用诽谤的方式为从属地位投票

IF 0.2 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pluralist Pub Date : 2023-10-01 DOI:10.5406/19446489.18.3.03
Duckkyun Lee
{"title":"用诽谤的方式为从属地位投票","authors":"Duckkyun Lee","doi":"10.5406/19446489.18.3.03","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"In this paper, I develop an account of slurs focusing on their two underappreciated features. The first underappreciated feature is what I call their “communal nature.” Slurs are communal. The meaning of a slur depends on the existence of a significant number of people who are bigoted against the target. When this condition is not satisfied, a slur loses its power to offend. This can be seen when we consider how philosophers choose examples of slurs to avoid offending people. For example, Williamson, in his essay “Reference, Inference and the Semantics of Pejoratives,” uses a slur for Germans as his main example. What makes the slur for Germans a safe example to use is the fact that there is no widespread bigotry against Germans in any Anglophone country. Had there been strong enmity between Germans and the people in the Anglophone countries, even if Williamson had chosen an outdated slur, his example would not have been such a safe choice. Slurs are words that bigots use to offend and harm the people they are bigoted against. When there are no bigots, neither are there slurs.The focus on the communal nature of slurs leads to the second underappreciated feature of slurs. A bigot does not use a slur just to express his beliefs or feelings, but to subordinate his target. To subordinate others, a bigot needs to cooperate and coordinate with other bigots. In this paper, I will propose a mechanism for how slurs work as a tool for coordinating subordination. To account for the communal and subordinating nature of slurs, I turn to speech act theory and explain what kind of illocutionary act is performed when one uses a slur.1My proposal is to understand utterances made using a slur, or slurring,2 as an act of casting a vote for ranking the target as socially inferior. On this view, a slur is a conventional tool used to cast a vote demanding the subordination of its target. The considerations that motivate this view are as follows: First, the uses of a slur are the results of consciously choosing it over its neutral counterpart. By explicitly avoiding a neutral counterpart term, one can show their support for fellow bigots and the willingness to participate in whatever activity they do. Second, the point of using a slur does not seem to be exhausted by its role of expressing the bigot's negative beliefs about the target. We can see this when we consider that the way to fight a slur is to impose strict prohibitions against its use, not by objecting to the content of the slurring utterance. This can be better explained when we understand the slur as a conventional tool for the performance of a certain type of action, rather than a word that has distinctive descriptive content different from the descriptive content of its neutral counterpart. Finally, the point of some speech acts is not just expressing the state of the mind of the speaker. The point of some speech acts is to change what is the case in society. To make an utterance using a slur seems to fall into this latter category of speech acts. What would bigots be up to if they were not engaged in the project of creating a society where their target was inferior to them? This consideration suggests that making an utterance using a slur might fall into the kind of speech act Searle calls declaration (Taxonomy 361–68). As a declaration, slurring is an attempt to change society such that the target is subordinated.Insofar as an election is understood as a process within which people collectively decide on what should be the case in society by indicating their stance for or against a proposal, slurring can be understood as a casting of a vote in the election bigots’ proposal to subordinate their target. I argue that this account can better explain why a slur cannot function as a slur without there being a significant number of bigots, and how it is used to coordinate the bigots’ effort of subordinating their target.The paper proceeds in the following order. In section 2, I briefly delineate the target of my account. Among many different pejoratives, my account attempts to investigate the slurs that target not individuals with certain features, but groups as a whole, and slurs for which there are neutral counterpart terms. In section 3, I will explain in detail what I mean by the claim that slurs have a communal and subordinating nature and why I do not think the existing accounts give a satisfactory explanation of them. In section 4, I develop and justify my own proposal that slurs are a conventional tool to perform the illocutionary act of voting for subordination. Understanding slurring as an act of voting for subordination can give us a helpful insight into how the social hierarchy comes into existence; slurring satisfies important conditions to count as an act of voting; a typical strategy of fighting slurring also supports my proposal. Finally, in section 5, I will briefly show how my proposal can explain other important characteristics of slurs just as well as any other rivaling accounts. Especially, I will outline two important explanatory challenges: the projective behavior of slurs and our conflicting intuitions about the truth-value of sentences with a slur.Before developing my view, I want to make clear what I count as a slur. First, slurs are pejorative terms that target groups, not individuals. They target different kinds of groups: racial groups, religious groups, occupational groups, groups with certain sexual orientations, and so on. This distinguishes slurs from pejoratives targeting individuals. For example, words like “asshole” are not considered a slur since there is no socially recognized group associated with it. Second, slurs are pejoratives that are paired with a neutral counterpart. This distinguishes slurs from other group-targeting pejoratives that do not have a corresponding neutral counterpart. For example, “pimp” is a pejorative for a certain group of people, but since it lacks a neutral counterpart, I do not count it as a slur in this paper.Slurs are derogatory words. They are deeply offensive. What is it about them that makes their use so offensive? To answer this question, let's start with some obvious features of slurs. Slurs are words that are used by bigots. What interests do slurs serve for them? Ultimately, what makes a bigot a bigot is that he has an interest in making life harder for the people he is bigoted against. A slur might have various uses, but one thing that is certain is that it is a means for a bigot to achieve this goal. Slurs contribute to the achievement of this goal by helping bigots recognize each other and coordinate with each other. When a bigot uses a slur, he knows very well that there are other slur users out there and that by using the slur, he is joining them. These features show that slurs are the words that bigots use to create a society, together with other bigots, where their target is subordinated.I believe that what I have said so far would be acceptable to most who work on slurs. However, the existing accounts of slurs that have been proposed so far do not yield a satisfactory explanation for the two features. The goal of this section is to show this and to motivate the need for an alternative account. Although there are numerous and varied accounts of slurs, one can categorize the existing accounts from the perspective of speech act theory, by looking at what kinds of speech act each account of slurs thinks can be performed with utterances containing slurs. For a succinct overview of the existing accounts, I will illustrate them using the following hypothetical conversation between Sam, Chris, and Alex.(Here and below, to avoid mentions of slurs, I will use the following notation system to talk about slurs. “S*” is a slur for a group. “G*” is a neutral counterpart term referring to the group that “S*” targets. Asterisks are used to differentiate slurs targeting different groups. “S*” and “S**” are two different slurs that target two different groups, G* and G**.)In this conversation, Sam answered Chris's question and gave her information about the new boss's group identity. Alex, in addition to answering Chris's question, asserted that the information Sam gave was incorrect and provided different information about the new boss's group identity. However, this description of the conversation above would be an extremely distorted description of what happened in the conversation. They did not merely exchange information about the new boss. By using slurs, they did something bad to the new boss, G*, and G**, and this warrants offense.3 All accounts of slurs seek to identify what it is that they did that warrants offense in addition to exchanging information about the new boss's group identity.According to the existing accounts, what they did in addition to the exchange of information largely fell into two categories. First, the offensiveness of their speech lies at the locutionary level. What Alex, Chris, and Sam did by using the slurs was a violation of a norm governing our choice of words when we produce meaningful utterances.4 It is not that their utterances with slurs have a special illocutionary force that warrants offense. The problem is that they violated the norm that prohibits the use of slurs. That is what makes their utterances so offensive, just as using a swear word in a formal address is offensive. The kind of speech act performed using a slur does not matter.Secondly, we can understand the offensiveness as coming from a specific illocutionary act that was performed using it. What warrants offense is not just the act of choosing a prohibited word, but what one does in using the prohibited word. Accounts that take this approach can again be divided roughly into three sub-classes depending on the kind of illocutionary act they identify as the act performed by using a slur. First, using a slur is an act of conveying some false, derogatory information about the target. Though the exact mechanism with which the derogatory information is conveyed varies from account to account,5 what they are doing in the conversation in addition to exchanging the information about the new boss's group identity is to convey the false information that members of G* and G** have some negative properties.6 Second, illocutionary acts performed using a slur are acts of getting the hearer to adopt an adversary attitude toward their targets.7 Finally, utterances of sentences containing a slur could be an act of expressing negative emotions against the target.8 By uttering “she was an S*,” Sam expressed her contempt for the new boss's group identity.Formulated in terms of the speech act theory framework, these approaches are not mutually exclusive, as one can perform multiple acts with a single utterance. So the accounts above should be understood as identifying the primary source of the offensiveness of slurs. Taken as such, each account has its own merits and shortcomings. However, what they share in common is their negligence of the two key features of slurs: their communal character and their role as a tool for subordination. No accounts suggested so far capture the fact that bigots use slurs only if they know that there are other fellow bigots using them, nor do they ask what it implies that they are using slurs together with other bigots. In what follows, I will elucidate these two features of slurs in detail and explain in what sense the existing accounts cannot satisfactorily explicate them.Let us consider the communal nature first. All linguistic expressions depend on the linguistic convention, and they are communal to that extent. However, the communal nature of slurs goes beyond mere conventionality. Slurs are communal because the success of the offensive speech act performed by using a slur depends on the existence of a certain social group, that is, a large number of people who are bigoted against their targets.To see this, imagine an American who is extremely bigoted against the British people. She learns the slur for the British from a dictionary and starts using it to refer to them, intending her speech to be as offensive and scandalous as speech with other well-known slurs. However, contrary to her expectations, her speech act