会恢复到正常状态,但哈耶克自己在《通往农奴制之路》中提出的滑坡论点是基于这样一种观点,即不受约束的权力往往会变得根深蒂固,并产生一种倾向于极权主义的动力。正如哈耶克当时所主张的那样,全面规划所需的充分权力,甚至会把最善意的社会主义者拖入极权主义的致命政治。为什么这些机制不适用于过渡时期的独裁政权,这些独裁政权不寻求为社会主义铺平道路,而是寻求自由威权主义?哈耶克的防线可能是诉诸《通往农奴制之路》中的一个观点,根据这个观点,这种动力只由经济干预主义而不是政治干预引发,也就是说,如果自由专制主义放弃经济干预,它可能会阻止任何潜在的极权主义动力,但这种区分是否令人信服是相当有争议的。尽管哈耶克至少有一个论点,尽管是一个薄弱的论点,但它仍然是一个真正的谜,为什么<s:1>斯托从来没有明确地关注过这个难题;尤其如此,因为他和哈耶克都敏锐地意识到了卡尔·施密特的工作。在他关于例外状态的著作中,一个重要且并非完全不合理的观点是,自由主义者的野心是通过编纂规则来控制例外状态的模式和由此产生的紧急权力,从而遏制例外状态变化无常的本质,最终是徒劳的。因此,如果r<s:1>斯托的希望是,他的过渡性独裁政权将继续保持过渡性,因为它被写入了宪法——如果曾经有过多数人支持它——这几乎是naïve从施密特的观点来看。因此,我们看到,在这两种情况下,提出的改革战略或多或少与各自观点背后的明确假设不相容。我们的最后一个案例是James Buchanan的作品,他也是最吸引人的例子,因为虽然r<s:1>斯托和Eucken大多试图避免战略和执行的问题,但他却一次又一次地直接解决这个问题。布坎南的具体挑战与我们已经讨论过的困扰新自由主义者的问题并没有完全不同。它可以用一个简单的问题的形式非常简洁地陈述,但事实证明,这个问题仍然具有相当毁灭性的含义。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
The revolution will not be theorized: Neoliberal thought and the problem of transition

Neoliberalism is a notoriously contested term, and even among those who principally subscribe to it, which is mostly its critics, fierce debates persist over its nature, how to study it properly—and whether it is still the appropriate conceptual armament to understand the contemporary world and an arguably emerging “post-neoliberalism” (Davies & Gane, 2021). Not only is it controversial how neoliberalism should be defined—a governing rationality in the spirit of Foucault's governmentality lectures (Foucault, 2008), a portfolio of certain policies, or a strategy of transnational capital to restore and safeguard profit rates (Harvey, 2005)—but also on what level to study it, either that of “actually existing neoliberalism” (Brenner & Theodore, 2002; Cahill, 2014), a set of theories and arguments, or both.

My starting point and focus for most of this paper is neoliberal thought as it is represented by the writings of Friedrich Hayek, Milton Friedman, the German ordoliberals, and, importantly, James Buchanan. My aim is to develop a critical account of neoliberal thought that will abstain from explicitly normative criticisms and rather opt for a more indirect but effective and somewhat novel critique that holds neoliberalism to its own standards and shows how it fails to meet them or is pushed into adopting highly questionable positions in the attempt to do so. The argument proceeds as follows: As already suggested, the meaning of neoliberalism is heavily contested, so I will provide the basis of my argument by laying out a brief account of neoliberalism, which relies on a theoretical-historical reconstruction of its context of emergence around the middle of the 20th century. What I conclude from this reconstruction is that we are well-advised not to narrow down neoliberalism too much and not to downplay its internal heterogeneities. Therefore, rather than trying to isolate a number of doctrines or positions as quintessentially neoliberal or even considering them to be the “essence” of neoliberalism, I argue that what unites neoliberal discourse is not a set of positive convictions—although there is some significant overlap in certain areas—but rather a shared problematic that pertains to the preconditions of functioning markets.

Within that overall problematic, democracy is one of the most pressing problems according to neoliberal thinkers, because virtually all of them agree that it complicates the task of setting up and securing the workings of functioning markets significantly. Still, this basic agreement notwithstanding, neoliberal accounts of democracy display a considerable range of specific diagnoses as to the nature and source of its dysfunctionalities or even pathologies. Accordingly, the second step of the argument is a survey of some selected lines of critique of democracy as they are formulated by leading neoliberals. Among other things, this survey helps us appreciate the heterogeneities of neoliberal thought, but, more importantly for my purposes, it also gives us a sense of the deep reservations neoliberals have with regard to democracy and the trenchant nature of their critique.

As the specific critiques of democracy vary among neoliberals, so do the suggested remedies and reforms put forward. Accordingly, in the next step, several selected reform proposals are scrutinized that range from the vague call for a “strong state” to Hayek's “model constitution” and the much more specific argument for the introduction of a constitutional balanced-budget amendment, which is a signature demand of Buchanan. What this survey shows us, among other things, is the radical nature of the neoliberal reform proposals, which is important to my overall argument.

Despite the highly controversial implications of all of these reform proposals, I will deliberately forego engaging them directly based on normative arguments. Instead, my critique focuses on the missing analytical link between neoliberal diagnostics and respective remedies. In order to show this, the fourth and final part of the argument shifts attention to the politics of neoliberal transformation, that is, whether and how this kind of politics is theorized in neoliberal accounts. Again, there is a certain degree of variance between Hayek, Eucken and Buchanan, but the common denominator here is the inability to theorize such a politics without violating the respective assumptions underlying the critical diagnostics or moving beyond the confines of liberal democracy as a condition of implementing such reforms. Thus, the key thesis I wish to defend in the following contends that neoliberal thought lacks any plausible solution to the so-called problem of transition—if they care to reflect on it at all.1

These findings lead to several different interpretations with more or less far-reaching implications that are discussed in the concluding section.

