重新审视生活工资:沃尔格林博姿联盟案例

IF 0.7 Q4 BUSINESS, FINANCE Journal of Applied Corporate Finance Pub Date : 2024-06-02 DOI:10.1111/jacf.12611
Tom Gosling
{"title":"重新审视生活工资:沃尔格林博姿联盟案例","authors":"Tom Gosling","doi":"10.1111/jacf.12611","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>In 2022, ShareAction, a well-known British activist responsible investment NGO, tabled a resolution at Sainsbury's one of the UK's largest supermarket chains, demanding that they become an accredited Living Wage employer. I wrote up the case in this journal a year ago in an article titled: “Lessons for ESG Activists: The Case of Sainsbury's and the Living Wage.” 1 That proposal was rejected by around five out of every six shareholders at the 2022 Sainsbury's AGM.</p><p>So, I was interested to see the investor response to a similar proposal making a similar demand filed by John Chevedden at the 2024 AGM of Walgreens Boots Alliance (WBA).2 The filing was supported by The Shareholder Commons and ShareAction. Were any of my lessons for ESG activists learned? And what should we make of the case made by the proposers?</p><p>On the face of it, this resolution turned out to be even less persuasive than the ShareAction proposal at Sainsbury's: fewer than one in ten of WBA's investors supported it.3 Set against this is the fact that ESG proposals have always tended to receive less support at US than European companies, and over the last 2 years even more so. So perhaps the support can be considered comparable, all things considered.</p><p>Did the proposal reflect any of the lessons that I proposed we learn from the Sainsbury's proposal? Were shareholders right to reject it? I will argue that the answers are “yes, at least in part,” to the first question—and “yes, though with regrets,” to the second.</p><p>How did the WBA proposal stack up against these?</p><p><b>The Business Case Needs to be Compelling and Made with Precision and Care</b>. Two years ago, I was quite critical of the business case put forward by ShareAction to support their proposal. It was very much framed in terms of the benefits to Sainsbury's of paying a living wage, but without compelling evidence to support the case. Indeed, most of the evidence ShareAction cited either was not applicable to the situation or even undermined its own case.4 They failed to demonstrate that paying higher wages than necessary in a competitive low margin business would help Sainsbury's be more successful.</p><p>There are <i>theoretical reasons</i> why higher wages can be more than offset by increased productivity, but it is not an automatic result, and the win-win scenario can be quite difficult to pull off. It is not clear that shareholders are better placed than company management to decide whether this can be done in the specific circumstances faced by the company. Indeed, if improving shareholder value was as easy as increasing wages, we would expect more management teams in the retail sector to follow this path, whereas only a small minority do.5</p><p>This line of argument is notably different from that set out in the Sainsbury's proposal. The proposers are explicitly acknowledging and accepting the possibility that paying living wages might damage WBA's financial returns. Their innovation is to contend that this sacrifice of returns will be more than offset by reduced inequality leading to higher economic growth and therefore improved returns on the investor's diversified portfolio overall.</p><p>Some readers will recognize this as an application of so-called <i>Universal Owner Theory</i> (UOT), which begins by observing that diversified shareholders end up owning what amounts to a slice of the whole economy. Therefore, externalities created by companies that harm the economy also harm the diversified investor's portfolio. This can justify the investor's efforts to influence those companies to address and limit the effects of such externalities. The costs associated with such efforts are proposed to be offset by the financial benefits from the reduced externalities that show up elsewhere in the portfolio.</p><p>An example helps to explain universal ownership theory, and how its magic is supposed to work.</p><p>To show how diversified share ownership in theory leads investors to address negative externalities in order to maximize portfolio returns, law scholar Madison Condon uses the example of an investor holding stakes in oil majors and food and beverage conglomerates. The former cause climate change, the latter suffer from it. If the costs to the food and beverage holdings exceed the profits made by the oil majors, the investor might conclude that the value-maximizing action at the portfolio level is to cut emissions at their oil holdings (by forcing production cuts) to preserve value in their food and beverage holdings.7</p><p>The important thing to note, however, is that UOT claims to be addressing social and environmental concerns <i>in order to</i> achieve the highest possible returns in the investor's portfolio overall. In this sense, it differs from the concept of shareholder welfare maximization described by, for example, Oliver Hart and Luigi Zingales.8 The concept of shareholder welfare (as opposed to value) begins by recognizing that shareholders have non-financial as well as strictly financial preferences, and that investor stewardship should take both of these into account, potentially trading one off against the other. But UOT is different in that it holds out the possibility that a diversified investors’ <i>financial</i> interests <i>at the portfolio level</i> can be <i>maximized</i> by managing systemic risks and addressing negative externalities created by companies within the portfolio.</p><p><b>UOT and the Problem of Inequality</b>. I have written extensively elsewhere about the problems that UOT arguments run into in practice when trying to respond to the specific case of climate change,9 and will just briefly summarize my arguments here. But I find at least four major practical difficulties with the UOT argument presented by Shareholder Commons in the case of Walgreens.</p><p>First, even if enactment of the resolution did reduce inequality, it is very difficult to prove that reducing inequality would indeed lead to higher diversified market returns. The Shareholder Commons cites papers highlighting the potential economic benefits of reduced inequality. While I'm personally sympathetic to the idea that <i>society</i> would benefit from finding ways to limit inequality, my review of the evidence for the Sainsbury's resolution suggested the difficulty of providing convincing (much less conclusive) evidence that <i>the economy</i> would be strengthened by investor efforts to impose such equality. And the evidence that <i>financial markets</i> would respond well to such efforts is even less persuasive.10 The negative relationship claimed by some researchers between inequality and economic growth over the ranges of inequality commonly seen in developed economies seems to be quite heavily disputed. Indeed, over the past two decades, it is the US stock market and economy that has spectacularly outperformed despite its own commonly cited inequality problem.11</p><p>Second, it is not even clear that introducing a living wage at WBA would indeed reduce income inequality in the United States. There are two possibilities. One is that, following Costco's example, WBA transitions onto a higher-wage, higher- productivity path and helps set a market benchmark for cashier and salesperson pay in the US market. Between them, the two companies employ around 450,000 staff in the United States, of which plausibly some 300,000 would benefit from a living wage commitment. This represents roughly 5% of the total US retail cashier and salesperson employment of around 6.2 million.12 The big prize would be if WBA's decision forced the behemoth that is Walmart (with its 1.6 million US employees) to adopt a living wage policy. But the other quite real possibility is that WBA simply ends up with a cost disadvantage compared with other retail competitors, loses market share, reduces employment, and makes no contribution to wider reduction in inequality. To be assured of success in its social mission, universal owners would have to be such a dominating presence among US (if not global) investors—and embrace WBA's resolution so completely—that all of WBA's major retail competitors felt compelled to follow suit.