is hardly offensive, unlike a slur for African Americans. What explains the difference in the offensiveness is that, whereas there are many who are bigoted against African Americans, there is only a meager number of people who are bigoted against the British. Imagine this same American moved to Ireland. Her speech would be quite offensive, since antipathy against the British people is still strong in Ireland. Using the slur, she would be able to perform an offensive and scandalous speech act there. This shows that whatever speech act one performs using a slur, its success as an offensive speech act depends on the fact that there must be a significant number of fellow bigots in the society.The communal nature of a slur manifests itself not just in the way its offensiveness covaries with the bigotry against its target in a society. It also manifests itself in the way it is created. Someone who is extremely bigoted against a certain group of people might create a word to use as a slur for them. Further, somehow, everyone in her linguistic community knows the story about this new word. Yet this is not sufficient to make her use of the word offensive. So long as there is only one person who is bigoted against the group, her use of the word would strike people as eccentric rather than offensive. Only when there are sufficient people who share her bigotry and adopt her word can the word be used as a slur. Whatever she wants to do with the word, she cannot do it alone.These considerations show that for a bigot to use a slur successfully, that is, to perform whatever offensive speech act that is normally performed with a slur, there needs to be a group of fellow bigots using the slur. How could the existing accounts explain this fact? Among the two kinds of accounts classified above, the accounts that identify the offensive speech act performed with a slur as an illocutionary act are hard-pressed to explain this fact.Suppose slurs are offensive because they are used to convey some false and derogatory information about the target. In principle, then, one can always create a slur because one can create a word that encodes some false and derogatory information about some group. To those who are familiar with the word, the use of the word would be offensive, but its offensiveness would not depend on the existence of people who are bigoted against the same group. The same can be said about other kinds of speech acts that the existing account has identified with the slur. Anyone can create a new word to give an offensive order or to express one's negative emotional state. To perform the intended offensive speech act successfully, one needs to make sure that one's interlocutors become familiar with your lexicon. However, there need not be a large number of fellow bigots using the word. You can convey some information, give an order, or express your emotional state by making your intention known to your interlocutor.The account according to which the offensiveness of slurs comes from the fact that they are prohibited words better captures the communal aspect. If a slur is a prohibited word, a natural explanation for its prohibition is that there are many people who use the word in an offensive way. Otherwise, there would be no point in prohibiting it. However, this account does not explain why slurs are prohibited in the first place. There must be something offensive in what bigots do with the word, such that the targets need to prohibit it. Unless what bigots do with slurs is clarified, the prohibited word account cannot offer a satisfactory examination of slurs.Slurs are words that bigots use when they want their targets to be subordinated. This is not to say that individual bigots form the intention to subordinate the target whenever they use a slur. The psychological state of an individual user of a slur might differ from situation to situation. Someone might use a slur when he is annoyed by the presence of a member of a racial group he hates. He might use a slur at different times when he thinks that his bigoted beliefs about a racial group have been vindicated by the act of a member of the group. Regardless of the intention behind each token use of a slur, that slur contributes to the subordination of the targeted group. This is the reason why we treat slurs differently than swearing words in general.The key question is how a slur contributes to the subordination of its target. All the existing accounts of slurs can explain the relationship between the uses of slurs and subordination as a causal relationship. For example, if a slur has derogatory content about its target as part of its meaning, its use can convey that content to the audience, change the beliefs of the audience, and as a result, change how the audience treats the target group. According to this understanding, using a slur is not itself an act of subordinating the target. A bigot does something else, and the subordination of the target might or might not follow, depending on how downstream causal effects unfold. When I argue that slurs have a subordinating nature, what I mean is not merely that they can causally contribute to the subordination of their target; I also mean that the use of slurs is itself an act of subordination. Regardless of the intention behind the use of a slur, its use always constitutes an act of subordination. The following fact supports this understanding.There is a distinctive way in which we resist the use of slurs, which is to outrightly ban their use. This would not be the case if slurs were just causally responsible for subordination. When we hear someone using a slur, the only effective way of resisting it is to stop the person from using it. However, if subordination is just a causal effect of a slurring speech act, we should be able to do many more things to prevent the use of a slur from having subordination as its causal effect. For example, if a slur is a word that has derogatory implications about its target as its literal meaning, one could explicitly reject to endorse the proposition expressed with the slur, by saying something like “No, he is not an S* because he is charming, athletic, and smart.” However, this would be an absurd response to an utterance of a slur.Compare this with the case of the use of derogatory words that target people with certain (imaginary) characteristics. We can resist this use by arguing that the relevant characteristics do not exist at all or are not instantiated by the targets. For example, against the use of the S-word against a woman, we can say something like: “No, women are not promiscuous or unchaste. These are old-fashioned concepts that do not apply to anything.” This response is possible because the literal content of the S-word is causally responsible for the connection between its use and the subordination of women. That this kind of resistance to a slur is impossible shows that there is no literal content in slurs that is responsible for the subordination of their target.When we understand the use of slurs as constituting a distinctive kind of speech act whose illocutionary point is to subordinate its target, we don't have to look for the medium that is causally responsible for the connection between the use of a slur and subordination, and we can understand why the only effective way of resisting slurs is to ban their use outright. The key task is, then, to explain how an act of using certain words could be an act of subordination. Before developing my own account, I will make the notion of subordination clear. Once we have a clear understanding of what subordination consists of, we will be able to understand how an act of using certain words can be an act of subordination as well.Rae Langton develops an account of pornography in which pornography is understood as an illocutionary act of subordinating women. According to Langton, a speech act is an illocutionary act of subordination when it does one of the following things: unfairly ranking the target as having inferior worth, legitimizing discriminatory behaviors against the target, or unjustly depriving its target of some important rights or powers (304). “Blacks are not permitted to vote” uttered by a South African legislator during apartheid is an example of a subordinating speech act that deprives black people of political rights. Pornography might be a subordinating speech act if, by representing women as sexual objects, it ranks women as socially inferior to men or legitimizes treating women as such.Although Langton's purpose is not to develop an extensive account of subordinating speech acts, her account of subordinating speech acts and their application to pornographic speech acts is illuminating. First, she explores the possibility of attributing an illocutionary force to a speech act that looks drastically different from paradigmatic cases of speech acts with the illocutionary force in question. In her view, pornography is very different from such paradigmatic cases of speech acts of assigning rankings to people: it is not made with the explicit rules for who can assign rankings to whom under which conditions (Langton, “Speech Acts” 310). However, as Langton's work shows, this does not necessarily mean that pornography cannot be an act of ranking women as inferior. We can reasonably assume that the hierarchy between people and the authority to determine the relative ranks between people can exist outside highly organized social institutions (Langton, “Speech Acts” 312). In principle, an illocutionary act can appear to be completely different from paradigm cases of the same kind.Second, Langton offers a general strategy with which one can justify an ascription of an illocutionary force to a speech act regardless of its seeming difference from paradigm cases. According to Langton, one can justify an ascription of an illocutionary force to a speech act by asking three questions: First, whether the speech in question has satisfied some important felicity conditions to have the illocutionary force in question. Felicity conditions are conditions that an attempt to perform a speech act must meet for it to be successful. A common felicity condition for declarations is authority. For example, we cannot call a speech act of declaring a move in a game as a foul if the speaker does not meet important conditions for it that include being the appointed umpire of the game (see Austin 12–24); second, whether the hearer takes the speech to have the illocutionary force in question; third, whether the perlocutionary effect of the speech can be best explained by supposing that the speech has the illocutionary force. Using this strategy, she gives three reasons to consider pornography as a subordinating illocutionary act: First, pornographers, even if they are not held in high esteem in society, are authoritative for the men who “want to know which moves in the sexual game are legitimate” (Langton, “Speech Acts” 312). Second, many women take pornography to be subordinating; that is, many women take pornography to have the illocutionary force of subordination. Finally, that pornography has subordinating illocutionary force might be one reason why it has the perlocutionary effect of making men more likely to see women as sexual objects. These reasons are all fallible, yet they support the ascription of the subordinating illocutionary force to pornography.We can apply the same strategy to speech acts made with a slur. They do not seem to be an act of subordination. A person can make an order, an assertion, or a question using a slur, and how can they be all understood as acts of subordinating their target? We can apply Langton's formulas to answer this question. First, does speech made with a slur satisfy the felicity conditions to have the illocutionary force of subordinating its target? Second, do the hearers take the speech to have the illocutionary force of subordination? Third, is the perlocutionary effect of speech made with a slur best explained by supposing that it has the illocutionary force of subordination? I suggest that the answers to these three questions are all positive.Let me start with the third question. Is there a perlocutionary effect of speech with a slur that can be better explained by understanding it as an act of ranking the target as inferior? The phenomenon that supports my proposal is the very existence and persistence of the social hierarchy between groups within a society. As Searle points out, what is distinctive