It is commonplace nowadays to note the contested nature and potential vacuity of the term neoliberalism. Faced with these allegations, scholars of neoliberalism often hasten to offer some kind of working definition of neoliberalism, lest they lend credence to suspicions that they are operating with an empty signifier carrying political rather than analytical meaning. Accordingly, a set of policies—typically centered around the agenda of the Washington Consensus—is identified as quintessentially neoliberal, certain ideas or principles are considered to make up its core or essence or, neoliberal is simply that, which members of the Mont Pèlerin Society promulgate, which is an elegant but, upon closer inspection, not entirely convincing way to circumvent the problem (Chomsky, 1999; Crouch, 2011; Mirowski & Plehwe, 2009). On the other hand, there are regular interventions by scholars who emphasize the enormous variability/transformability of neoliberalism and its characteristic ability to form more or less tension-laden amalgamations with other political-intellectual projects, which makes it seemingly impossible, or at least intellectually imprudent, to aim for some hard and fast definition that “fixes” neoliberalism and its meaning(s): “Crisply unambiguous, essentialist definitions of neoliberalism have proved to be incredibly elusive” (Peck, 2010, p. 8).

My own account of neoliberalism will try to strike a balance between overly parsimonious definitional attempts that do not hold up under closer scrutiny and the analytically defeatist solution to dissolve neoliberalism into various neoliberalisms that allegedly share nothing but Wittgensteinian family resemblances. The starting point of my conceptual approach is the observation that neoliberalism has become a truly toxic label these days, and it might therefore be useful to begin with a look at those who did describe themselves, albeit fleetingly and reluctantly, as neoliberals at the time and clarify the intellectual and political agenda that they attached the label “neoliberal” to. In other words, it is necessary to reconstruct the intellectual and political context of neoliberalism's emergence.

Processes of emergence do not have a single origin but are dispersed, and the same goes for neoliberalism. Nevertheless, it is possible to identify the Colloque Walter Lippmann as the “birth” of neoliberalism in the sense of the first culmination point of these processes and the event at which, for the first time, the term was officially adopted, denoting a shared agenda of the participants, which included not just Hayek, Wilhelm Röpke, and Alexander Rüstow but also Jacques Rueff, Louis Rougier (the convener of the meeting) and, of course, Walter Lippmann himself. At this point, an impressive scholarship on the Colloque exists, so there is no need to go into the details of the proceedings (see instead Burgin, 2012; Dardot & Laval, 2013; Innset, 2020; Reinhoudt & Audier, 2018). The overall picture that emerges from them is a liberalism on the defensive that seeks to regain the status of a real contender against its main antagonists, collectivism and—to a lesser degree back then—Keynesianism. In the eyes of practically all of the participants except for Ludwig von Mises, this endeavor presupposed a critical revision of the classical liberal agenda, and, most notably, abandoning simplistic formulas such as “laissez-faire,” or, what some referred to as “Manchesterism.”2 The neoliberal discourse in formation here was, thus, a far cry from the creed of “self-regulating markets.” Instead, the entire point of the neoliberal approach is to affirm the value of markets against collectivists and Keynesians while insisting that they are not nearly as robust and self-sustaining as large parts of the liberal tradition were inclined to believe up to that point. To put it more pointedly, the market per se was not the solution to all problems; rather, the market itself turned into a problem for neoliberal thought as it was seen as an entity in need of constant care and premised upon a number of preconditions. Therefore, what I call the neoliberal problematic pertains to the preconditions of functioning markets, that is, markets on which the price mechanism reigns as unperturbed as possible.3

The irreducible heterogeneities that characterize neoliberal discourse are not the least due to the manifold and at times contradictory ways in which this problematic can be, and has been, spelled out and addressed. Still, what becomes clear is that neoliberal thought might be centered around the notion of markets, but the intellectual energies of those whose work is animated by this problematic, such as Buchanan, Hayek, or the German ordoliberals, inevitably gravitate toward the infrastructure that needs to be put in place and defended against changing adversaries for these markets to function. This is the realm of the social and the political, and therefore it is only stringent for the neoliberals to invest so much time into conceptualizing the state—and democracy.

When neoliberals talk about democracy, they typically refer to democracy in its existing form, that is, their discourse rarely ventures into philosophical inquiries into the nature and theory of democracy. The predominant form their discourse takes is that of a critique of the respective contemporary forms of representative democracy.

These respective contexts leave an imprint on the various accounts of democracy, but rather than probing the details of each, in this survey, I will highlight what I consider to be three types of arguments or varieties of the neoliberal critique of democracy that can be analytically distinguished.4

The first set of arguments against democracy considered here is particularly prominent in ordoliberal discourse but not exclusive to it:5 For Wilhelm Röpke and Walter Eucken, the main threat associated with democracy is due to the influence of a new phenomenon on the political scene, namely, the masses. With the rise of mass democracy, the latter have acquired a heretofore unknown leverage over political decisions, or at least this is the assumption under which the ordoliberals in particular are operating. Hence, the problem is not the existence of masses per se but rather their integration into the political process through mass democratic institutions as it unfolds unevenly but steadily over the course of the first half of the 20th century. While the aversion against the masses may seem no more than a variant on the venerable liberal-conservative topos of the tyranny of the majority, there is more to it. The masses are more than a majority. In a discourse crucially shaped by Gustave Le Bon's Crowds, Sigmund Freud's Group Psychology and the Analysis of the Ego, and Jose Ortega Y. Gasset's Revolt of the Masses (who was invited to the Colloque but did not participate), the concept of the masses is psychologically (and at times racially) charged. Masses are attributed with infantilism and general irrationality, which makes them the perfect molding material for demagogues who exploit their uncritical receptiveness and malleability to mobilize them for political projects—typically ones that involve state planning and collectivization from the perspective of the ordoliberals. There is ample textual evidence for this stance, so a few examples may suffice here as the basis of this interpretation. Eucken notes: “But while people can only live in certain orders, the mass tends towards destroying these exact orders” (Eucken, 1960, p. 14), and in one of the classic texts inaugurating the ordoliberal tradition from 1932, he laments “that the simultaneous process of democratisation lent the parties, and the masses and interest groups that they organised, much greater influence over the management of the state, and so upon economic policy” (Eucken, 2017, [1932], p. 59). Röpke complements these views: “In all countries, in some less, in others more, society has been ground into a mass of individuals, who have never been so closely herded together and so dependent on each other and yet at the same time they are more rootless, more isolated and more like grains of sand than ever before … All the misery, all the problems of our time have their ultimate roots here…” (Röpke, 1950, [1942], p. 92). Elsewhere, he draws on the above-mentioned social psychological framing of the masses: “As a part of ‘mass’, we are different from what we normally are and should be in healthy circumstances; we are subhuman, herdlike, and the state of society dangerously corresponds to our own” (Röpke, 1960, p. 53). And while the most extreme manifestations of what might be called the mass syndrome only occur in what Röpke terms mass in the “acute state,” massification as a permanent condition is hardly less alarming, since it heralds the reign of mediocre brutes at the expense of the “unalterable aristocracy of nature” Röpke hopes to defend (Röpke, 1960, p. 55). To sum up this line of criticism, economic policy is simply too important and much too intricate to leave it to the wayward masses, who may not sit in parliaments and run governments in representative democracies, but are still too influential under the conditions of mass democracy, even if only as the object of demagogic agitation and mobilization. If the alliance of these forces had their way, democracy is bound to transform into collectivism, that is, the prime adversary of neoliberal thought: “There is no denying it: the collectivist state is rooted in the masses” (Röpke, 1950, p. 86).