</p><p>Third, given that the proposers accept that adopting a living wage could reduce profits at WBA, they are asking directors at WBA to take an action that they would very likely view as inconsistent with their fiduciary duties, which are to the company and its shareholders as a whole. As Marcel Kahan and Ed Rock have described in detail, the single-firm focus of fiduciary duties makes it extremely difficult for directors to even contemplate an action that knowingly harms their company's competitive position and value to benefit other companies in an investor's portfolio, however convinced of this socially beneficial outcome.13 Of course, it might be argued that investors are simply encouraging WBA directors to take the “higher ground” path to value creation followed by Costco. But one might also question whether certain groups of shareholders are better placed than directors to judge whether this would in fact be successful in WBA's case?</p><p>Fourth, the prospect of institutional investors imposing their view of economic policy on companies through living wage policies looks dangerously close to the kind of political overreach that can be highly inflammatory, inviting the kind of backlash we've recently witnessed by the US political right. In my discussion of the Sainsbury's case, I argued that living wage policies were an odd fight for shareholders to pick given the very well-established infrastructure in the UK for setting minimum wages involving an independent Low Pay Commission—a body with both with a remarkably high level of cross-party support and a mandate to raise living wages as fast as possible consistent with maintaining economic growth and employment. The Commission's work has resulted in a statutory minimum wage that is actually quite close to the “real living wage.”14 Given the political reality of US “federalism,” the process of setting minimum wages in the United States is more fragmented with both federal and state minimum wages and a less clear mandate for how they are set. The Federal Minimum Wage is a clearly inadequate $7.25 per hour, and while most states have a higher minimum wage than this, many do not. And where they do, the shortfall compared with independently calculated living wages is generally much greater than in the United Kingdom.15 This strengthens the argument that in the United States the minimum wage setting process may not be functioning effectively. Many of us believe that higher worker wages would improve social welfare and that the economic costs of minimum wages have often been overstated by the economics profession. But this feels dangerously close to an argument about political priorities than one that is rigorously rooted in financial market valuations. The existence of minimum wage legislation does suggest that shareholders would need to step carefully to avoid being seen as imposing their political views on society outside the democratic process. This raises the bar for the strength of evidence required for shareholders to weigh in on this issue in their engagements with companies.</p><p>To sum up then, two high profile living wage proposals on either side of the Atlantic have failed to secure support of more than a small minority of shareholders. The fact that the WBA resolution achieved even less support than the one at Sainsbury's is at one level surprising because it avoided at least some of the problems I identified in the Sainsbury's case. Part of the explanation is the differing attitudes of US and European shareholders—differences that have only been amplified by the recent US culture wars around ESG. But another part is that the fundamental business case remains so unpersuasive (if not implausible). Indeed, the case based on Universal Owner Theory is probably even more speculative than one linked—like a plan to replicate Costco's success—to the prospects of a single retail company. There are simply too many uncertainties and potentially broken links in the chain of logic for many fiduciaries to convince themselves, in good faith, of the merits of the case. For this reason, and given the difficulty of finding conclusive evidence of the connection to portfolio returns, proposals are probably better framed as posing questions that give management the latitude or option—but not the obligation—to act. The focus on “outcomes” from stewardship has led to increasingly prescriptive engagement demands with demonstrable “results.” However, particularly in the environmental and social sphere, such forceful stewardship is likely to run into problems with fiduciary duty at every level: between the asset owner and their beneficiary; between the asset manager and the asset owner; and between the directors and the company. The reality is that it will be virtually impossible for shareholders to force directors to take actions that damage their companies’ prospects.</p><p>Few would discourage the prospect of seeing more Costcos—companies that appear able to combine high wages and high productivity. But perhaps we need to find a different route to get there. The idea of using shareholder resolutions to impose actions on recalcitrant managements seems to be running out of road across the ESG spectrum, and relying on questionable business cases doesn't seem to be helping. Some of this may be more effectively framed in terms of ethics. Even Milton Friedman proposed that in seeking to create as much shareholder value as possible, business should conform to the basic rules of society, including those embodied in ethical custom. And ethical customs evolve. For example, it has become increasingly accepted that business should be conducted while avoiding slavery in supply chains, even if that add to costs. By making it known to companies that they view decent treatment of human beings, including avoiding poverty wages, as an ethical norm, shareholders create the space for boards to make different decisions. But by attempting to achieve outcomes that impose burdens on, and reduce the competitiveness of, individual companies, based on rationales that only a few shareholders can in good faith subscribe to, resolutions of the type proposed by ShareAction and The Shareholder Commons are almost certain to understate the level of investor support for fair wage policies. At times, aiming for less is likely to achieve more.</p>","PeriodicalId":46789,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Applied Corporate Finance","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.7000,"publicationDate":"2024-06-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/jacf.12611","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Living wages revisited: The case of Walgreens Boots Alliance\",\"authors\":\"Tom Gosling\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/jacf.12611\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>In 2022, ShareAction, a well-known British activist responsible investment NGO, tabled a resolution at Sainsbury's one of the UK's largest supermarket chains, demanding that they become an accredited Living Wage employer. I wrote up the case in this journal a year ago in an article titled: “Lessons for ESG Activists: The Case of Sainsbury's and the Living Wage.” 1 That proposal was rejected by around five out of every six shareholders at the 2022 Sainsbury's AGM.