about social reality is that it is created and maintained by our linguistic activity.9 When successful, what is said in a declaration becomes the case. “Blacks are not permitted to vote” uttered by a South African legislator during apartheid makes it the case that blacks are not permitted to vote. On the contrary, “Blacks are prone to violence” uttered by the same legislator cannot make it the case that blacks are prone to violence, regardless of how many people accept what has been asserted. The relative rank of a social group within a social hierarchy is also what is determined by declarations. When a declaration about the rank of a group within a social hierarchy is successful, it becomes part of the social reality that the group takes up that position in the social hierarchy. The relative rank of groups in a society can be determined in various ways, for example, by a King's order. However, the ranks of each group can persist as long as the people in the society continue to collectively represent them as having these ranks. The group has the lower social rank only if the majority in a society collectively represents that group as having a lower social rank than they have. However, there is no natural base in response to which people form the belief that different groups have different ranks that they have. The hierarchy of a given society is based on its people representing the society as having that social hierarchy. Since there is no natural base for that representation, the representation needs to be reproduced again and again. That is, the fact that there is an unjust social hierarchy in our society that is determined by one's race, gender, sexuality, and so on, indicates that the performances of declarations in which those who are subordinated are represented as inferior are made repeatedly. Furthermore, since social hierarchy cannot be created and maintained without the collaboration of the majority of society, such declarations need to be made by the majority of the members of the society.Slurs have the characteristics that make them an apt tool for such subordinating declarations for at least three reasons. First, slurs are paired with their neutral counterparts. Therefore, a slur can function as a linguistic tag that is attached to its target as a marker for an inferior social position. Second, the uses of a slur are the result of an intentional choice over its neutral counterpart. For this reason, a slur is an efficient tool for indicating one's position. Since the knowledge of the meaning of a slur includes the knowledge about the kind of people who use the slur, a conscious choice to use a slur indicates that one has a similar position to that of the slur users. Furthermore, since slurs can be used anytime when there is a need to refer to the target group, one can indicate one's position anytime without interrupting the flow of the conversation. Finally, one can indicate one's position using a slur without being fully explicit about what it is that one is committed to. As pointed out by many who work on slurs,10 it is notoriously difficult to specify what descriptive content a slur has. However, if a slur is a tool for indicating one's support for the existing social hierarchy, it is no wonder that there seems to be no fixed descriptive content with a slur. One indicates one's position by using the same word as bigots do. At the same time, one can secure plausible deniability by not making one's position explicit. Therefore, when there is a slur, more people can participate in subordinating speech acts without worrying about backlash. For these reasons, slurs are suited to the collective maintenance of the social hierarchy. A large number of people can indicate their position voluntarily and safely, thereby participating in a declaration that ranks the targets as inferior.These features of slurs suggest that slurs are a conventional tool for a collective declaration that creates and maintains an unjust social hierarchy. Slurs are used by individuals at different times and in different places, so using a slur is a collective declaration, but not in the sense that people perform the declaration by consciously organizing themselves for the declaration. Rather, it is a collective declaration in the sense that people can do things together by indicating their commitment to a common goal. The declaration in question is similar to making a decision informally at a meeting. People can indicate their support for a proposal by performing a speech act that indicates their acceptance of the proposal. A simple movement like a nod or applause would be enough for them to perform a declaration together. Slurs play the same role when insofar as we understand society as a place where what should be normatively the case is constantly being contested by the members of the society. Those who use a slur indicate their approval of the proposal that the target of the slur should be ranked as lower than themselves. In this sense, using a slur in a speech act is similar to casting a vote in an informal decision-making process. By using a slur, an individual casts a vote and participates in","PeriodicalId":42609,"journal":{"name":"Pluralist","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2000,"publicationDate":"2023-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Casting a Vote for Subordination Using a Slur\",\"authors\":\"Duckkyun Lee\",\"doi\":\"10.5406/19446489.18.3.03\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"In this paper, I develop an account of slurs focusing on their two underappreciated features. The first underappreciated feature is what I call their “communal nature.” Slurs are communal. The meaning of a slur depends on the existence of a significant number of people who are bigoted against the target. When this condition is not satisfied, a slur loses its power to offend. This can be seen when we consider how philosophers choose examples of slurs to avoid offending people. For example, Williamson, in his essay “Reference, Inference and the Semantics of Pejoratives,” uses a slur for Germans as his main example. What makes the slur for Germans a safe example to use is the fact that there is no widespread bigotry against Germans in any Anglophone country. Had there been strong enmity between Germans and the people in the Anglophone countries, even if Williamson had chosen an outdated slur, his example would not have been such a safe choice. Slurs are words that bigots use to offend and harm the people they are bigoted against. When there are no bigots, neither are there slurs.The focus on the communal nature of slurs leads to the second underappreciated feature of slurs. A bigot does not use a slur just to express his beliefs or feelings, but to subordinate his target. To subordinate others, a bigot needs to cooperate and coordinate with other bigots. In this paper, I will propose a mechanism for how slurs work as a tool for coordinating subordination. To account for the communal and subordinating nature of slurs, I turn to speech act theory and explain what kind of illocutionary act is performed when one uses a slur.1My proposal is to understand utterances made using a slur, or slurring,2 as an act of casting a vote for ranking the target as socially inferior. On this view, a slur is a conventional tool used to cast a vote demanding the subordination of its target. The considerations that motivate this view are as follows: First, the uses of a slur are the results of consciously choosing it over its neutral counterpart. By explicitly avoiding a neutral counterpart term, one can show their support for fellow bigots and the willingness to participate in whatever activity they do. Second, the point of using a slur does not seem to be exhausted by its role of expressing the bigot's negative beliefs about the target. We can see this when we consider that the way to fight a slur is to impose strict prohibitions against its use, not by objecting to the content of the slurring utterance. This can be better explained when we understand the slur as a conventional tool for the performance of a certain type of action, rather than a word that has distinctive descriptive content different from the descriptive content of its neutral counterpart. Finally, the point of some speech acts is not just expressing the state of the mind of the speaker. The point of some speech acts is to change what is the case in society. To make an utterance using a slur seems to fall into this latter category of speech acts. What would bigots be up to if they were not engaged in the project of creating a society where their target was inferior to them? This consideration suggests that making an utterance using a slur might fall into the kind of speech act Searle calls declaration (Taxonomy 361–68). As a declaration, slurring is an attempt to change society such that the target is subordinated.Insofar as an election is understood as a process within which people collectively decide on what should be the case in society by indicating their stance for or against a proposal, slurring can be understood as a casting of a vote in the election bigots’ proposal to subordinate their target. I argue that this account can better explain why a slur cannot function as a slur without there being a significant number of bigots, and how it is used to coordinate the bigots’ effort of subordinating their target.The paper proceeds in the following order. In section 2, I briefly delineate the target of my account. Among many different pejoratives, my account attempts to investigate the slurs that target not individuals with certain features, but groups as a whole, and slurs for which there are neutral counterpart terms. In section 3, I will explain in detail what I mean by the claim that slurs have a communal and subordinating nature and why I do not think the existing accounts give a satisfactory explanation of them. In section 4, I develop and justify my own proposal that slurs are a conventional tool to perform the illocutionary act of voting for subordination. Understanding slurring as an act of voting for subordination can give us a helpful insight into how the social hierarchy comes into existence; slurring satisfies important conditions to count as an act of voting; a typical strategy of fighting slurring also supports my proposal. Finally, in section 5, I will briefly show how my proposal can explain other important characteristics of slurs just as well as any other rivaling accounts. Especially, I will outline two important explanatory challenges: the projective behavior of slurs and our conflicting intuitions about the truth-value of sentences with a slur.Before developing my view, I want to make clear what I count as a slur. First, slurs are pejorative terms that target groups, not individuals. They target different kinds of groups: racial groups, religious groups, occupational groups, groups with certain sexual orientations, and so on. This distinguishes slurs from pejoratives targeting individuals. For example, words like “asshole” are not considered a slur since there is no socially recognized group associated with it. Second, slurs are pejoratives that are paired with a neutral counterpart. This distinguishes slurs from other group-targeting pejoratives that do not have a corresponding neutral counterpart. For example, “pimp” is a pejorative for a certain group of people, but since it lacks a neutral counterpart, I do not count it as a slur in this paper.Slurs are derogatory words. They are deeply offensive. What is it about them that makes their use so offensive? To answer this question, let's start with some obvious features of slurs. Slurs are words that are used by bigots. What interests do slurs serve for them? Ultimately, what makes a bigot a bigot is that he has an interest in making life harder for the people he is bigoted against. A slur might have various uses, but one thing that is certain is that it is a means for a bigot to achieve this goal. Slurs contribute to the achievement of this goal by helping bigots recognize each other and coordinate with each other. When a bigot uses a slur, he knows very well that there are other slur users out there and that by using the slur, he is joining them. These features show that slurs are the words that bigots use to create a society, together with other bigots, where their target is subordinated.I believe that what I have said so far would be acceptable to most who work on slurs. However, the existing accounts of slurs that have been proposed so far do not yield a satisfactory explanation for the two features. The goal of this section is to show this and to motivate the need for an alternative account. Although there are numerous and varied accounts of slurs, one can categorize the existing accounts from the perspective of speech act theory, by looking at what kinds of speech act each account of slurs thinks can be performed with utterances containing slurs. For a succinct overview of the existing accounts, I will illustrate them using the following hypothetical conversation between Sam, Chris, and Alex.