The second line of criticism also owes its classic formulation to another ordoliberal, namely, Alexander Rüstow. The target of this criticism, in addition to the mass dimension of contemporary democracy, is its alleged excessive “pluralism.” Rüstow succinctly sums up the respective core concern: “The democratic, parliamentary structure of some of the economically leading states caused the economic corruption to spread to the internal policy of the state, to the political parties, and to the [sic!] parliamentarism itself. The political parties were slowly transformed into parliamentary agencies of economic pressure groups and were financed by them. … The pathological form of government which developed this way was that of pluralism…” (Rüstow, 2017a, [1942], p. 159). Under conditions of mass democracy, (economic) pressure groups will gain such extraordinary influence that they can almost dictate their will to political parties; the result is marginalization of a vaguely defined common good, which is dissolved into what Eucken calls in no uncertain terms “group anarchy” (Eucken, 1960, p. 171). The state, as the presumptive guardian of this common good, is undermined in this process of economic-political clientelism, and Rüstow echoes the scathing criticism of pluralism by Carl Schmitt in his conclusion: “What takes place here accords with the motto: ‘The state as prey’” (Rüstow, 2017b, [1932], p. 147). Under conditions of unchecked pluralism, the state is weakened continuously and the resulting centrifugal dynamics ultimately become unmanageable as the political community falls apart at the hands of particularistic actors emerging from every corner of society.

Thirdly, there is a strictly contemporary line of criticism that still exhibits some correspondence to the critique of pluralism just sketched. The central theorem underlying this critique is that of rent-seeking, which describes a behavior that seeks to gain some kind of advantage over others not through productive action and competition but rather by lobbying for some kind of special treatment, typically an exemption from certain rules. This idea builds on the insights of game theory and rational choice approaches, according to which individual utility is often maximized when (generally beneficial) rules apply to all but the individual in question, and much of the public choice critique of democracy is built around this basal notion: Under conditions of democracy, the constant demand for special treatment of societal/economic actors is met by an eager supplier in the form of political actors hoping thus to increase their chances of reelection. As one of the cofounders of the public choice tradition, it is a matter of course, that Buchanan puts the rent-seeking theorem at the center of his critique of representative democracy and he is not the only neoliberal who does so: Milton Friedman as well as the later Hayek would occasionally, albeit not systematically, draw on the basic logic of rent-seeking (see Friedman & Friedman, 1984). The fundamental problem that allegedly ensues from rent-seeking can be summed up in the following way: Assuming that everybody else engages in rent-seeking, individual rationality dictates that one does so as well because, otherwise, one would be indirectly disadvantaged to the degree that others gain exemptions from rules that still apply to oneself. This means that rent-seeking has an inherently expansive dynamic, and as a general practice, it backfires against the intent of its subjects because even if individual rent-seeking may be successful and provides an advantage, this is vastly outweighed by the multiple disadvantages one has to suffer due to all other rent-seeking activities, assuming they are successful as well. Thus, in pursuit of their individual utility, the actors in a society end up putting themselves at a disadvantage. Just as in the pluralist scenario, it is particularism that prevails here, albeit with a tragic twist. But not only does the “rent-seeking society” (Buchanan et al., 1980) harm its current members: Exemptions and other special treatments typically come with some kind of price tag, and since financing through raising taxes is not a realistic option under public choice assumptions, and lawmakers, as well as government, have less and less control over inflation, the prime strategy to pay for rents is through deficits and debt—burdening the almost proverbial “future generations” with financial obligations that they had no say in—arguably a clear violation of the democratic principle of autonomy.