</p><p>So, I was interested to see the investor response to a similar proposal making a similar demand filed by John Chevedden at the 2024 AGM of Walgreens Boots Alliance (WBA).2 The filing was supported by The Shareholder Commons and ShareAction. Were any of my lessons for ESG activists learned? And what should we make of the case made by the proposers?</p><p>On the face of it, this resolution turned out to be even less persuasive than the ShareAction proposal at Sainsbury's: fewer than one in ten of WBA's investors supported it.3 Set against this is the fact that ESG proposals have always tended to receive less support at US than European companies, and over the last 2 years even more so. So perhaps the support can be considered comparable, all things considered.</p><p>Did the proposal reflect any of the lessons that I proposed we learn from the Sainsbury's proposal? Were shareholders right to reject it? I will argue that the answers are “yes, at least in part,” to the first question—and “yes, though with regrets,” to the second.</p><p>How did the WBA proposal stack up against these?</p><p><b>The Business Case Needs to be Compelling and Made with Precision and Care</b>. Two years ago, I was quite critical of the business case put forward by ShareAction to support their proposal. It was very much framed in terms of the benefits to Sainsbury's of paying a living wage, but without compelling evidence to support the case. Indeed, most of the evidence ShareAction cited either was not applicable to the situation or even undermined its own case.4 They failed to demonstrate that paying higher wages than necessary in a competitive low margin business would help Sainsbury's be more successful.</p><p>There are <i>theoretical reasons</i> why higher wages can be more than offset by increased productivity, but it is not an automatic result, and the win-win scenario can be quite difficult to pull off. It is not clear that shareholders are better placed than company management to decide whether this can be done in the specific circumstances faced by the company. Indeed, if improving shareholder value was as easy as increasing wages, we would expect more management teams in the retail sector to follow this path, whereas only a small minority do.5</p><p>This line of argument is notably different from that set out in the Sainsbury's proposal. The proposers are explicitly acknowledging and accepting the possibility that paying living wages might damage WBA's financial returns. Their innovation is to contend that this sacrifice of returns will be more than offset by reduced inequality leading to higher economic growth and therefore improved returns on the investor's diversified portfolio overall.</p><p>Some readers will recognize this as an application of so-called <i>Universal Owner Theory</i> (UOT), which begins by observing that diversified shareholders end up owning what amounts to a slice of the whole economy. Therefore, externalities created by companies that harm the economy also harm the diversified investor's portfolio. This can justify the investor's efforts to influence those companies to address and limit the effects of such externalities. The costs associated with such efforts are proposed to be offset by the financial benefits from the reduced externalities that show up elsewhere in the portfolio.</p><p>An example helps to explain universal ownership theory, and how its magic is supposed to work.</p><p>To show how diversified share ownership in theory leads investors to address negative externalities in order to maximize portfolio returns, law scholar Madison Condon uses the example of an investor holding stakes in oil majors and food and beverage conglomerates. The former cause climate change, the latter suffer from it. If the costs to the food and beverage holdings exceed the profits made by the oil majors, the investor might conclude that the value-maximizing action at the portfolio level is to cut emissions at their oil holdings (by forcing production cuts) to preserve value in their food and beverage holdings.7</p><p>The important thing to note, however, is that UOT claims to be addressing social and environmental concerns <i>in order to</i> achieve the highest possible returns in the investor's portfolio overall. In this sense, it differs from the concept of shareholder welfare maximization described by, for example, Oliver Hart and Luigi Zingales.8 The concept of shareholder welfare (as opposed to value) begins by recognizing that shareholders have non-financial as well as strictly financial preferences, and that investor stewardship should take both of these into account, potentially trading one off against the other. But UOT is different in that it holds out the possibility that a diversified investors’ <i>financial</i> interests <i>at the portfolio level</i> can be <i>maximized</i> by managing systemic risks and addressing negative externalities created by companies within the portfolio.</p><p><b>UOT and the Problem of Inequality</b>. I have written extensively elsewhere about the problems that UOT arguments run into in practice when trying to respond to the specific case of climate change,9 and will just briefly summarize my arguments here. But I find at least four major practical difficulties with the UOT argument presented by Shareholder Commons in the case of Walgreens.</p><p>First, even if enactment of the resolution did reduce inequality, it is very difficult to prove that reducing inequality would indeed lead to higher diversified market returns. The Shareholder Commons cites papers highlighting the potential economic benefits of reduced inequality. While I'm personally sympathetic to the idea that <i>society</i> would benefit from finding ways to limit inequality, my review of the evidence for the Sainsbury's resolution suggested the difficulty of providing convincing (much less conclusive) evidence that <i>the economy</i> would be strengthened by investor efforts to impose such equality. And the evidence that <i>financial markets</i> would respond well to such efforts is even less persuasive.10 The negative relationship claimed by some researchers between inequality and economic growth over the ranges of inequality commonly seen in developed economies seems to be quite heavily disputed. Indeed, over the past two decades, it is the US stock market and economy that has spectacularly outperformed despite its own commonly cited inequality problem.11</p><p>Second, it is not even clear that introducing a living wage at WBA would indeed reduce income inequality in the United States. There are two possibilities. One is that, following Costco's example, WBA transitions onto a higher-wage, higher- productivity path and helps set a market benchmark for cashier and salesperson pay in the US market. Between them, the two companies employ around 450,000 staff in the United States, of which plausibly some 300,000 would benefit from a living wage commitment. This represents roughly 5% of the total US retail cashier and salesperson employment of around 6.2 million.12 The big prize would be if WBA's decision forced the behemoth that is Walmart (with its 1.6 million US employees) to adopt a living wage policy. But the other quite real possibility is that WBA simply ends up with a cost disadvantage compared with other retail competitors, loses market share, reduces employment, and makes no contribution to wider reduction in inequality. To be assured of success in its social mission, universal owners would have to be such a dominating presence among US (if not global) investors—and embrace WBA's resolution so completely—that all of WBA's major retail competitors felt compelled to follow suit.