(Here and below, to avoid mentions of slurs, I will use the following notation system to talk about slurs. “S*” is a slur for a group. “G*” is a neutral counterpart term referring to the group that “S*” targets. Asterisks are used to differentiate slurs targeting different groups. “S*” and “S**” are two different slurs that target two different groups, G* and G**.)In this conversation, Sam answered Chris's question and gave her information about the new boss's group identity. Alex, in addition to answering Chris's question, asserted that the information Sam gave was incorrect and provided different information about the new boss's group identity. However, this description of the conversation above would be an extremely distorted description of what happened in the conversation. They did not merely exchange information about the new boss. By using slurs, they did something bad to the new boss, G*, and G**, and this warrants offense.3 All accounts of slurs seek to identify what it is that they did that warrants offense in addition to exchanging information about the new boss's group identity.According to the existing accounts, what they did in addition to the exchange of information largely fell into two categories. First, the offensiveness of their speech lies at the locutionary level. What Alex, Chris, and Sam did by using the slurs was a violation of a norm governing our choice of words when we produce meaningful utterances.4 It is not that their utterances with slurs have a special illocutionary force that warrants offense. The problem is that they violated the norm that prohibits the use of slurs. That is what makes their utterances so offensive, just as using a swear word in a formal address is offensive. The kind of speech act performed using a slur does not matter.Secondly, we can understand the offensiveness as coming from a specific illocutionary act that was performed using it. What warrants offense is not just the act of choosing a prohibited word, but what one does in using the prohibited word. Accounts that take this approach can again be divided roughly into three sub-classes depending on the kind of illocutionary act they identify as the act performed by using a slur. First, using a slur is an act of conveying some false, derogatory information about the target. Though the exact mechanism with which the derogatory information is conveyed varies from account to account,5 what they are doing in the conversation in addition to exchanging the information about the new boss's group identity is to convey the false information that members of G* and G** have some negative properties.6 Second, illocutionary acts performed using a slur are acts of getting the hearer to adopt an adversary attitude toward their targets.7 Finally, utterances of sentences containing a slur could be an act of expressing negative emotions against the target.8 By uttering “she was an S*,” Sam expressed her contempt for the new boss's group identity.Formulated in terms of the speech act theory framework, these approaches are not mutually exclusive, as one can perform multiple acts with a single utterance. So the accounts above should be understood as identifying the primary source of the offensiveness of slurs. Taken as such, each account has its own merits and shortcomings. However, what they share in common is their negligence of the two key features of slurs: their communal character and their role as a tool for subordination. No accounts suggested so far capture the fact that bigots use slurs only if they know that there are other fellow bigots using them, nor do they ask what it implies that they are using slurs together with other bigots. In what follows, I will elucidate these two features of slurs in detail and explain in what sense the existing accounts cannot satisfactorily explicate them.Let us consider the communal nature first. All linguistic expressions depend on the linguistic convention, and they are communal to that extent. However, the communal nature of slurs goes beyond mere conventionality. Slurs are communal because the success of the offensive speech act performed by using a slur depends on the existence of a certain social group, that is, a large number of people who are bigoted against their targets.To see this, imagine an American who is extremely bigoted against the British people. She learns the slur for the British from a dictionary and starts using it to refer to them, intending her speech to be as offensive and scandalous as speech with other well-known slurs. However, contrary to her expectations, her speech act is hardly offensive, unlike a slur for African Americans. What explains the difference in the offensiveness is that, whereas there are many who are bigoted against African Americans, there is only a meager number of people who are bigoted against the British. Imagine this same American moved to Ireland. Her speech would be quite offensive, since antipathy against the British people is still strong in Ireland. Using the slur, she would be able to perform an offensive and scandalous speech act there. This shows that whatever speech act one performs using a slur, its success as an offensive speech act depends on the fact that there must be a significant number of fellow bigots in the society.The communal nature of a slur manifests itself not just in the way its offensiveness covaries with the bigotry against its target in a society. It also manifests itself in the way it is created. Someone who is extremely bigoted against a certain group of people might create a word to use as a slur for them. Further, somehow, everyone in her linguistic community knows the story about this new word. Yet this is not sufficient to make her use of the word offensive. So long as there is only one person who is bigoted against the group, her use of the word would strike people as eccentric rather than offensive. Only when there are sufficient people who share her bigotry and adopt her word can the word be used as a slur. Whatever she wants to do with the word, she cannot do it alone.These considerations show that for a bigot to use a slur successfully, that is, to perform whatever offensive speech act that is normally performed with a slur, there needs to be a group of fellow bigots using the slur. How could the existing accounts explain this fact? Among the two kinds of accounts classified above, the accounts that identify the offensive speech act performed with a slur as an illocutionary act are hard-pressed to explain this fact.Suppose slurs are offensive because they are used to convey some false and derogatory information about the target. In principle, then, one can always create a slur because one can create a word that encodes some false and derogatory information about some group. To those who are familiar with the word, the use of the word would be offensive, but its offensiveness would not depend on the existence of people who are bigoted against the same group. The same can be said about other kinds of speech acts that the existing account has identified with the slur. Anyone can create a new word to give an offensive order or to express one's negative emotional state. To perform the intended offensive speech act successfully, one needs to make sure that one's interlocutors become familiar with your lexicon. However, there need not be a large number of fellow bigots using the word. You can convey some information, give an order, or express your emotional state by making your intention known to your interlocutor.The account according to which the offensiveness of slurs comes from the fact that they are prohibited words better captures the communal aspect. If a slur is a prohibited word, a natural explanation for its prohibition is that there are many people who use the word in an offensive way. Otherwise, there would be no point in prohibiting it. However, this account does not explain why slurs are prohibited in the first place. There must be something offensive in what bigots do with the word, such that the targets need to prohibit it. Unless what bigots do with slurs is clarified, the prohibited word account cannot offer a satisfactory examination of slurs.Slurs are words that bigots use when they want their targets to be subordinated. This is not to say that individual bigots form the intention to subordinate the target whenever they use a slur. The psychological state of an individual user of a slur might differ from situation to situation. Someone might use a slur when he is annoyed by the presence of a member of a racial group he hates. He might use a slur at different times when he thinks that his bigoted beliefs about a racial group have been vindicated by the act of a member of the group. Regardless of the intention behind each token use of a slur, that slur contributes to the subordination of the targeted group. This is the reason why we treat slurs differently than swearing words in general.The key question is how a slur contributes to the subordination of its target. All the existing accounts of slurs can explain the relationship between the uses of slurs and subordination as a causal relationship. For example, if a slur has derogatory content about its target as part of its meaning, its use can convey that content to the audience, change the beliefs of the audience, and as a result, change how the audience treats the target group. According to this understanding, using a slur is not itself an act of subordinating the target. A bigot does something else, and the subordination of the target might or might not follow, depending on how downstream causal effects unfold. When I argue that slurs have a subordinating nature, what I mean is not merely that they can causally contribute to the subordination of their target; I also mean that the use of slurs is itself an act of subordination. Regardless of the intention behind the use of a slur, its use always constitutes an act of subordination. The following fact supports this understanding.There is a distinctive way in which we resist the use of slurs, which is to outrightly ban their use. This would not be the case if slurs were just causally responsible for subordination. When we hear someone using a slur, the only effective way of resisting it is to stop the person from using it. However, if subordination is just a causal effect of a slurring speech act, we should be able to do many more things to prevent the use of a slur from having subordination as its causal effect. For example, if a slur is a word that has derogatory implications about its target as its literal meaning, one could explicitly reject to endorse the proposition expressed with the slur, by saying something like “No, he is not an S* because he is charming, athletic, and smart.” However, this would be an absurd response to an utterance of a slur.Compare this with the case of the use of derogatory words that target people with certain (imaginary) characteristics. We can resist this use by arguing that the relevant characteristics do not exist at all or are not instantiated by the targets. For example, against the use of the S-word against a woman, we can say something like: “No, women are not promiscuous or unchaste. These are old-fashioned concepts that do not apply to anything.” This response is possible because the literal content of the S-word is causally responsible for the connection between its use and the subordination of women. That this kind of resistance to a slur is impossible shows that there is no literal content in slurs that is responsible for the subordination of their target.When we understand the use of slurs as constituting a distinctive kind of speech act whose illocutionary point is to subordinate its target, we don't have to look for the medium that is causally responsible for the connection between the use of a slur and subordination, and we