Finally, there is a line of critique that focuses on the decline of the rule of law in relation to democracy and problematizes the alleged unlimited nature of the latter. The prime exemplar of this line of argument is Friedrich August Hayek, who laid out the various aspects in numerous writings. To be sure, Hayek conceded that democracy, in principle, had its merits: “[I]t is the only convention we have yet discovered to make peaceful change possible” (Hayek, 2003, III, p. 137) However, the ideal of democracy and its basic thrust of limiting power became disfigured over time. The Constitution of Liberty already contains the central point of Hayek's critique in a nutshell: “The crucial conception of the doctrinaire democrat is that of popular sovereignty. This means to him that Majority rule is unlimited and unlimitable. The ideal of democracy, originally intended to prevent all arbitrary power, thus becomes the justification for a new arbitrary power” (Hayek, 2006, p. 93) The deeper reason for this, according to Hayek, is the erosion of the principle of the rule of law, which he chronicles in the Constitution of Liberty and that involves, prominently, the shedding of any formal prerequisites of what constitutes a genuine law. While in the heyday of liberalism, only those legal rules that were abstract, general, and directed at future behavior were considered to be law in the proper sense of the term, nowadays, Hayek claims, whatever emerges from a legislature is deemed to have the power of law, thus empowering parliaments to engage in the kind of discretionary planning activities that he considers to be harmful on any number of levels. And since there are no longer any formal restrictions on this unrestrained democracy, politicians have no instruments at their disposal to fend off the demands from societal interest groups. “The root of the trouble is, of course, to sum up, that in an unlimited democracy the holders of discretionary powers are forced to use them, whether they wish it or not, to favour particular groups on whose swing vote their powers depend” (Hayek, 2003, III, p. 139), concludes Hayek, thus echoing in this regard the second and third lines of critique sketched out above. The main thrust of Hayek's argument, though, is a combination of the critique of democracy as majority rule—spelled out most prominently in The Constitution of Liberty (see Hayek, 2006, pp. 90–102)—and the contention that this majority rule is no longer restrained in any meaningful way, thus giving rise to an almost dystopian “unlimited democracy,” which, Hayek thought, would ultimately lead toward totalitarianism: “[T]he whole work [Law, Legislation and Liberty] has been inspired by a growing apprehension about the direction in which the political order of what used to be regarded as the most advanced countries is tending. The growing conviction … that this threatening development towards a totalitarian state is made inevitable by certain deeply entrenched defects of construction of the generally accepted type of ‘democratic’ government has forced me to think through various alternative arrangements” (Hayek, 2003, I, p. xx).

It is to these alternative arrangements in the works of the various neoliberals accounts discussed here that we now turn to.

It would exceed the scope of this paper to survey every reform proposal submitted by leading neoliberals, so I will merely focus on three more or less specific reform visions being put forward by Buchanan, Hayek as well as the ordoliberals Rüstow and Eucken, respectively, which are to deal with the various shortcomings or pathologies of democracy as they are pinpointed in the diagnoses sketched out in the preceding section.

Let us begin with what arguably is the most specific proposal to be found in the neoliberal reform portfolio and which came to be a signature demand raised by James Buchanan, although a slightly different version has also been promoted by Milton Friedman. The proposal seeks to address the proclivity to engage in rent-seeking behavior or rather to grant rents to interest groups on behalf of elected officials in order to improve chances at reelection. Buchanan became ever more pessimistic in his assessment of (American) democracy over the years, eventually claiming that “the appeal to the experience of history, and not least to recent events in the United States, does suggest that government, in its current institutional setting, is close to being out of the control of the electorate” (Brennan & Buchanan, 1980, p. 25). In order to come to terms with this deteriorating situation, one of Buchanan's prime suggestions is to pursue the strategy of reining in democratic excesses through tighter controls of the way public expenditures are financed. What democracy requires is a rule that precludes the debt/deficit financing of these outlays, and it should preferably be instituted on the highest possible legal level: a constitutional balanced-budget amendment (Buchanan, 1997). The amendment would stipulate rather that all current state expenditures must be financed through actual revenue, be it taxation or otherwise; it would be simply unconstitutional to accrue deficits and debt to finance state expenditures. Given such restrictions, politicians are expected to restrain runaway spending and curtail public expenditure, instead of attempting to rely on a low tax strategy to succeed at the polls. Whether this is a realistic scenario for the impact of such a proposal could be discussed in much greater detail as could be the normative questions related to it, but following the strategy of my critique laid out initially, I will confine myself to this quick exposition and move on to the second and much more elaborate reform proposal, which is Hayek's “model constitution” (Hayek, 2003, pp. 105–127).

The major thrust of Hayek's proposal is a restoration of a strict separation of powers between government and legislature. His diagnosis problematizes the conflation of both, and therefore real bicameralism has to be reinstituted where legislatures only pass laws in the proper sense of the term that circumscribe the room for discretionary action the government enjoys. Of the many noteworthy aspects of this exercise in institutional design, I will only highlight one particularly intriguing aspect that has also drawn considerable criticism: In many respects, the governing assembly hardly differs in its main characteristics from empirically existing governments, although Hayek is seriously entertaining the disenfranchisement of anybody who receives transfers or salaries from the state in governmental elections (Hayek, 2003, p. 120). Still, the major target of criticism is the election rules for the legislature, which is arguably the real locus of power in this new institutional set-up as the governmental assembly is to be strictly “bound by the rules of just conduct laid down by the Legislative Assembly” (Hayek, 2003, p. 119). Members of the legislature are to be elected in the following way: Each year all citizens of the age of 45 choose their representatives out of the midst of their demographic cohort to replace the contingent of outgoing legislators at the end of their 15-year term. What Hayek has in mind is “an assembly of men and women elected at a relatively mature age for fairly long periods, such as fifteen years, so they would not be re-eligible nor forced to return to earning a living in the market but be assured of continued public employment in such honorific but neutral positions as lay judges, so that during their tenure as legislators they would be neither dependent on party support nor concerned about their personal future” (Hayek, 2003, p. 113). The rationale behind this design is clear enough. The long tenure, ineligibility to be reelected, and guaranteed future employment seek to minimize the incentive to engage in rent-seeking behavior on behalf of legislators and, furthermore, the structuring principle of age groups allegedly would preclude the formation of political party affiliations within the legislatures. And even if they were to form, “those leaning towards different parties would be induced to discuss the issues together, and would become conscious that they had the common task of representing the outlook of their generation…” (Hayek, 2003, p. 118). Obviously, this radical proposal is open to many criticisms from the perspective of democratic theory, but let us leave this aside and instead turn to the final proposal to be considered here, which is also the least specific, calling for the transformation of statehood into a “strong state” as its main proponents Alexander Rüstow and Walter Eucken refer to it.