</p><p>Third, given that the proposers accept that adopting a living wage could reduce profits at WBA, they are asking directors at WBA to take an action that they would very likely view as inconsistent with their fiduciary duties, which are to the company and its shareholders as a whole. As Marcel Kahan and Ed Rock have described in detail, the single-firm focus of fiduciary duties makes it extremely difficult for directors to even contemplate an action that knowingly harms their company's competitive position and value to benefit other companies in an investor's portfolio, however convinced of this socially beneficial outcome.13 Of course, it might be argued that investors are simply encouraging WBA directors to take the “higher ground” path to value creation followed by Costco. But one might also question whether certain groups of shareholders are better placed than directors to judge whether this would in fact be successful in WBA's case?</p><p>Fourth, the prospect of institutional investors imposing their view of economic policy on companies through living wage policies looks dangerously close to the kind of political overreach that can be highly inflammatory, inviting the kind of backlash we've recently witnessed by the US political right. In my discussion of the Sainsbury's case, I argued that living wage policies were an odd fight for shareholders to pick given the very well-established infrastructure in the UK for setting minimum wages involving an independent Low Pay Commission—a body with both with a remarkably high level of cross-party support and a mandate to raise living wages as fast as possible consistent with maintaining economic growth and employment. The Commission's work has resulted in a statutory minimum wage that is actually quite close to the “real living wage.”14 Given the political reality of US “federalism,” the process of setting minimum wages in the United States is more fragmented with both federal and state minimum wages and a less clear mandate for how they are set. The Federal Minimum Wage is a clearly inadequate $7.25 per hour, and while most states have a higher minimum wage than this, many do not. And where they do, the shortfall compared with independently calculated living wages is generally much greater than in the United Kingdom.15 This strengthens the argument that in the United States the minimum wage setting process may not be functioning effectively. Many of us believe that higher worker wages would improve social welfare and that the economic costs of minimum wages have often been overstated by the economics profession. But this feels dangerously close to an argument about political priorities than one that is rigorously rooted in financial market valuations. The existence of minimum wage legislation does suggest that shareholders would need to step carefully to avoid being seen as imposing their political views on society outside the democratic process. This raises the bar for the strength of evidence required for shareholders to weigh in on this issue in their engagements with companies.</p><p>To sum up then, two high profile living wage proposals on either side of the Atlantic have failed to secure support of more than a small minority of shareholders. The fact that the WBA resolution achieved even less support than the one at Sainsbury's is at one level surprising because it avoided at least some of the problems I identified in the Sainsbury's case. Part of the explanation is the differing attitudes of US and European shareholders—differences that have only been amplified by the recent US culture wars around ESG. But another part is that the fundamental business case remains so unpersuasive (if not implausible). Indeed, the case based on Universal Owner Theory is probably even more speculative than one linked—like a plan to replicate Costco's success—to the prospects of a single retail company. There are simply too many uncertainties and potentially broken links in the chain of logic for many fiduciaries to convince themselves, in good faith, of the merits of the case. For this reason, and given the difficulty of finding conclusive evidence of the connection to portfolio returns, proposals are probably better framed as posing questions that give management the latitude or option—but not the obligation—to act. The focus on “outcomes” from stewardship has led to increasingly prescriptive engagement demands with demonstrable “results.” However, particularly in the environmental and social sphere, such forceful stewardship is likely to run into problems with fiduciary duty at every level: between the asset owner and their beneficiary; between the asset manager and the asset owner; and between the directors and the company. The reality is that it will be virtually impossible for shareholders to force directors to take actions that damage their companies’ prospects.</p><p>Few would discourage the prospect of seeing more Costcos—companies that appear able to combine high wages and high productivity. But perhaps we need to find a different route to get there. The idea of using shareholder resolutions to impose actions on recalcitrant managements seems to be running out of road across the ESG spectrum, and relying on questionable business cases doesn't seem to be helping. Some of this may be more effectively framed in terms of ethics. Even Milton Friedman proposed that in seeking to create as much shareholder value as possible, business should conform to the basic rules of society, including those embodied in ethical custom. And ethical customs evolve. For example, it has become increasingly accepted that business should be conducted while avoiding slavery in supply chains, even if that add to costs. By making it known to companies that they view decent treatment of human beings, including avoiding poverty wages, as an ethical norm, shareholders create the space for boards to make different decisions. But by attempting to achieve outcomes that impose burdens on, and reduce the competitiveness of, individual companies, based on rationales that only a few shareholders can in good faith subscribe to, resolutions of the type proposed by ShareAction and The Shareholder Commons are almost certain to understate the level of investor support for fair wage policies. At times, aiming for less is likely to achieve more.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":46789,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Journal of Applied Corporate Finance\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.7000,\"publicationDate\":\"2024-06-02\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/jacf.12611\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Journal of Applied Corporate Finance\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/jacf.12611\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q4\",\"JCRName\":\"BUSINESS, FINANCE\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Applied Corporate Finance","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/jacf.12611","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q4","JCRName":"BUSINESS, FINANCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