can understand why the only effective way of resisting slurs is to ban their use outright. The key task is, then, to explain how an act of using certain words could be an act of subordination. Before developing my own account, I will make the notion of subordination clear. Once we have a clear understanding of what subordination consists of, we will be able to understand how an act of using certain words can be an act of subordination as well.Rae Langton develops an account of pornography in which pornography is understood as an illocutionary act of subordinating women. According to Langton, a speech act is an illocutionary act of subordination when it does one of the following things: unfairly ranking the target as having inferior worth, legitimizing discriminatory behaviors against the target, or unjustly depriving its target of some important rights or powers (304). “Blacks are not permitted to vote” uttered by a South African legislator during apartheid is an example of a subordinating speech act that deprives black people of political rights. Pornography might be a subordinating speech act if, by representing women as sexual objects, it ranks women as socially inferior to men or legitimizes treating women as such.Although Langton's purpose is not to develop an extensive account of subordinating speech acts, her account of subordinating speech acts and their application to pornographic speech acts is illuminating. First, she explores the possibility of attributing an illocutionary force to a speech act that looks drastically different from paradigmatic cases of speech acts with the illocutionary force in question. In her view, pornography is very different from such paradigmatic cases of speech acts of assigning rankings to people: it is not made with the explicit rules for who can assign rankings to whom under which conditions (Langton, “Speech Acts” 310). However, as Langton's work shows, this does not necessarily mean that pornography cannot be an act of ranking women as inferior. We can reasonably assume that the hierarchy between people and the authority to determine the relative ranks between people can exist outside highly organized social institutions (Langton, “Speech Acts” 312). In principle, an illocutionary act can appear to be completely different from paradigm cases of the same kind.Second, Langton offers a general strategy with which one can justify an ascription of an illocutionary force to a speech act regardless of its seeming difference from paradigm cases. According to Langton, one can justify an ascription of an illocutionary force to a speech act by asking three questions: First, whether the speech in question has satisfied some important felicity conditions to have the illocutionary force in question. Felicity conditions are conditions that an attempt to perform a speech act must meet for it to be successful. A common felicity condition for declarations is authority. For example, we cannot call a speech act of declaring a move in a game as a foul if the speaker does not meet important conditions for it that include being the appointed umpire of the game (see Austin 12–24); second, whether the hearer takes the speech to have the illocutionary force in question; third, whether the perlocutionary effect of the speech can be best explained by supposing that the speech has the illocutionary force. Using this strategy, she gives three reasons to consider pornography as a subordinating illocutionary act: First, pornographers, even if they are not held in high esteem in society, are authoritative for the men who “want to know which moves in the sexual game are legitimate” (Langton, “Speech Acts” 312). Second, many women take pornography to be subordinating; that is, many women take pornography to have the illocutionary force of subordination. Finally, that pornography has subordinating illocutionary force might be one reason why it has the perlocutionary effect of making men more likely to see women as sexual objects. These reasons are all fallible, yet they support the ascription of the subordinating illocutionary force to pornography.We can apply the same strategy to speech acts made with a slur. They do not seem to be an act of subordination. A person can make an order, an assertion, or a question using a slur, and how can they be all understood as acts of subordinating their target? We can apply Langton's formulas to answer this question. First, does speech made with a slur satisfy the felicity conditions to have the illocutionary force of subordinating its target? Second, do the hearers take the speech to have the illocutionary force of subordination? Third, is the perlocutionary effect of speech made with a slur best explained by supposing that it has the illocutionary force of subordination? I suggest that the answers to these three questions are all positive.Let me start with the third question. Is there a perlocutionary effect of speech with a slur that can be better explained by understanding it as an act of ranking the target as inferior? The phenomenon that supports my proposal is the very existence and persistence of the social hierarchy between groups within a society. As Searle points out, what is distinctive about social reality is that it is created and maintained by our linguistic activity.9 When successful, what is said in a declaration becomes the case. “Blacks are not permitted to vote” uttered by a South African legislator during apartheid makes it the case that blacks are not permitted to vote. On the contrary, “Blacks are prone to violence” uttered by the same legislator cannot make it the case that blacks are prone to violence, regardless of how many people accept what has been asserted. The relative rank of a social group within a social hierarchy is also what is determined by declarations. When a declaration about the rank of a group within a social hierarchy is successful, it becomes part of the social reality that the group takes up that position in the social hierarchy. The relative rank of groups in a society can be determined in various ways, for example, by a King's order. However, the ranks of each group can persist as long as the people in the society continue to collectively represent them as having these ranks. The group has the lower social rank only if the majority in a society collectively represents that group as having a lower social rank than they have. However, there is no natural base in response to which people form the belief that different groups have different ranks that they have. The hierarchy of a given society is based on its people representing the society as having that social hierarchy. Since there is no natural base for that representation, the representation needs to be reproduced again and again. That is, the fact that there is an unjust social hierarchy in our society that is determined by one's race, gender, sexuality, and so on, indicates that the performances of declarations in which those who are subordinated are represented as inferior are made repeatedly. Furthermore, since social hierarchy cannot be created and maintained without the collaboration of the majority of society, such declarations need to be made by the majority of the members of the society.Slurs have the characteristics that make them an apt tool for such subordinating declarations for at least three reasons. First, slurs are paired with their neutral counterparts. Therefore, a slur can function as a linguistic tag that is attached to its target as a marker for an inferior social position. Second, the uses of a slur are the result of an intentional choice over its neutral counterpart. For this reason, a slur is an efficient tool for indicating one's position. Since the knowledge of the meaning of a slur includes the knowledge about the kind of people who use the slur, a conscious choice to use a slur indicates that one has a similar position to that of the slur users. Furthermore, since slurs can be used anytime when there is a need to refer to the target group, one can indicate one's position anytime without interrupting the flow of the conversation. Finally, one can indicate one's position using a slur without being fully explicit about what it is that one is committed to. As pointed out by many who work on slurs,10 it is notoriously difficult to specify what descriptive content a slur has. However, if a slur is a tool for indicating one's support for the existing social hierarchy, it is no wonder that there seems to be no fixed descriptive content with a slur. One indicates one's position by using the same word as bigots do. At the same time, one can secure plausible deniability by not making one's position explicit. Therefore, when there is a slur, more people can participate in subordinating speech acts without worrying about backlash. For these reasons, slurs are suited to the collective maintenance of the social hierarchy. A large number of people can indicate their position voluntarily and safely, thereby participating in a declaration that ranks the targets as inferior.These features of slurs suggest that slurs are a conventional tool for a collective declaration that creates and maintains an unjust social hierarchy. Slurs are used by individuals at different times and in different places, so using a slur is a collective declaration, but not in the sense that people perform the declaration by consciously organizing themselves for the declaration. Rather, it is a collective declaration in the sense that people can do things together by indicating their commitment to a common goal. The declaration in question is similar to making a decision informally at a meeting. People can indicate their support for a proposal by performing a speech act that indicates their acceptance of the proposal. A simple movement like a nod or applause would be enough for them to perform a declaration together. Slurs play the same role when insofar as we understand society as a place where what should be normatively the case is constantly being contested by the members of the society. Those who use a slur indicate their approval of the proposal that the target of the slur should be ranked as lower than themselves. In this sense, using a slur in a speech act is similar to casting a vote in an informal decision-making process. By using a slur, an individual casts a vote and participates in\",\"PeriodicalId\":42609,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Pluralist\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.2000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-10-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Pluralist\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.5406/19446489.18.3.03\",\"RegionNum\":4,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"0\",\"JCRName\":\"PHILOSOPHY\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Pluralist","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.5406/19446489.18.3.03","RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