This remedy manifests the stringent conclusion from the critical diagnosis of excessive pluralism, which is prevalent among most ordoliberals; even Röpke, who is less vocal on this theme, reminds his readers that “the immense danger of this unhealthy pluralism is that pressure groups covetously beset the state” and that “any responsible government must examine carefully all the possible means of resisting this pluralistic disintegration of the state” (Röpke, 1960, pp. 144, 143). Still, the most vehement calls for a strong state come from his ordoliberal compatriots Rüstow and Eucken. The former concludes his lecture State Policy and the Necessary Conditions for Economic Liberalism from 1932 with the following remarks: “The new liberalism, which I and my friends promote, demands a strong state, a state that is positioned above the economy, above the interested parties, in the place where it belongs. And with this confession of faith in a strong state that promotes liberal economic policies and—because the two mutually condition each other—in liberal economic policies that promote a strong state, with this confession I should like to end” (Rüstow, 2017b, p. 149). The state is thus to remove itself from the pluralistic rancor of political parties and interest groups and take up a position that enables it to fend off the demands coming from these actors. In the same year, Eucken published what will come to be considered a founding text of the ordoliberal tradition, entitled Structural Transformation of the State and the Crisis of Capitalism. In this far-ranging article, Eucken lays out his own version of the narrative of liberal decline, which, in his view, happens to coincide with that of Carl Schmitt in this respect and comes to the fore in “the transformation of the liberal state into an economic state” (Eucken, 2017, p. 59). For Eucken, the merging of state, society, and economy encapsulated in the economic state is of the most serious consequence as it “has undermined independent decision-making on the part of the state, something upon which its very existence depends. … All recent economic policy clearly demonstrates this corrosive process: it amounts to a plethora of measures, each of which can be traced back to the wishes of different powerful economic groups but which, taken together, have no coherence and are entirely lacking in system” (Eucken, 2017, pp. 59—60). The state, in short, “lacks the real independent power to make its own decisions” (p. 60).

Similar to Rüstow, Eucken thus demands that the state overcome its looming pluralistic dissolution and instead disentangle itself from the grip of particularistic actors in order to restore a unified and independent will formation of its own in order to become the true “guardian of the competitive order” (Eucken, 1960, p. 327) and enforce it even against powerful economic actors. How this would reflect upon the system of (pluralist) democracy and to what extent it would decline as collateral damage of this operation, if not the actual target of it, is left unaddressed by Eucken—but this omission may in itself be considered rather telling.

These three proposals entail rather controversial ingredients, but, as noted before, I have not sketched them out here to scrutinize them critically, but rather to show that neoliberals invariantly responded to the diagnosed problems of democracy with rather ambitious reform proposals. Without exception, they presupposed that the time for a pragmatic muddling through had passed, and decisive, transformative action had to be taken. What is imagined here, even in the most specific and less far-reaching demand of the constitutional balanced-budget amendment, is more than a marginal policy adjustment but rather amounts to what Hall in his classic discussion refers to as second- or even third-order/paradigmatic change—with the more encompassing proposals from Hayek and the ordoliberals certainly qualifying as the latter (see Hall, 1993). Given the large-scale and rather drastic transformations envisioned, it seems all the more important that there is some consideration given to the way these could be brought about and who the actors are that could plausibly be believed to pursue such strategies, in short, the problem of transformation. But this turns out to be more than a minor challenge for all the neoliberals discussed here.

What this section will show is that neoliberals invariably fail in theorizing a politics of neoliberal transformation, albeit in different and instructive ways. As established in the preceding section, neoliberal reforms are not designed as incremental processes of adjustment, rather they entail a decisive break with the status quo—which is only consequent, given the bleak picture that the diagnoses of contemporary democratic societies paint. But how should transformation be brought about and who are the actors that are to usher in this epochal process of change?

Let us begin with Eucken, whose position in these matters is arguably the weakest among the neoliberals considered here as his account of potential reform strategies amounts to the very absence of such an account. In some of his post-war writings and especially in the posthumously published Principles of Economic Policy, Eucken does indeed identify potential actors that are to enforce a competitive order as the crucial aspect of a broader, interlocking structure of societal orders. The state, churches, and science are thus characterized as “ordering potencies” (Eucken, 1960, p. 325), but their respective potential lies dormant and so Eucken's exposition of the three potencies amounts in large parts to lamenting their respective inability to realize this potential. In other words, Eucken is at a loss as to how the state is to disentangle itself from the sway that interest groups and political parties have over it, or how churches and science could be restored to their former authority and influence. Especially with regard to the state, the task is a formidable one as truly ordoliberal economic policy presupposes the autonomy of the state, which it supposedly achieves, and thus Eucken finds himself in a logical circle: “Without a competitive order no state capable of action can emerge and, conversely, without a state capable of action no competitive order can emerge” (Eucken, 1960, p. 338).

While in Eucken's case, the matter of neoliberal strategy is not pursued any further, Röpke addresses the question of the actors who could bring about his particular ordoliberal vision of a decentralized and demassified society. “The conviction is rightly gaining ground that the important thing is that every society should have a small but influential group of leaders who feel themselves to be the whole community's guardians of inviolable norms and values and who strictly live up to this guardianship. What we need is true nobilitas naturalis” (Röpke, 1960, p. 130). There is no need to go into the details of Röpke's extolling of a virtuous class of clerks benevolently guarding the political community, which draws on Plato's notion of a guardian class as well as classically conservative notions of natural(ized) social hierarchy. What deserves attention in our context is the already deeply pessimistic framing of Röpke's introduction of a nobilitas naturalis. “Evidently, many and sometimes difficult conditions must be fulfilled and endure if such a natural aristocracy is to develop and endure and if it is to discharge its tasks. It must grow and mature, and the slowness of its ripening is matched by the swiftness of its possible destruction” (Röpke, 1960, p. 131). Thus, as soon as the actors of Röpke's reform agenda are introduced, they all but disappear again as it turns out that theirs is a profoundly fleeting existence that depends on a rather unlikely constellation of factors and conditions that all to easily evaporate, and with it the cherished “aristocrats of public spirit” (p. 131). And to be sure, this is not just rhetoric, considering Röpke's lengthy characterizations of these “clerks.” What is required among other things to qualify as one of society's guardians is a “life of dedicated endeavor on behalf of all, unimpeachable integrity, constant restraint of our common greed, proved soundness of judgment, a spotless private life, indomitable courage to stand up for truth and law, and generally the highest example” (Röpke, 1960, pp. 130—131). Given this demanding profile, it is no surprise that the emergence and persistence of such a guardian class are characterized as exceedingly unlikely. After all, it seems as if it would take actors of almost otherworldly nature to satisfy Röpke's standards, and so it is only consequent for him to refer to them as “secularized saints,” and given the religious idiom into which these matters are transferred in Röpke's account, it seems appropriate to refer to this as a typical ‘deus-ex-machina’-motive, which reveals the lacunae in Röpke's thought.