8 股东福利(与价值相对)的概念首先承认股东既有非财务偏好,也有严格意义上的财务偏好,而投资者的管理应同时考虑到这两方面,并有可能在两者之间进行权衡。但 UOT 的不同之处在于,它认为多元化投资者在投资组合层面的财务利益可以通过管理系统性风险和解决投资组合内公司造成的负面外部效应而实现最大化。我曾在其他地方写过大量文章,讨论 UOT 理论在试图应对气候变化这一具体案例时在实践中遇到的问题,9 在此我只想简单总结一下我的论点。但我发现 Shareholder Commons 在沃尔格林案例中提出的 UOT 论证至少存在四大实际困难。首先,即使决议的颁布确实减少了不平等,也很难证明减少不平等确实会带来更高的多元化市场回报。Shareholder Commons 引用的论文强调了减少不平等可能带来的经济效益。虽然我个人赞同社会将从限制不平等的方法中获益的观点,但我对 Sainsbury's 决议证据的审查表明,很难提供令人信服的(更不用说确凿的)证据,证明投资者为实现这种平等所做的努力将加强经济。10 一些研究者声称,在发达经济体常见的不平等范围内,不平等与经济增长之间存在负相关关系,这似乎存在很大争议。事实上,在过去二十年里,尽管美国存在人们常说的不平等问题,但美国股市和经济的表现却惊人地好于其他国家。11其次,甚至不清楚在WBA引入生活工资是否真的会减少美国的收入不平等。有两种可能性。一种可能是,WBA 以 Costco 为榜样,走上了高工资、高生产率的道路,并为美国市场的收银员和销售员薪酬设定了市场基准。这两家公司在美国共雇用了约 45 万名员工,其中约 30 万名员工将从生活工资承诺中受益。这大约占美国零售业收银员和销售员总就业人数(约 620 万人)的 5%。12 如果 WBA 的决定迫使拥有 160 万美国员工的巨无霸沃尔玛采取生活工资政策,那将是最大的奖赏。但另一种相当现实的可能性是,与其他零售业竞争者相比,WBA最终只会在成本上处于劣势,失去市场份额,减少就业,对更广泛地减少不平等现象毫无贡献。第三,鉴于提议者承认采用生活工资可能会减少西雅图百货公司的利润,他们要求西雅图百货公司的董事们采取的行动很可能会被他们视为不符合他们对公司及其全体股东的信托责任。正如马塞尔-卡汉(Marcel Kahan)和埃德-罗克(Ed Rock)所详细描述的那样,信托责任以单一公司为中心,使得董事们甚至很难考虑采取明知会损害公司竞争地位和价值的行动,来为投资者投资组合中的其他公司谋利,无论他们多么相信这种有利于社会的结果。第四,机构投资者通过生活工资政策将自己的经济政策观点强加给公司的前景,看起来很危险地接近于那种可能极具煽动性的政治越权行为,会招致我们最近目睹的美国政治右派的反弹。在讨论 Sainsbury's 案例时,我曾指出,鉴于英国在制定最低工资标准方面已经建立了非常完善的基础设施,其中包括一个独立的低薪委员会--该机构不仅拥有极高的跨党派支持率,而且还被授权在保持经济增长和就业的前提下尽可能快地提高生活工资,因此股东们选择生活工资政策是很奇怪的。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Living wages revisited: The case of Walgreens Boots Alliance