在本文中,我开发了一个关于诽谤的帐户,重点关注它们的两个未被重视的特征。第一个未被重视的特点是我称之为“公共性质”。辱骂是公共的。诽谤的意义取决于存在相当数量的人对目标抱有偏见。当这个条件不满足时,诽谤就失去了冒犯的力量。当我们考虑哲学家如何选择诽谤的例子来避免冒犯别人时,就可以看到这一点。例如,威廉姆森在他的文章“参考,推理和贬义词的语义”中,使用了对德国人的诽谤作为他的主要例子。对德国人的诽谤之所以是一个安全的例子,是因为在任何英语国家都没有对德国人的普遍偏见。如果德国人和英语国家的人民之间存在强烈的敌意,即使威廉姆森选择了一个过时的诽谤,他的榜样也不会是这样一个安全的选择。污言秽语是偏执狂用来冒犯和伤害他们所反对的人的词语。没有偏执狂,也就没有诽谤。对辱骂的公共性质的关注导致了辱骂的第二个未被重视的特征。偏执狂不只是为了表达自己的信仰或感受而使用诽谤,而是为了使他的目标屈从。为了使他人服从,偏执者需要与其他偏执者合作和协调。在本文中,我将提出一种机制,如何诽谤工作作为协调下属的工具。为了解释辱骂的共同性和从属性,我转向言语行为理论,并解释当一个人使用辱骂时,会执行什么样的言外行为。我的建议是将使用侮辱性言语或含糊不清的话语理解为一种投票行为,将目标置于社会地位低下的地位。根据这种观点,诽谤是用来投票要求其目标服从的常规工具。促使这一观点的考虑如下:首先,使用诽谤是有意识地选择它而不是其中性对立物的结果。通过明确地避免使用中立的对应词,人们可以表明他们对其他偏执狂的支持,并愿意参与他们所做的任何活动。其次,使用诽谤的意义似乎并没有因为它表达偏执狂对目标的负面信念而耗尽。当我们考虑到打击诽谤的方式是严格禁止使用它,而不是反对诽谤言论的内容时,我们就可以看到这一点。当我们将诽谤理解为执行某种行为的常规工具,而不是具有与其中性对应的描述性内容不同的独特描述性内容的单词时,可以更好地解释这一点。最后,一些言语行为的目的不仅仅是表达说话者的思想状态。一些言语行为的目的是改变社会现状。用污语说话似乎属于后一种言语行为。如果偏执狂不参与创造一个他们的目标不如他们的社会的计划,他们会做什么呢?这一考虑表明,使用诽谤的话语可能属于塞尔称之为声明的言语行为(分类法361-68)。作为一种宣言,模糊化是一种改变社会的尝试,使目标处于从属地位。如果选举被理解为一个过程,在这个过程中,人们通过表明他们支持或反对一项提案的立场,集体决定社会应该发生什么,那么诽谤可以被理解为对选举偏执者的提议投下一票,以使他们的目标服从。我认为,这种说法可以更好地解释为什么如果没有大量的偏执狂,诽谤就不能成为诽谤,以及它是如何被用来协调偏执狂使其目标服从的努力的。论文按以下顺序进行。在第2节中,我简要地描述了我的帐户的目标。在许多不同的贬义词中,我的描述试图调查那些不是针对具有某些特征的个人,而是针对整体群体的诽谤,以及那些有中立对应术语的诽谤。在第3节中,我将详细解释我所说的诽谤具有共同性和从属性的说法是什么意思,以及为什么我认为现有的说法没有给出令人满意的解释。在第4节中,我发展并证明了我自己的建议,即诽谤是执行投票服从的言外行为的传统工具。把含糊不清理解为一种对从属地位的投票行为,可以帮助我们了解社会等级制度是如何形成的;含糊其辞符合重要条件,可以算作投票行为;一个典型的对抗口齿不清的策略也支持我的建议。 最后,在第5节中,我将简要展示我的建议如何能够解释slurs的其他重要特征,就像任何其他竞争账户一样。特别是,我将概述两个重要的解释性挑战:污语的投射行为和我们对带有污语的句子的真值的相互冲突的直觉。在阐述我的观点之前,我想澄清一下我认为什么是诽谤。首先,slurs是针对群体而非个人的贬义词。他们针对不同的群体:种族群体、宗教群体、职业群体、有特定性取向的群体等等。这区分了诽谤和针对个人的贬义词。例如,像“混蛋”这样的词不被认为是诽谤,因为没有社会认可的群体与之相关。其次,slurs是与中性对应词搭配的贬义词。这区别于其他没有相应的中性对应物的群体目标贬义词。例如,“皮条客”是对特定人群的贬义,但由于它缺乏一个中立的对应词,所以我在本文中不将其视为诽谤。Slurs是贬义词。他们非常无礼。是什么让它们的使用如此令人反感?为了回答这个问题,让我们从slurs的一些明显特征开始。污言秽语是偏执狂用的词。诽谤对他们有什么好处?最终,使偏执者成为偏执者的原因是,他有兴趣让他所偏执的人的生活更加艰难。诽谤可能有各种各样的用途,但有一点是肯定的,那就是它是偏执狂实现这一目标的一种手段。诽谤有助于实现这一目标,因为它帮助偏执狂相互认识并相互协调。当一个偏执狂使用侮辱性言论时,他非常清楚还有其他使用侮辱性言论的人,而且通过使用侮辱性言论,他也加入了他们的行列。这些特征表明,污言秽语是偏执狂与其他偏执狂一起创造一个社会的词语,在这个社会中,他们的目标是从属的。我相信,到目前为止,我所说的对于大多数从事诽谤工作的人来说是可以接受的。然而,到目前为止提出的关于诽谤的现有说法并没有对这两个特征给出令人满意的解释。本节的目的就是要说明这一点,并激发对替代帐户的需求。尽管对侮辱性言语的描述多种多样,但我们可以从言语行为理论的角度对现有的描述进行分类,看看每种侮辱性言语认为可以用包含侮辱性言语的话语进行什么样的言语行为。为了简明地概述现有帐户,我将使用Sam、Chris和Alex之间的以下假设对话来说明它们。(在这里和下面,为了避免提及诽谤,我将使用以下符号系统来谈论诽谤。“S*”是对一个群体的蔑称。“G*”是一个中立的对应术语,指的是“S*”所针对的群体。星号用于区分针对不同群体的诽谤。“S*”和“S**”是两种不同的诽谤,针对两个不同的群体,G*和G**。)在这段对话中,Sam回答了Chris的问题,并给了她关于新老板群体身份的信息。Alex除了回答Chris的问题外,还断言Sam提供的信息不正确,并提供了新老板的团体身份的不同信息。然而,上述对对话的描述是对对话中发生的事情的极度扭曲的描述。他们不仅交换了关于新老板的信息。通过使用污言秽语,他们对新老板做了一些不好的事情,G**和G**,这应该被冒犯除了交换有关新老板的团体身份的信息外,所有关于诽谤的描述都试图找出他们做了什么值得冒犯的事情。根据现有的说法,他们除了交换情报外,所做的事情主要分为两类。首先,他们言语的冒犯性在于言语层面。亚历克斯、克里斯和山姆使用侮辱性词语的行为违反了我们在表达有意义的话语时选择词语的准则这并不是说他们的侮辱性话语有一种特殊的非言语力量,足以引起冒犯。问题是,他们违反了禁止使用诽谤的规范。这就是为什么他们的话语如此令人反感,就像在正式讲话中使用脏话一样令人反感。使用侮辱性语言的言语行为并不重要。其次,我们可以将冒犯性理解为来自使用它进行的特定的言外行为。构成冒犯的不仅仅是选择禁忌词的行为,还有使用禁忌词的行为。 采用这种方法的叙述可以再次大致分为三个子类,这取决于他们认为使用诽谤进行的行为是哪种言外行为。首先,使用诽谤是一种传递关于目标的一些虚假、贬损信息的行为。尽管每个人传达贬谤信息的确切机制各不相同,但他们在谈话中除了交换有关新老板群体身份的信息外,还在传递G*和G**成员具有某些负面特性的错误信息第二,使用诽谤进行的言外行为是使听者对其目标采取敌对态度的行为最后,含有侮辱性的句子的说出可能是一种对目标表达负面情绪的行为通过说出“she was a S*”,Sam表达了她对新老板群体身份的蔑视。根据言语行为理论框架,这些方法并不是相互排斥的,因为一个人可以用一个话语来执行多个行为。因此,上述描述应被理解为识别侮辱性言论的主要来源。这样看来,每一种说法都有自己的优点和缺点。然而,他们的共同之处在于他们忽视了诽谤的两个关键特征:它们的共性和它们作为从属工具的作用。到目前为止,还没有人提出这样一个事实,即偏执狂只有在知道有其他偏执狂同伴在使用它们时才会使用侮辱性语言,他们也不会问自己与其他偏执狂一起使用侮辱性语言意味着什么。在下文中,我将详细阐明诽谤的这两个特征,并解释现有的说法在什么意义上不能令人满意地解释它们。让我们先考虑公共性质。所有的语言表达都依赖于语言惯例,它们在某种程度上是共同的。然而,侮辱性的公共性质不仅仅是传统。辱骂是群体性的,因为使用辱骂进行的攻击性言语行为的成功取决于一定社会群体的存在,即大量对其目标抱有偏见的人。为了理解这一点,想象一下一个对英国人民极端偏执的美国人。她从字典中了解到英国人的侮辱性用语,并开始用它来指代他们,打算让她的讲话像其他众所周知的侮辱性用语一样具有冒犯性和诽谤性。然而,与她的期望相反,她的言论行为几乎没有冒犯性,不像对非洲裔美国人的诽谤。这种冒犯性的不同之处在于,尽管有很多人对非裔美国人抱有偏见,但对英国人抱有偏见的人却很少。想象一下,同样是这个美国人搬到了爱尔兰。她的讲话会很无礼,因为爱尔兰人对英国人的反感仍然很强烈。利用这一侮辱性言论,她可以在那里做出令人反感和诽谤性的言论。这表明,无论一个人使用侮辱性语言进行何种言语行为,其作为攻击性言语行为的成功取决于社会中必须有相当数量的偏执者。诽谤的公共性质不仅表现在它的攻击性与社会中对其目标的偏见相一致。它也表现在它被创造的方式上。对某一群体极端偏执的人可能会创造一个词来诋毁他们。此外,不知何故,她的语言社区里的每个人都知道这个新词的故事。然而,这并不足以使她使用“冒犯”这个词。只要只有一个人对这个群体抱有偏见,她使用这个词就会让人觉得古怪,而不是无礼。只有当有足够多的人认同她的偏执并接受她的话时,这个词才能被用作诽谤。无论她想用这个世界做什么,她都无法独自完成。这些考虑表明,对于一个偏执者来说,要成功地使用诽谤,也就是说,要执行任何通常使用诽谤进行的攻击性言语行为,需要有一群偏执者使用诽谤。现存的账目如何解释这一事实呢?在上述分类的两种说法中,将侮辱性言语行为认定为言外行为的说法很难解释这一事实。假设诽谤是冒犯性的,因为它们被用来传达一些关于目标的虚假和贬损的信息。因此,原则上,一个人总是可以创造一个诽谤,因为一个人可以创造一个包含一些关于某个群体的虚假和贬损信息的词。对于那些熟悉这个词的人来说,使用这个词是令人反感的,但它的令人反感并不取决于对同一群体有偏见的人的存在。 同样的情况也适用于其他类型的言论行为,这些行为已经被现有的账户认定为诽谤。任何人都可以创造新词来表达冒犯性的命令或表达自己的消极情绪状态。为了成功地进行有意的冒犯性言语行为,你需要确保你的对话者熟悉你的词汇。然而,不一定会有大量的偏执者使用这个词。你可以通过让对话者知道你的意图来传达一些信息、下达命令或表达你的情绪状态。根据这种说法,辱骂的冒犯性来自于它们是被禁止的事实,这更好地抓住了公共方面。如果一个侮辱性的词是被禁止使用的,一个自然的解释是,有很多人用侮辱性的方式使用这个词。否则,禁止它就没有意义了。然而,这个说法并没有解释为什么诽谤首先是被禁止的。偏执狂对这个词的使用一定有冒犯之处,因此目标需要禁止它。除非偏执狂对污言秽语做了什么澄清,否则禁词账户无法提供令人满意的污言秽语检查。当偏执狂想让他们的目标臣服时,他们就会使用污言秽语。这并不是说,每当偏执狂使用诽谤时,他们就会形成使目标服从的意图。使用侮辱性语言的个人的心理状态可能因情况而异。当一个人对他所憎恨的种族群体成员的出现感到恼火时,他可能会使用slur。当他认为他对一个种族群体的偏见被该群体成员的行为证明是正确的时候,他可能会在不同的时候使用侮辱性的语言。无论每次象征性地使用诽谤背后的意图如何,这种诽谤都有助于目标群体的从属地位。这就是为什么我们把污言秽语和一般的脏话区别对待的原因。关键的问题是,诽谤是如何使其目标屈从的。现有的所有关于侮辱性言语的说法都可以将侮辱性言语的使用与从属关系解释为一种因果关系。例如,如果一个诽谤包含贬损其目标的内容作为其含义的一部分,那么它的使用可以将该内容传达给受众,改变受众的信念,从而改变受众对待目标群体的方式。根据这一理解,使用诽谤本身并不是一种使目标服从的行为。偏执狂做了其他事情,目标的从属关系可能会或可能不会随之发生,这取决于下游因果关系如何展开。当我说污言秽语具有从属性质时,我的意思不仅仅是它们可以导致目标的从属;我还想说,使用诽谤本身就是一种从属行为。不管使用诽谤背后的意图如何,它的使用总是构成一种从属行为。以下事实支持这种理解。我们有一种独特的方式来抵制诽谤的使用,那就是直接禁止使用。如果诽谤只是造成从属关系的因果责任,情况就不会如此了。当我们听到有人使用诽谤时,唯一有效的抵抗方法就是阻止这个人使用它。然而,如果从属关系只是一个含糊不清的言语行为的因果效应,我们应该能够做更多的事情来防止使用一个含糊不清的行为将从属关系作为其因果效应。例如,如果一个词的字面意思是贬损它的目标,那么一个人可以明确地拒绝认可这个词所表达的命题,比如说“不,他不是S*,因为他很有魅力、运动能力强、聪明。”然而,这将是一个荒谬的回应一个诽谤的话语。将这种情况与针对具有某些(想象的)特征的人使用贬义词的情况进行比较。我们可以通过争辩相关特征根本不存在或者目标没有实例化来抵制这种使用。例如,反对对女人使用淫乱的词,我们可以这样说:“不,女人不是滥交或不贞洁。这些都是过时的概念,不适用于任何事情。”这种反应是可能的,因为“s”这个词的字面内容与它的使用和女性从属地位之间的联系有因果关系。这种对诽谤的抵抗是不可能的,这表明诽谤中没有文字内容对其目标的从属地位负责。 当我们理解诽谤的使用构成了一种独特的言语行为,其言外之意是使其目标服从时,我们就不必去寻找导致使用诽谤和服从之间联系的媒介,我们就能理解为什么抵制诽谤的唯一有效方法是彻底禁止使用它们。因此,关键的任务是解释使用某些词语的行为是如何成为从属行为的。在发展我自己的账户之前,我要澄清从属关系的概念。一旦我们清楚地了解了从属的构成,我们就能理解使用某些词语的行为是如何成为从属的行为的。雷·兰顿发展了一种关于色情的描述,在这种描述中,色情被理解为一种从属女性的非言语行为。根据兰顿的观点,言语行为是一种从属的言外行为,当言语行为有以下行为之一时:不公正地将目标定为价值较低的人,使针对目标的歧视行为合法化,或不公正地剥夺目标的某些重要权利或权力(304)。在种族隔离时期,一位南非议员说的“黑人不允许投票”就是剥夺黑人政治权利的从属言论行为的例子。色情作品可能是一种从属的言语行为,如果通过将女性描绘成性对象,它将女性在社会上置于男性之下,或者将女性视为这种行为合法化。虽然兰顿的目的不是对从属言语行为进行广泛的描述,但她对从属言语行为及其在色情言语行为中的应用的描述是有启发性的。首先,她探讨了将言外力量归因于言语行为的可能性,这种行为与具有言外力量的言语行为的范例案例截然不同。在她看来,色情作品与给人们分配排名的言语行为的典型案例非常不同:它没有明确的规则来规定谁可以在什么条件下给谁分配排名(兰顿,“言语行为”310)。然而,正如兰顿的研究表明的那样,这并不一定意味着色情作品不能是一种将女性置于低人一等地位的行为。我们可以合理地假设,人与人之间的等级和决定人与人之间相对等级的权威可以存在于高度组织化的社会机构之外(兰顿,“言语行为”312)。原则上,言外行为可以表现为完全不同于同类范例案例。其次,兰顿提供了一种一般策略,人们可以用它来证明将一种言外力量归因于言语行为,而不管它与范式案例的表面差异。根据兰顿的观点,人们可以通过提出三个问题来证明将言外力量归于言语行为的正当性:首先,所讨论的言语是否满足了产生所讨论的言外力量的一些重要的幸福条件。幸福条件是试图执行言语行为必须满足的条件才能成功。声明的一个常见的幸福条件是权威性。例如,如果说话者不符合重要条件(包括作为游戏的指定裁判员),我们就不能将宣布游戏中的一个移动的言语行为称为犯规;第二,听者是否认为言语有言外之力;第三,假设言语具有言外力量,是否可以最好地解释言语的言外效果。利用这一策略,她给出了三个理由,认为色情是一种从属的言外行为:首先,色情工作者,即使他们在社会上不受高度尊重,对于那些“想知道性游戏中哪些动作是合法的”的男人来说是权威的(兰顿,“言语行为”312)。第二,许多女性认为色情是从属的;也就是说,许多女性认为色情作品具有从属的言外之力。最后,色情作品具有从属的言外力量,这可能是它具有言外效应的原因之一,它使男性更有可能将女性视为性对象。这些理由都是站不住脚的,但它们都支持把非言性力量归于色情。我们可以将同样的策略应用于带有诽谤的言语行为。这似乎不是一种服从行为。一个人可以用诽谤来发出命令、断言或提出问题,而这些又怎么能被理解为使目标服从的行为呢?我们可以用兰顿公式来回答这个问题。 首先,侮辱性言语是否满足具有使其目标服从的言外力量的适当条件?第二,听者是否认为言语具有从属的言外之力?第三,假设带有诽谤的言语具有从属的言外力量,是否能最好地解释其言外效果?我认为这三个问题的答案都是肯定的。让我从第三个问题开始。是否有一种带有诽谤的言语的过言效应,可以通过将其理解为一种将目标置于低贱地位的行为来更好地解释?支持我的建议的现象是社会中群体之间的社会等级的存在和持续。正如塞尔所指出的,社会现实的独特之处在于它是由我们的语言活动创造和维持的如果成功,则声明中所说的内容将成为实际情况。在种族隔离时期,一位南非立法者说过“黑人不被允许投票”,说明黑人不被允许投票。相反,同一位立法者所说的“黑人有暴力倾向”并不能证明黑人有暴力倾向,不管有多少人接受这种说法。一个社会群体在社会等级制度中的相对地位也是由宣言决定的。当关于一个群体在社会等级中的地位的声明成功时,它就成为社会现实的一部分,即该群体在社会等级中占据了那个位置。社会中各群体的相对等级可以通过各种方式来确定,例如,通过国王的命令。然而,只要社会上的人们继续集体代表他们拥有这些等级,每个群体的等级就可以持续存在。只有当一个社会中的大多数人集体认为这个群体的社会地位比他们低时,这个群体的社会地位才会更低。然而,人们相信不同的群体有不同的等级,并没有自然的基础。一个社会的等级制度是建立在代表这个社会的人的基础上的。由于这种表现没有自然基础,所以这种表现需要一次又一次地复制。也就是说,在我们的社会中存在着由种族、性别、性取向等决定的不公正的社会等级制度,这一事实表明,那些被从属的人被代表为劣等人的宣言的表现是反复出现的。此外,由于没有社会大多数人的合作就不能建立和维持社会等级制度,因此这种声明需要由社会大多数成员作出。污言秽语的特点使它们成为这种从属声明的合适工具,原因至少有三个。首先,污言秽语与中性词汇配对。因此,污言秽语可以作为一种语言标签,作为社会地位低下的标记,附着在其目标对象身上。其次,诽谤的使用是故意选择其中立对应的结果。因此,诽谤是表明自己立场的有效工具。由于对辱骂的含义的了解包括对使用辱骂的人的类型的了解,有意识地选择使用辱骂表明你与辱骂者的立场相似。此外,由于诽谤可以在任何时候使用,当需要提及目标群体时,一个人可以在任何时候表明自己的立场,而不会打断谈话的进程。最后,一个人可以用诽谤来表明自己的立场,而不必完全明确自己所承诺的是什么。正如许多研究诽谤的人所指出的那样,10众所周知,很难确定诽谤包含哪些描述性内容。然而,如果诽谤是一种表明对现有社会等级的支持的工具,那么似乎没有固定的描述性内容与诽谤就不足为奇了。一个人用与偏执狂相同的词来表明自己的立场。与此同时,一个人可以通过不明确自己的立场来获得合理的否认。因此,当出现诽谤时,更多的人可以参与从属言论行为,而不必担心反弹。由于这些原因,诽谤适合于社会等级的集体维护。大量的人可以自愿和安全地表明自己的立场,从而参与到将目标列为劣等的声明中来。污语的这些特征表明,污语是一种集体宣言的传统工具,它创造并维持了不公正的社会等级制度。 个体在不同的时间、不同的地点使用侮辱性言语,因此使用侮辱性言语是一种集体的声明,但并不是说人们通过有意识地组织自己来进行声明。相反,它是一种集体宣言,人们可以通过表明他们对共同目标的承诺来共同做事。该宣言类似于在非正式会议上作出决定。人们可以通过言语行为来表示他们对某项提议的支持,以表示他们接受该提议。一个简单的动作,比如点头或鼓掌,就足以让他们一起发表宣言。当我们把社会理解为一个应该是规范的情况不断被社会成员争论的地方时,诽谤也扮演着同样的角色。那些使用诽谤的人表示赞成将诽谤的目标排在比自己低的位置。从这个意义上说,在言语行为中使用诽谤类似于在非正式决策过程中投票。通过使用诽谤,个人可以投票并参与其中
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Casting a Vote for Subordination Using a Slur
In this paper, I develop an account of slurs focusing on their two underappreciated features. The first underappreciated feature is what I call their “communal nature.” Slurs are communal. The meaning of a slur depends on the existence of a significant number of people who are bigoted against the target. When this condition is not satisfied, a slur loses its power to offend. This can be seen when we consider how philosophers choose examples of slurs to avoid offending people. For example, Williamson, in his essay “Reference, Inference and the Semantics of Pejoratives,” uses a slur for Germans as his main example. What makes the slur for Germans a safe example to use is the fact that there is no widespread bigotry against Germans in any Anglophone country. Had there been strong enmity between Germans and the people in the Anglophone countries, even if Williamson had chosen an outdated slur, his example would not have been such a safe choice. Slurs are words that bigots use to offend and harm the people they are bigoted against. When there are no bigots, neither are there slurs.The focus on the communal nature of slurs leads to the second underappreciated feature of slurs. A bigot does not use a slur just to express his beliefs or feelings, but to subordinate his target. To subordinate others, a bigot needs to cooperate and coordinate with other bigots. In this paper, I will propose a mechanism for how slurs work as a tool for coordinating subordination. To account for the communal and subordinating nature of slurs, I turn to speech act theory and explain what kind of illocutionary act is performed when one uses a slur.1My proposal is to understand utterances made using a slur, or slurring,2 as an act of casting a vote for ranking the target as socially inferior. On this view, a slur is a conventional tool used to cast a vote demanding the subordination of its target. The considerations that motivate this view are as follows: First, the uses of a slur are the results of consciously choosing it over its neutral counterpart. By explicitly avoiding a neutral counterpart term, one can show their support for fellow bigots and the willingness to participate in whatever activity they do. Second, the point of using a slur does not seem to be exhausted by its role of expressing the bigot's negative beliefs about the target. We can see this when we consider that the way to fight a slur is to impose strict prohibitions against its use, not by objecting to the content of the slurring utterance. This can be better explained when we understand the slur as a conventional tool for the performance of a certain type of action, rather than a word that has distinctive descriptive content different from the descriptive content of its neutral counterpart. Finally, the point of some speech acts is not just expressing the state of the mind of the speaker. The point of some speech acts is to change what is the case in society. To make an utterance using a slur seems to fall into this latter category of speech acts. What would bigots be up to if they were not engaged in the project of creating a society where their target was inferior to them? This consideration suggests that making an utterance using a slur might fall into the kind of speech act Searle calls declaration (Taxonomy 361–68). As a declaration, slurring is an attempt to change society such that the target is subordinated.Insofar as an election is understood as a process within which people collectively decide on what should be the case in society by indicating their stance for or against a proposal, slurring can be understood as a casting of a vote in the election bigots’ proposal to subordinate their target. I argue that this account can better explain why a slur cannot function as a slur without there being a significant number of bigots, and how it is used to coordinate the bigots’ effort of subordinating their target.The paper proceeds in the following order. In section 2, I briefly delineate the target of my account. Among many different pejoratives, my account attempts to investigate the slurs that target not individuals with certain features, but groups as a whole, and slurs for which there are neutral counterpart terms. In section 3, I will explain in detail what I mean by the claim that slurs have a communal and subordinating nature and why I do not think the existing accounts give a satisfactory explanation of them. In section 4, I develop and justify my own proposal that slurs are a conventional tool to perform the illocutionary act of voting for subordination. Understanding slurring as an act of voting for subordination can give us a helpful insight into how the social hierarchy comes into existence; slurring satisfies important conditions to count as an act of voting; a typical strategy of fighting slurring also supports my proposal. Finally, in section 5, I will briefly show how my proposal can explain other important characteristics of slurs just as well as any other rivaling accounts. Especially, I will outline two important explanatory challenges: the projective behavior of slurs and our conflicting intuitions about the truth-value of sentences with a slur.Before developing my view, I want to make clear what I count as a slur. First, slurs are pejorative terms that target groups, not individuals. They target different kinds of groups: racial