With regard to Rüstow, we already know that the proposed remedy is the transformation of the current, weak state into a strong one. But how to bypass the entrenched networks of interested parties who are capable of whipping the masses into action against any kind of reform effort that threatens their access to the troughs of money and power? In an early intervention in the form of a lecture from 1929, Rüstow imagines a path toward a nonpluralist politics that can be referred to as transitional dictatorship without a stretch. After all, the title of the lecture is Dictatorship within the Bounds of Democracy (Rüstow, 1959, [1929]). According to his proposal, the government led by a chancellor would be granted the right to govern for a certain period of time, even if it lacks a parliamentary majority. The suspension of the possibility of being forced to resign or have bills and measures defeated in parliamentary votes is to give the government the leeway to pursue what Rüstow undoubtedly imagined to be the kind of politics that Röpke's aristocrats of the public spirit would have enacted. Once the granted time period is over, the suspension of parliamentary power and oversight ceases and the government has to face the respective scrutiny as well as the possibility of being voted out of office again. “This means the preservation of democracy because it is a time-limited dictatorship, not in the strict sense of the term, but, as it were, a dictatorship with a probational period” (Rüstow, 1959, p. 99).

In Hayek's case, things are, unsurprisingly, more complex, but the thrust of his point is clear enough. Already in Law, Legislation and Liberty, he discusses emergency powers as potentially necessary to secure the long-term stability of a political community in the midst of a crisis and/or the verge of totalitarian collectivism (Hayek, 2003, III, p. 124). This argument is located at a neuralgic point in Hayek's thought, systematically speaking, because just as in the case of other neoliberals, he faces the task of spelling out a plausible path toward a more neoliberal society amid a world that, according to his own analysis, has already begun its descent on the (in-)famous Road to Serfdom. Emergency powers and a state of exception in the form of a transitory dictatorship represent the theoretical bridge that connects the status quo with Hayek's neoliberal vision. This comes to the fore most clearly and also most controversially in Hayek's notorious comments on Chile after the coup of Augusto Pinochet, displaying his usual candor in an interview with El Mercurio in 1981: “As long-term institutions I am totally against dictatorships. But a dictatorship may be a necessary system for a transitional period. At times it is necessary for a country to have, for a time, some kind of dictatorial power. As you will understand, it is possible for a dictator to govern in a liberal way. … My personal impression … is that in Chile … we will witness the transition from a dictatorial to a liberal government…” (El Mercurio, 1981, p. D9).

By the early 1980s, Hayek had obviously persuaded himself that a transitional dictatorship was a legitimate option to save political communities from succumbing to totalitarianism-cum-collectivism, and as we know from the quote in the preceding section, Hayek was also convinced that this was not just a matter pertaining to Chile or other “underdeveloped” countries but that the slide into totalitarianism was a tendency inherent to actually existing contemporary democracy.

What are we to make of these proposals? Starting with Rüstow, if the envisioned “dictatocracy” is really to remain within the boundaries of democracy, it would have to be established through a parliamentary vote changing the constitution. However, as he himself notes, “I am not enough of a utopian to assume that a proposition as I just sketched it would normally find a majority to change the constitution in the Reichstag today. … If we had a Reichstag where something like that was conceivable then the proposition would be unnecessary” (Rüstow, 1959, p. 100). And given this “Catch 22,” which parallels the respective problems in Eucken, Rüstow must either bury his hopes for a truly transformative politics that walks the thin line between democracy and dictatorship, or he would have to discard his remnant democratic sensibilities and opt for dictatorial politics sans phrase.

Both Rüstow and Hayek face another more general problem, they leave largely unaddressed, namely, whether it is realistic to assume that transitional dictatorship remains transitional. To be sure, history knows instances where dictators or democratic leaders with de facto dictatorial powers quietly and dutifully stepped aside and thus enabled a return to normal conditions, but it was Hayek himself who had based his slippery slope argument in The Road to Serfdom on the notion that unchecked powers tend to become entrenched and engender a dynamic that tends toward the totalitarian. The plenitude of power required for comprehensive planning, as Hayek had argued back then, would even drag the most well-meaning socialists into the deadly politics of totalitarianism. Why would these mechanisms not apply to the transitional dictatorships that do not seek to pave the way toward socialism but liberal authoritarianism? A Hayekian line of defense may be to resort to a point contained in The Road to Serfdom, according to which such a dynamic is triggered only by economic interventionism and not political interventions, that is, if liberal authoritarianism abstained from economic interventions, it might arrest any potential totalitarian dynamic, but whether this differentiation is a convincing one is rather disputable. While Hayek at least has an argument, albeit a weak one, it remains a real mystery, why Rüstow never gave any explicit attention to this conundrum; all the more so, since he—and also Hayek—were acutely aware of the work of Carl Schmitt. And in his writings on the state of exception, one major and not entirely implausible point is that the liberal ambition of arresting the mercurial nature of a state of exception by codifying rules that govern its modalities and the emergency powers ensuing from it is ultimately futile. So if Rüstow's hope was that his version of a transitional dictatocracy would remain transitional because it was thus codified in the constitution—if there was ever a majority in favor of it—this is almost naïve from a Schmittian point of view. So we see that in both cases, the reform strategy proposed is incompatible with more or less explicit assumptions underlying the respective points of view.