In 2022, ShareAction, a well-known British activist responsible investment NGO, tabled a resolution at Sainsbury's one of the UK's largest supermarket chains, demanding that they become an accredited Living Wage employer. I wrote up the case in this journal a year ago in an article titled: “Lessons for ESG Activists: The Case of Sainsbury's and the Living Wage.” 1 That proposal was rejected by around five out of every six shareholders at the 2022 Sainsbury's AGM.

So, I was interested to see the investor response to a similar proposal making a similar demand filed by John Chevedden at the 2024 AGM of Walgreens Boots Alliance (WBA).2 The filing was supported by The Shareholder Commons and ShareAction. Were any of my lessons for ESG activists learned? And what should we make of the case made by the proposers?

On the face of it, this resolution turned out to be even less persuasive than the ShareAction proposal at Sainsbury's: fewer than one in ten of WBA's investors supported it.3 Set against this is the fact that ESG proposals have always tended to receive less support at US than European companies, and over the last 2 years even more so. So perhaps the support can be considered comparable, all things considered.

Did the proposal reflect any of the lessons that I proposed we learn from the Sainsbury's proposal? Were shareholders right to reject it? I will argue that the answers are “yes, at least in part,” to the first question—and “yes, though with regrets,” to the second.

How did the WBA proposal stack up against these?

The Business Case Needs to be Compelling and Made with Precision and Care. Two years ago, I was quite critical of the business case put forward by ShareAction to support their proposal. It was very much framed in terms of the benefits to Sainsbury's of paying a living wage, but without compelling evidence to support the case. Indeed, most of the evidence ShareAction cited either was not applicable to the situation or even undermined its own case.4 They failed to demonstrate that paying higher wages than necessary in a competitive low margin business would help Sainsbury's be more successful.