groups, religious groups, occupational groups, groups with certain sexual orientations, and so on. This distinguishes slurs from pejoratives targeting individuals. For example, words like “asshole” are not considered a slur since there is no socially recognized group associated with it. Second, slurs are pejoratives that are paired with a neutral counterpart. This distinguishes slurs from other group-targeting pejoratives that do not have a corresponding neutral counterpart. For example, “pimp” is a pejorative for a certain group of people, but since it lacks a neutral counterpart, I do not count it as a slur in this paper.Slurs are derogatory words. They are deeply offensive. What is it about them that makes their use so offensive? To answer this question, let's start with some obvious features of slurs. Slurs are words that are used by bigots. What interests do slurs serve for them? Ultimately, what makes a bigot a bigot is that he has an interest in making life harder for the people he is bigoted against. A slur might have various uses, but one thing that is certain is that it is a means for a bigot to achieve this goal. Slurs contribute to the achievement of this goal by helping bigots recognize each other and coordinate with each other. When a bigot uses a slur, he knows very well that there are other slur users out there and that by using the slur, he is joining them. These features show that slurs are the words that bigots use to create a society, together with other bigots, where their target is subordinated.I believe that what I have said so far would be acceptable to most who work on slurs. However, the existing accounts of slurs that have been proposed so far do not yield a satisfactory explanation for the two features. The goal of this section is to show this and to motivate the need for an alternative account. Although there are numerous and varied accounts of slurs, one can categorize the existing accounts from the perspective of speech act theory, by looking at what kinds of speech act each account of slurs thinks can be performed with utterances containing slurs. For a succinct overview of the existing accounts, I will illustrate them using the following hypothetical conversation between Sam, Chris, and Alex.(Here and below, to avoid mentions of slurs, I will use the following notation system to talk about slurs. “S*” is a slur for a group. “G*” is a neutral counterpart term referring to the group that “S*” targets. Asterisks are used to differentiate slurs targeting different groups. “S*” and “S**” are two different slurs that target two different groups, G* and G**.)In this conversation, Sam answered Chris's question and gave her information about the new boss's group identity. Alex, in addition to answering Chris's question, asserted that the information Sam gave was incorrect and provided different information about the new boss's group identity. However, this description of the conversation above would be an extremely distorted description of what happened in the conversation. They did not merely exchange information about the new boss. By using slurs, they did something bad to the new boss, G*, and G**, and this warrants offense.3 All accounts of slurs seek to identify what it is that they did that warrants offense in addition to exchanging information about the new boss's group identity.According to the existing accounts, what they did in addition to the exchange of information largely fell into two categories. First, the offensiveness of their speech lies at the locutionary level. What Alex, Chris, and Sam did by using the slurs was a violation of a norm governing our choice of words when we produce meaningful utterances.4 It is not that their utterances with slurs have a special illocutionary force that warrants offense. The problem is that they violated the norm that prohibits the use of slurs. That is what makes their utterances so offensive, just as using a swear word in a formal address is offensive. The kind of speech act performed using a slur does not matter.Secondly, we can understand the offensiveness as coming from a specific illocutionary act that was performed using it. What warrants offense is not just the act of choosing a prohibited word, but what one does in using the prohibited word. Accounts that take this approach can again be divided roughly into three sub-classes depending on the kind of illocutionary act they identify as the act performed by using a slur. First, using a slur is an act of conveying some false, derogatory information about the target. Though the exact mechanism with which the derogatory information is conveyed varies from account to account,5 what they are doing in the conversation in addition to exchanging the information about the new boss's group identity is to convey the false information that members of G* and G** have some negative properties.6 Second, illocutionary acts performed using a slur are acts of getting the hearer to adopt an adversary attitude toward their targets.7 Finally, utterances of sentences containing a slur could be an act of expressing negative emotions against the target.8 By uttering “she was an S*,” Sam expressed her contempt for the new boss's group identity.Formulated in terms of the speech act theory framework, these approaches are not mutually exclusive, as one can perform multiple acts with a single utterance. So the accounts above should be understood as identifying the primary source of the offensiveness of slurs. Taken as such, each account has its own merits and shortcomings. However, what they share in common is their negligence of the two key features of slurs: their communal character and their role as a tool for subordination. No accounts suggested so far capture the fact that bigots use slurs only if they know that there are other fellow bigots using them, nor do they ask what it implies that they are using slurs together with other bigots. In what follows, I will elucidate these two features of slurs in detail and explain in what sense the existing accounts cannot satisfactorily explicate them.Let us consider the communal nature first. All linguistic expressions depend on the linguistic convention, and they are communal to that extent. However, the communal nature of slurs goes beyond mere conventionality. Slurs are communal because the success of the offensive speech act performed by using a slur depends on the existence of a certain social group, that is, a large number of people who are bigoted against their targets.To see this, imagine an American who is extremely bigoted against the British people. She learns the slur for the British from a dictionary and starts using it to refer to them, intending her speech to be as offensive and scandalous as speech with other well-known slurs. However, contrary to her expectations, her speech act is hardly offensive, unlike a slur for African Americans. What explains the difference in the offensiveness is that, whereas there are many who are bigoted against African Americans, there is only a meager number of people who are bigoted against the British. Imagine this same American moved to Ireland. Her speech would be quite offensive, since antipathy against the British people is still strong in Ireland. Using the slur, she would be able to perform an offensive and scandalous speech act there. This shows that whatever speech act one performs using a slur, its success as an offensive speech act depends on the fact that there must be a significant number of fellow bigots in the society.The communal nature of a slur manifests itself not just in the way its offensiveness covaries with the bigotry against its target in a society. It also manifests itself in the way it is created. Someone who is extremely bigoted against a certain group of people might create a word to use as a slur for them. Further, somehow, everyone in her linguistic community knows the story about this new word. Yet this is not sufficient to make her use of the word offensive. So long as there is only one person who is bigoted against the group, her use of the word would strike people as eccentric rather than offensive. Only when there are sufficient people who share her bigotry and adopt her word can the word be used as a slur. Whatever she wants to do with the word, she cannot do it alone.These considerations show that for a bigot to use a slur successfully, that is, to perform whatever offensive speech act that is normally performed with a slur, there needs to be a group of fellow bigots using the slur. How could the existing accounts explain this fact? Among the two kinds of accounts classified above, the accounts that identify the offensive speech act performed with a slur as an illocutionary act are hard-pressed to explain this fact.Suppose slurs are offensive because they are used to convey some false and derogatory information about the target. In principle, then, one can always create a slur because one can create a word that encodes some false and derogatory information about some group. To those who are familiar with the word, the use of the word would be offensive, but its offensiveness would not depend on the existence of people who are bigoted against the same group. The same can be said about other kinds of speech acts that the existing account has identified with the slur. Anyone can create a new word to give an offensive order or to express one's negative emotional state. To perform the intended offensive speech act successfully, one needs to make sure that one's interlocutors become familiar with your lexicon. However, there need not be a large number of fellow bigots using the word. You can convey some information, give an order, or express your emotional state by making your intention known to your interlocutor.The account according to which the offensiveness of slurs comes from the fact that they are prohibited words better captures the communal aspect. If a slur is a prohibited word, a natural explanation for its prohibition is that there are many people who use the word in an offensive way. Otherwise, there would be no point in prohibiting it. However, this account does not explain why slurs are prohibited in the first place. There must be something offensive in what bigots do with the word, such that the targets need to prohibit it. Unless what bigots do with slurs is clarified, the prohibited word account cannot offer a satisfactory examination of slurs.Slurs are words that bigots use when they want their targets to be subordinated. This is not to say that individual bigots form the intention to subordinate the target whenever they use a slur. The psychological state of an individual user of a slur might differ from situation to situation. Someone might use a slur when he is annoyed by the presence of a member of a racial group he hates. He might use a slur at different times when he thinks that his bigoted beliefs about a racial group have been vindicated by the act of a member of the group. Regardless of the intention behind each token use of a slur, that slur contributes to the subordination of the targeted group. This is the reason why we treat slurs differently than swearing words in general.The key question is how a slur contributes to the subordination of its target. All the existing accounts of slurs can explain the relationship between the uses of slurs and subordination as a causal relationship. For example, if a slur has derogatory content about its target as part of its meaning, its use can convey that content to the audience, change the beliefs of the audience, and as a result, change how the audience treats the target group. According to this understanding, using a slur is not itself an act of subordinating the target. A bigot does something else, and the subordination of the target might or might not follow, depending on how downstream causal effects unfold. When I argue that slurs have a subordinating nature, what I mean is not merely that they can causally contribute to the subordination of their target; I also mean that the use of slurs is itself an act of subordination. Regardless of the intention behind the use of a slur, its use always constitutes an act of subordination. The following fact supports this understanding.There is a distinctive way in which we resist the use of slurs, which is to outrightly ban their use. This would not be the case if slurs were just causally responsible for subordination. When we hear someone using a slur, the only effective way