Our final case study is the work of James Buchanan, who is also the most fascinating example because while Rüstow and Eucken mostly try to avoid the issue of strategy and implementation, he grapples with it directly over and over again.

Buchanan's specific challenge is not altogether different from the problems haunting the neoliberals we have already discussed. It can be stated quite succinctly in the form of a simple question that still proves to have rather devastating implications. If the assumptions of the public choice theory suggest that homo oeconomicus is a behavioral model appropriate for the analysis of political actors and rent-seeking is a practice not only rent seekers but also those who are in a position to grant rents, that is, politicians, benefit from, how can we assume that these actors will pass a constitutional balanced-budget amendment designed to curb among other things rent-seeking behavior?

Obviously, Buchanan was well aware of the problem he faced and undertook multiple unsuccessful attempts to deal with it, the chronicling of which would exceed the scope of the paper. Eventually, he found himself forced to rethink a crucial element in his own thought, namely, that of homo oeconomicus and how it was intertwined with rent-seeking behavior.

Over time he becomes more and more adamant that homo oeconomicus is just one of several personae that make up any actual person and at times suggests an almost dualist anthropology when he writes that there is “a struggle within each of us … between rent-seeker and the constitutionalists, and that almost all citizens will play, simultaneously, both roles” (Buchanan, 1991, pp. 2, 10). This battle between normative orientations will become a site of major strategic importance for Buchanan because the conclusion he draws is that “the constitutionalist” in ourselves needs to be strengthened against the “rent-seeker” just as Rousseau thought the “citoyen” had to be strengthened vis-à-vis the “bourgeois.” It is only consequent, therefore, that Buchanan writes that “the reform that I seek lies first of all in attitudes” (Buchanan, 1975, p. 176). This is noteworthy because it contradicts the claim routinely made by liberals or conservatives that they subscribe to a realist anthropology that “takes people as they are” and treats their preferences as “exogenous variables” refraining from any attempt to educate or change them but solely focus on social and political rules. Buchanan does want to change people, and he more and more explicitly embraces the notion that in this matter it is not enough to appeal to homo oeconomicus. In a paper titled “The Soul of Classical Liberalism,” Buchanan diagnoses the failure of liberalism to capture the hearts and minds of people because it lacks an appealing narrative: “Science and self-interest, especially as combined, do indeed lend force to any argument. But a vision of an ideal, over and beyond science and self-interest, is necessary, and those who profess membership in the club of classical liberals have failed singularly in their neglect of this requirement” (Buchanan, 2000, p. 112). The constitutionalist in us cannot be strengthened through a “rational” argument appealing to the authority of science or self-interest alone, because what is at stake is an entire worldview that one comes to believe in. Only when attitudinal patterns have changed to a sufficient degree will it be possible to pursue the political project Buchanan continues to envision, which he describes as no less than a “constitutional revolution,” in sharp contrast to the incrementalism of “pragmatic reform” (Buchanan & Di Pierro, 1969, p. 95). However, this strategy entails a major concession that Buchanan himself spells out: “To hold out hope for reform in the basic rules describing the sociopolitical game, we must introduce elements that violate the self-interest postulate” (Brennan & Buchanan, 1985, p. 146). This is remarkable given that the entire critique of the rent-seeking society and actually existing democracy, of course, rests on the “self-interest postulate” of homo oeconomicus.

And so here we finally come to see that not only Buchanan had to attenuate his stance regarding the potential benevolence of actors, thus moving a little closer to the views of those who like Röpke place their hopes in a particular set of actors, but he also comes to commit himself not to a state of exception as a precondition of neoliberal reform but to what might be called a politics of the extraordinary with the radical connotations of a revolution. And so, in similarity to Hayek and Rüstow, Buchanan conceives of neoliberal reform politics as a caesura that can produce a real rupture of the iron cage of the ever same in which the entrenched rent-seeking networks are dismantled and the “basic rules of the sociopolitical rules” can finally be changed. Not only are these dreams of rupture shared by Buchanan and Hayek, but they are also expressed by Rüstow when he muses on “great politics, the politics that is the art of the impossible, that which wrongly was considered impossible” (Rüstow, 1963, p. 117) and Friedman who envisions a political window of opportunity within which “what seemed impossible suddenly becomes possible” (Friedman & Friedman, 1990, p. xiv). What is on display here is an almost eschatological hope for the moment of the great rupture, the day of reckoning and of reversal, when the powers that be are unseated and a new kingdom will be erected—only here, it is not the kingdom of god but rather the realm of neoliberalism.

What I have developed in this paper is a critique of neoliberal thought that rests on the latter's inability to theorize in a consistent and plausible manner the problem of transition. The neoliberals in that sense are similar to those whom Marx described and derided as Utopian Socialists: bursting with visions about a better future but unable to develop strategies to realize these visions. Despite the variations described above, an overall pattern can still be detected: With their at times harsh criticisms of actually existing democracies, neoliberal thinkers back themselves into a theoretical corner because the more apocalyptic the critical diagnoses get, the more difficult it is to sketch a path out of the misery that is the status quo. Put differently, what the neoliberal critic gains in terms of the urgency of his diagnoses, the neoliberal reformer loses in terms of the viability of change. This confronts neoliberals with a dilemma encapsulated best in Buchanan's concession regarding the weakening of the self-interest postulate: Either neoliberals want to hold on to their trenchant critiques of democracy and the assumptions underlying them, but then they effectively forfeit the ability to also explain how conditions could possibly be changed and their accounts in effect turn into pessimistic conservatism. Or they want to be able to maintain the theoretical ability to capture the politics of neoliberal reform, but then they have to relax some of their assumptions and in effect scale back their critique of the democratic status quo significantly.