There are theoretical reasons why higher wages can be more than offset by increased productivity, but it is not an automatic result, and the win-win scenario can be quite difficult to pull off. It is not clear that shareholders are better placed than company management to decide whether this can be done in the specific circumstances faced by the company. Indeed, if improving shareholder value was as easy as increasing wages, we would expect more management teams in the retail sector to follow this path, whereas only a small minority do.5

This line of argument is notably different from that set out in the Sainsbury's proposal. The proposers are explicitly acknowledging and accepting the possibility that paying living wages might damage WBA's financial returns. Their innovation is to contend that this sacrifice of returns will be more than offset by reduced inequality leading to higher economic growth and therefore improved returns on the investor's diversified portfolio overall.

Some readers will recognize this as an application of so-called Universal Owner Theory (UOT), which begins by observing that diversified shareholders end up owning what amounts to a slice of the whole economy. Therefore, externalities created by companies that harm the economy also harm the diversified investor's portfolio. This can justify the investor's efforts to influence those companies to address and limit the effects of such externalities. The costs associated with such efforts are proposed to be offset by the financial benefits from the reduced externalities that show up elsewhere in the portfolio.

An example helps to explain universal ownership theory, and how its magic is supposed to work.

To show how diversified share ownership in theory leads investors to address negative externalities in order to maximize portfolio returns, law scholar Madison Condon uses the example of an investor holding stakes in oil majors and food and beverage conglomerates. The former cause climate change, the latter suffer from it. If the costs to the food and beverage holdings exceed the profits made by the oil majors, the investor might conclude that the value-maximizing action at the portfolio level is to cut emissions at their oil holdings (by forcing production cuts) to preserve value in their food and beverage holdings.7

The important thing to note, however, is that UOT claims to be addressing social and environmental concerns in order to achieve the highest possible returns in the investor's portfolio overall. In this sense, it differs from the concept of shareholder welfare maximization described by, for example, Oliver Hart and Luigi Zingales.8 The concept of shareholder welfare (as opposed to value) begins by recognizing that shareholders have non-financial as well as strictly financial preferences, and that investor stewardship should take both of these into account, potentially trading one off against the other. But UOT is different in that it holds out the possibility that a diversified investors’ financial interests at the portfolio level can be maximized by managing systemic risks and addressing negative externalities created by companies within the portfolio.

UOT and the Problem of Inequality. I have written extensively elsewhere about the problems that UOT arguments run into in practice when trying to respond to the specific case of climate change,9 and will just briefly summarize my arguments here. But I find at least four major practical difficulties with the UOT argument presented by Shareholder Commons in the case of Walgreens.

First, even if enactment of the resolution did reduce inequality, it is very difficult to prove that reducing inequality would indeed lead to higher diversified market returns. The Shareholder Commons cites papers highlighting the potential economic benefits of reduced inequality. While I'm personally sympathetic to the idea that society would benefit from finding ways to limit inequality, my review of the evidence for the Sainsbury's resolution suggested the difficulty of providing convincing (much less conclusive) evidence that the economy would be strengthened by investor efforts to impose such equality. And the evidence that financial markets would respond well to such efforts is even less persuasive.10 The negative relationship claimed by some researchers between inequality and economic growth over the ranges of inequality commonly seen in developed economies seems to be quite heavily disputed. Indeed, over the past two decades, it is the US stock market and economy that has spectacularly outperformed despite its own commonly cited inequality problem.11

Second, it is not even clear that introducing a living wage at WBA would indeed reduce income inequality in the United States. There are two possibilities. One is that, following Costco's example, WBA transitions onto a higher-wage, higher- productivity path and helps set a market benchmark for cashier and salesperson pay in the US market. Between them, the two companies employ around 450,000 staff in the United States, of which plausibly some 300,000 would benefit from a living wage commitment. This represents roughly 5% of the total US retail cashier and salesperson employment of around 6.2 million.12 The big prize would be if WBA's decision forced the behemoth that is Walmart (with its 1.6 million US employees) to adopt a living wage policy. But the other quite real possibility is that WBA simply ends up with a cost disadvantage compared with other retail competitors, loses market share, reduces employment, and makes no contribution to wider reduction in inequality. To be assured of success in its social mission, universal owners would have to be such a dominating presence among US (if not global) investors—and embrace WBA's resolution so completely—that all of WBA's major retail competitors felt compelled to follow suit.