of resisting it is to stop the person from using it. However, if subordination is just a causal effect of a slurring speech act, we should be able to do many more things to prevent the use of a slur from having subordination as its causal effect. For example, if a slur is a word that has derogatory implications about its target as its literal meaning, one could explicitly reject to endorse the proposition expressed with the slur, by saying something like “No, he is not an S* because he is charming, athletic, and smart.” However, this would be an absurd response to an utterance of a slur.Compare this with the case of the use of derogatory words that target people with certain (imaginary) characteristics. We can resist this use by arguing that the relevant characteristics do not exist at all or are not instantiated by the targets. For example, against the use of the S-word against a woman, we can say something like: “No, women are not promiscuous or unchaste. These are old-fashioned concepts that do not apply to anything.” This response is possible because the literal content of the S-word is causally responsible for the connection between its use and the subordination of women. That this kind of resistance to a slur is impossible shows that there is no literal content in slurs that is responsible for the subordination of their target.When we understand the use of slurs as constituting a distinctive kind of speech act whose illocutionary point is to subordinate its target, we don't have to look for the medium that is causally responsible for the connection between the use of a slur and subordination, and we can understand why the only effective way of resisting slurs is to ban their use outright. The key task is, then, to explain how an act of using certain words could be an act of subordination. Before developing my own account, I will make the notion of subordination clear. Once we have a clear understanding of what subordination consists of, we will be able to understand how an act of using certain words can be an act of subordination as well.Rae Langton develops an account of pornography in which pornography is understood as an illocutionary act of subordinating women. According to Langton, a speech act is an illocutionary act of subordination when it does one of the following things: unfairly ranking the target as having inferior worth, legitimizing discriminatory behaviors against the target, or unjustly depriving its target of some important rights or powers (304). “Blacks are not permitted to vote” uttered by a South African legislator during apartheid is an example of a subordinating speech act that deprives black people of political rights. Pornography might be a subordinating speech act if, by representing women as sexual objects, it ranks women as socially inferior to men or legitimizes treating women as such.Although Langton's purpose is not to develop an extensive account of subordinating speech acts, her account of subordinating speech acts and their application to pornographic speech acts is illuminating. First, she explores the possibility of attributing an illocutionary force to a speech act that looks drastically different from paradigmatic cases of speech acts with the illocutionary force in question. In her view, pornography is very different from such paradigmatic cases of speech acts of assigning rankings to people: it is not made with the explicit rules for who can assign rankings to whom under which conditions (Langton, “Speech Acts” 310). However, as Langton's work shows, this does not necessarily mean that pornography cannot be an act of ranking women as inferior. We can reasonably assume that the hierarchy between people and the authority to determine the relative ranks between people can exist outside highly organized social institutions (Langton, “Speech Acts” 312). In principle, an illocutionary act can appear to be completely different from paradigm cases of the same kind.Second, Langton offers a general strategy with which one can justify an ascription of an illocutionary force to a speech act regardless of its seeming difference from paradigm cases. According to Langton, one can justify an ascription of an illocutionary force to a speech act by asking three questions: First, whether the speech in question has satisfied some important felicity conditions to have the illocutionary force in question. Felicity conditions are conditions that an attempt to perform a speech act must meet for it to be successful. A common felicity condition for declarations is authority. For example, we cannot call a speech act of declaring a move in a game as a foul if the speaker does not meet important conditions for it that include being the appointed umpire of the game (see Austin 12–24); second, whether the hearer takes the speech to have the illocutionary force in question; third, whether the perlocutionary effect of the speech can be best explained by supposing that the speech has the illocutionary force. Using this strategy, she gives three reasons to consider pornography as a subordinating illocutionary act: First, pornographers, even if they are not held in high esteem in society, are authoritative for the men who “want to know which moves in the sexual game are legitimate” (Langton, “Speech Acts” 312). Second, many women take pornography to be subordinating; that is, many women take pornography to have the illocutionary force of subordination. Finally, that pornography has subordinating illocutionary force might be one reason why it has the perlocutionary effect of making men more likely to see women as sexual objects. These reasons are all fallible, yet they support the ascription of the subordinating illocutionary force to pornography.We can apply the same strategy to speech acts made with a slur. They do not seem to be an act of subordination. A person can make an order, an assertion, or a question using a slur, and how can they be all understood as acts of subordinating their target? We can apply Langton's formulas to answer this question. First, does speech made with a slur satisfy the felicity conditions to have the illocutionary force of subordinating its target? Second, do the hearers take the speech to have the illocutionary force of subordination? Third, is the perlocutionary effect of speech made with a slur best explained by supposing that it has the illocutionary force of subordination? I suggest that the answers to these three questions are all positive.Let me start with the third question. Is there a perlocutionary effect of speech with a slur that can be better explained by understanding it as an act of ranking the target as inferior? The phenomenon that supports my proposal is the very existence and persistence of the social hierarchy between groups within a society. As Searle points out, what is distinctive about social reality is that it is created and maintained by our linguistic activity.9 When successful, what is said in a declaration becomes the case. “Blacks are not permitted to vote” uttered by a South African legislator during apartheid makes it the case that blacks are not permitted to vote. On the contrary, “Blacks are prone to violence” uttered by the same legislator cannot make it the case that blacks are prone to violence, regardless of how many people accept what has been asserted. The relative rank of a social group within a social hierarchy is also what is determined by declarations. When a declaration about the rank of a group within a social hierarchy is successful, it becomes part of the social reality that the group takes up that position in the social hierarchy. The relative rank of groups in a society can be determined in various ways, for example, by a King's order. However, the ranks of each group can persist as long as the people in the society continue to collectively represent them as having these ranks. The group has the lower social rank only if the majority in a society collectively represents that group as having a lower social rank than they have. However, there is no natural base in response to which people form the belief that different groups have different ranks that they have. The hierarchy of a given society is based on its people representing the society as having that social hierarchy. Since there is no natural base for that representation, the representation needs to be reproduced again and again. That is, the fact that there is an unjust social hierarchy in our society that is determined by one's race, gender, sexuality, and so on, indicates that the performances of declarations in which those who are subordinated are represented as inferior are made repeatedly. Furthermore, since social hierarchy cannot be created and maintained without the collaboration of the majority of society, such declarations need to be made by the majority of the members of the society.Slurs have the characteristics that make them an apt tool for such subordinating declarations for at least three reasons. First, slurs are paired with their neutral counterparts. Therefore, a slur can function as a linguistic tag that is attached to its target as a marker for an inferior social position. Second, the uses of a slur are the result of an intentional choice over its neutral counterpart. For this reason, a slur is an efficient tool for indicating one's position. Since the knowledge of the meaning of a slur includes the knowledge about the kind of people who use the slur, a conscious choice to use a slur indicates that one has a similar position to that of the slur users. Furthermore, since slurs can be used anytime when there is a need to refer to the target group, one can indicate one's position anytime without interrupting the flow of the conversation. Finally, one can indicate one's position using a slur without being fully explicit about what it is that one is committed to. As pointed out by many who work on slurs,10 it is notoriously difficult to specify what descriptive content a slur has. However, if a slur is a tool for indicating one's support for the existing social hierarchy, it is no wonder that there seems to be no fixed descriptive content with a slur. One indicates one's position by using the same word as bigots do. At the same time, one can secure plausible deniability by not making one's position explicit. Therefore, when there is a slur, more people can participate in subordinating speech acts without worrying about backlash. For these reasons, slurs are suited to the collective maintenance of the social hierarchy. A large number of people can indicate their position voluntarily and safely, thereby participating in a declaration that ranks the targets as inferior.These features of slurs suggest that slurs are a conventional tool for a collective declaration that creates and maintains an unjust social hierarchy. Slurs are used by individuals at different times and in different places, so using a slur is a collective declaration, but not in the sense that people perform the declaration by consciously organizing themselves for the declaration. Rather, it is a collective declaration in the sense that people can do things together by indicating their commitment to a common goal. The declaration in question is similar to making a decision informally at a meeting. People can indicate their support for a proposal by performing a speech act that indicates their acceptance of the proposal. A simple movement like a nod or applause would be enough for them to perform a declaration together. Slurs play the same role when insofar as we understand society as a place where what should be normatively the case is constantly being contested by the members of the society. Those who use a slur indicate their approval of the proposal that the target of the slur should be ranked as lower than themselves. In this sense, using a slur in a speech act is similar to casting a vote in an informal decision-making process. By using a slur, an individual casts a vote and participates in
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
Pluralist
Pluralist PHILOSOPHY-
CiteScore
0.50
自引率
0.00%
发文量
39
期刊最新文献
Casting a Vote for Subordination Using a Slur Affective Foundation of Society in Nietzsche's Philosophy Philosophy and the Modern African American Freedom Struggle: A Freedom Gaze The Dramatization of Absolute Idealism: Gabriel Marcel and F. H. Bradley Collective Regret and Guilt and Heroic Agency: A Pro-Existential Approach
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1