Describing this as a dilemma is the most modest version of this conclusion, which changes if we take the dimension of actually existing neoliberalism into account, which, after all, provides ample evidence for the possibility and factuality of neoliberal reform: The so-called debt brakes European countries have passed in response to the Eurozone Crisis is the equivalent of Buchanan's cherished balanced-budget amendment, and there are indeed such balanced-budget amendments on the state and municipal level in the United States (see Peck, 2014). Furthermore, when it comes to actors sufficiently isolated from democratic pressures to make “rational” decisions, there are, prominently, central banks that have been granted independence with minimal accountability requirements across the OECD world, and there is the European Commission in charge of overseeing competition and deficit rules in the Eurozone, both of which can be considered to be part of what has been referred to as “the rise of the unelected” (Vibert, 2009). Finally, one must not forget the international trade regimes, such as the WTO, free trade areas such as the European Union or Mercusor in South America, and free trade agreements such as CETA between Canada and the EU, all of which have effectively reined in the powers of sovereign nation-states in many trade-related areas and beyond (see Slobodian, 2018a). Adding this aspect prompts several further questions. First, if there are clear examples of neoliberal reform, are the lacunae in neoliberal theory not essentially moot points, and is that not an indication of the insignificance of neoliberal theory in comparison with actually existing neoliberalism? Moreover, given the realization of neoliberal reforms, might there not be something like a performative theory of transition, which can be distilled from the nonacademic endeavors of someone like Buchanan? Finally, how does the conclusion regarding the dilemma referred to above change with this in mind? Let me begin with this last question: Old-fashioned falsificationism would tell us that if the conclusion of a theory is at odds with observed reality, this necessarily means that there is something wrong with the assumptions of the theory. Applied to the constellation at hand, this means: Neoliberal theory arrives at conclusions that are at odds with observed reality, that is, the facticity of neoliberal reform politics; therefore, there is something wrong with the assumptions of the theory, meaning that the neoliberal critiques of democracy, to the extent that they rest on these assumptions, have to be considered questionable. Regarding the second question, it is true that neoliberals such as Buchanan and Hayek had their ideas about how their ideas could have an impact, which, in Buchanan's case, is chronicled by Nancy Maclean in her controversial account of his nonacademic activities, including cooperation with various interest groups and shady donors (see MacLean, 2017, pp. 199–204). Still, my point is that on the theoretical level, there are still lacunae that have repercussions for the plausibility of their critical analyses of democracy and this is what I am ultimately driving at with my argument.

Finally, Materialists will hasten to point out that identifying such lacunae will not make neoliberalism or its critique of democracy suddenly disappear and I agree. However, in order to be ultimately effective, the critique of neoliberalism must be conducted not only in the register of struggle and power politics, challenging actually existing neoliberalism but also in discursive contestation and the realm of theory on the basis of various kinds of critiques, including immanent ones pointing out inconsistencies, as I have tried to do here. Importantly, the argument contained in this paper is not supposed to “refute” neoliberal theory in its entirety, not the least because ideologies tend to contain contradictions, so identifying them does not necessarily deal a metaphorical death blow to them. My aim is a more specific one, namely, to highlight the dilemma that neoliberals face, which is most clearly on display in the case of Buchanan who openly concedes that the assumptions guiding his critique of democracy have to be relaxed in order to hold out hope for what he considers to be meaningful reforms, and thus undermine the plausibility of neoliberal arguments against democracy. There is no need to overstate the significance of such a critique, which is by no means sufficient, but, conversely, only focusing on the material level leaves to neoliberals the option of blaming unfaithful and incomplete implementation for any negative effect associated with, for example, introducing balanced-budget amendments, maintaining that their theoretical frameworks in themselves are not affected by this. It is such flaws in the framework that my critique aims to reveal.

Beyond this immediate conclusion, let me point out one more implication that appears to be worthy of more elaborate discussion in future research in light of what has been argued here:

Given the eschatological hopes neoliberals seem to harbor for a political rupture, this might also provide a link to the politics of what now is typically referred to as (right-wing) populism (but is de facto authoritarianism). After all, the self-portrayal of populist leaders who vow to “drain the swamp” and, generally, sweep aside decadent and corrupt establishments, corresponds to a considerable degree with what neoliberals apparently thought was necessary to overcome the gridlock and inertia of normal politics and implement neoliberal reforms. There can be little doubt that Hayek or Buchanan would have abhorred the notion of a Donald Trump as President of the United States or a Boris Johnson as Prime Minister of the UK—after all, they could not be any less “aristocrats of public spirit”; but still, the theoretical dilemmas their critiques of democracy create for them make the neoliberals inadvertently gravitate toward the kind of ruptural antiestablishment politics that populist movements and parties at least claim to represent. They are neoliberalism's “Frankenstein,” to borrow an expression from Wendy Brown (2018)—or its “bastards,” to borrow one from Quinn Slobodian (2018b). To be sure, one might argue that the Trump administration, to take a prominent example, attacked global regimes of economic multilateralism in the name of economic nationalism and would thus be in opposition to the kind of international free trade regimes, zones, and agreements cited above as manifestations of neoliberal reforms. However, upon closer inspection, the opposition to neoliberal designs turns out to be less than strict: The Trump administration indeed left NAFTA—but only to negotiate a new free trade zone called UMSCA with minimally better conditions for the United States. On the other hand, the tax reform under Trump could have just as well been passed under Reagan—in fact, Reagan's adviser from back then, Arthur Laffer, was also brought in as a consultant by the Trump administration. But while the opposition between them is overstated in many instances, my point is not that the substantive policies pursued by right-wing populists are all in congruence with neoliberal ideas. Rather, the major point of convergence between the two consists in their view of politics as necessarily disruptive in order to shake up the seemingly locked-in status quo dominated by mainstream political actors with no incentive to enact any real change to the “system.” By the same token, this is what turns both, neoliberals and right-wing populists, into antagonists of liberal democracy and its inertia, but while neoliberals dream of an ultra-stable world of almost self-enforcing rules to succeed in the moment of rupture, right-wing populists aim for the contrary: A world of rupture becoming permanent.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
52
期刊最新文献
Issue Information Issue Information Issue Information Fear of Black Consciousness By Lewis R. Gordon. Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2022 Deparochializing Political Theory By Melissa S. Williams, New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 2020
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1