Third, given that the proposers accept that adopting a living wage could reduce profits at WBA, they are asking directors at WBA to take an action that they would very likely view as inconsistent with their fiduciary duties, which are to the company and its shareholders as a whole. As Marcel Kahan and Ed Rock have described in detail, the single-firm focus of fiduciary duties makes it extremely difficult for directors to even contemplate an action that knowingly harms their company's competitive position and value to benefit other companies in an investor's portfolio, however convinced of this socially beneficial outcome.13 Of course, it might be argued that investors are simply encouraging WBA directors to take the “higher ground” path to value creation followed by Costco. But one might also question whether certain groups of shareholders are better placed than directors to judge whether this would in fact be successful in WBA's case?

Fourth, the prospect of institutional investors imposing their view of economic policy on companies through living wage policies looks dangerously close to the kind of political overreach that can be highly inflammatory, inviting the kind of backlash we've recently witnessed by the US political right. In my discussion of the Sainsbury's case, I argued that living wage policies were an odd fight for shareholders to pick given the very well-established infrastructure in the UK for setting minimum wages involving an independent Low Pay Commission—a body with both with a remarkably high level of cross-party support and a mandate to raise living wages as fast as possible consistent with maintaining economic growth and employment. The Commission's work has resulted in a statutory minimum wage that is actually quite close to the “real living wage.”14 Given the political reality of US “federalism,” the process of setting minimum wages in the United States is more fragmented with both federal and state minimum wages and a less clear mandate for how they are set. The Federal Minimum Wage is a clearly inadequate $7.25 per hour, and while most states have a higher minimum wage than this, many do not. And where they do, the shortfall compared with independently calculated living wages is generally much greater than in the United Kingdom.15 This strengthens the argument that in the United States the minimum wage setting process may not be functioning effectively. Many of us believe that higher worker wages would improve social welfare and that the economic costs of minimum wages have often been overstated by the economics profession. But this feels dangerously close to an argument about political priorities than one that is rigorously rooted in financial market valuations. The existence of minimum wage legislation does suggest that shareholders would need to step carefully to avoid being seen as imposing their political views on society outside the democratic process. This raises the bar for the strength of evidence required for shareholders to weigh in on this issue in their engagements with companies.

To sum up then, two high profile living wage proposals on either side of the Atlantic have failed to secure support of more than a small minority of shareholders. The fact that the WBA resolution achieved even less support than the one at Sainsbury's is at one level surprising because it avoided at least some of the problems I identified in the Sainsbury's case. Part of the explanation is the differing attitudes of US and European shareholders—differences that have only been amplified by the recent US culture wars around ESG. But another part is that the fundamental business case remains so unpersuasive (if not implausible). Indeed, the case based on Universal Owner Theory is probably even more speculative than one linked—like a plan to replicate Costco's success—to the prospects of a single retail company. There are simply too many uncertainties and potentially broken links in the chain of logic for many fiduciaries to convince themselves, in good faith, of the merits of the case. For this reason, and given the difficulty of finding conclusive evidence of the connection to portfolio returns, proposals are probably better framed as posing questions that give management the latitude or option—but not the obligation—to act. The focus on “outcomes” from stewardship has led to increasingly prescriptive engagement demands with demonstrable “results.” However, particularly in the environmental and social sphere, such forceful stewardship is likely to run into problems with fiduciary duty at every level: between the asset owner and their beneficiary; between the asset manager and the asset owner; and between the directors and the company. The reality is that it will be virtually impossible for shareholders to force directors to take actions that damage their companies’ prospects.

Few would discourage the prospect of seeing more Costcos—companies that appear able to combine high wages and high productivity. But perhaps we need to find a different route to get there. The idea of using shareholder resolutions to impose actions on recalcitrant managements seems to be running out of road across the ESG spectrum, and relying on questionable business cases doesn't seem to be helping. Some of this may be more effectively framed in terms of ethics. Even Milton Friedman proposed that in seeking to create as much shareholder value as possible, business should conform to the basic rules of society, including those embodied in ethical custom. And ethical customs evolve. For example, it has become increasingly accepted that business should be conducted while avoiding slavery in supply chains, even if that add to costs. By making it known to companies that they view decent treatment of human beings, including avoiding poverty wages, as an ethical norm, shareholders create the space for boards to make different decisions. But by attempting to achieve outcomes that impose burdens on, and reduce the competitiveness of, individual companies, based on rationales that only a few shareholders can in good faith subscribe to, resolutions of the type proposed by ShareAction and The Shareholder Commons are almost certain to understate the level of investor support for fair wage policies. At times, aiming for less is likely to achieve more.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
11.10%
发文量
44
期刊最新文献
Michael C. Jensen: Scholar, mentor, colleague Michael Jensen's contributions to the theory of the firm: A tribute in three acts A message from the editor Issue Information - TOC A message from the Editors
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1