企业社会责任与股东至上范式

IF 0.7 Q4 BUSINESS, FINANCE Journal of Applied Corporate Finance Pub Date : 2024-06-11 DOI:10.1111/jacf.12613
David J. Denis
{"title":"企业社会责任与股东至上范式","authors":"David J. Denis","doi":"10.1111/jacf.12613","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Recent years have witnessed an explosion in the attention paid to the notion of corporate social responsibility (CSR), the idea that corporations have an obligation to consider the impact of their decisions on a broad set of stakeholders that extends well beyond their investors. Such social concerns are by no means new; they were matters for corporate boardroom and top management discussions long before Milton Friedman published his famous editorial on the social responsibility of business.1 Nonetheless, for at least the past decade and since the passing of the Global Financial Crisis, CSR advocates have more vigorously pursued their mission of incorporating social concerns within the purview of corporate decision-making.</p><p>But why so much corporate attention to social matters now? Three possibilities come to mind. First, the urgency of social concerns and the perceived ability of and expectation that corporations will do something about them have increased over time as public companies have become steadily larger and their reach more global. Climate change is the prototype of a social issue whose urgency and scope continue to grow over time. Second is the possibility that, although the social concerns themselves have not changed much over time, individual preferences have changed and various stakeholders have become more sensitive to those concerns than before. A third possibility is that, although social concerns tend to arise from negative “externalities” that most economists assume are best managed through government regulation, growing or widespread skepticism about the ability of government institutions to address these concerns in cost-effective ways could lead to increased demand for corporate investment in addressing social challenges.</p><p>Regardless of the reason for the increased attention to CSR, it is almost invariably accompanied by calls for rethinking the idea of shareholder primacy in the corporate objective function. In this article, I address the question of whether the increased focus on CSR requires a paradigm shift away from the traditional shareholder primacy model toward one that gives more voice to stakeholders. My short answer to this question is no, and for three main reasons:</p><p>First, the increased focus on CSR has virtually nothing to do with the factors that led to the establishment of shareholder primacy as the dominant paradigm. The theory of shareholder primacy which is a cornerstone of modern corporate finance arose as an efficient solution to “contracting” problems faced by corporations that have a diverse set of stakeholders, each of which often has different preferences about what and how certain corporate decisions get made.2 Such contracting problems—which have long been, and will always be, with us—are likely to become even more intractable with the rising demand for CSR. Which leads to the suggestion: if we thought that shareholder primacy was part of an efficient organizational structure before the ascent of CSR, it may well be even more critical to corporate sustainability and success in the future.</p><p>Second, to the extent there is demand for CSR from investors and other stakeholders, market forces work to ensure that such demand is met even when shareholder primacy is an essential element of the corporate objective function. Such market forces take the form of consumer demand, employee preferences, and even investor preferences that lead public companies to devote time and capital to CSR initiatives as part of an overall objective of maximizing the wealth of their stockholders.</p><p>Third, and perhaps most importantly, a widespread corporate movement away from shareholder primacy toward a model dedicated to, say, stakeholder primacy is likely to produce “agency” and other contracting costs that exceed any CSR benefits to investors and other stakeholders.</p><p>The idea of shareholder primacy is rooted in the contracting framework of corporations that was developed by people like Michael Jensen and William Meckling in their seminal study published in the <i>Journal of Financial Economics</i>, as well as a pair of papers published by Jensen and Eugene Fama in the <i>Journal of Law and Economics</i>.3 These finance scholars view the corporation as a legal fiction that is best represented as “a nexus of contracts” among customers and all the different “factors of production,” including suppliers of labor and capital and other stakeholders, that affect, and in turn are affected by, the corporation.</p><p>Given this view of the firm, how companies end up being organized and structured is seen as the outcome of a competitive process in which all kinds of commercial enterprises, from sole proprietorships to global multinationals, attempt to supply the products demanded by customers at the lowest possible prices while covering all the costs incurred. Among such costs are those involved in managing the contracts among all the different parties to the firm.</p><p>The contracting structure that emerges from what amounts to a society-wide process of negotiation ends up specifying two things: (1) the payoffs to all stakeholders—that is, who gets what and when; and (2) the distribution of “decision rights”—who gets to make what decisions inside the firm. The goal of this process is to find and implement the contractual set-up that enables the firm to compete most effectively in the marketplace. And barring the case of externalities (which we take up later), the conclusion of most economists and (free-market) policymakers is that such competition ends up leading to the socially optimal use of the resources—notably, people and capital—involved.</p><p>How does such a process lead to shareholder primacy as the dominant paradigm? Corporations, as already noted, are best viewed as temporary, or at least finite-lived, associations among many different stakeholder groups—customers, suppliers, creditors, labor, communities, stockholders—with economic interests in and claims on the firm. In a widely cited paper published in 1960 titled “The Problem of Social Cost,” Nobel laureate Ronald Coase showed that when the writing and enforcement of contracts are assumed to be costless, the optimal decision rule in such a situation is to aim to maximize the <i>combined welfare</i> of <i>all</i> the major stakeholder groups. Having identified the corporate objective as maximizing the size of the aggregate payoffs (or the “total pie,” if you will) that can be divided among them, the function of the contracts is then the most efficient distribution of the resulting wealth among the various stakeholders—and by “most efficient” we mean the one that leads most predictably to the highest collective outcome.4</p><p>In practice, of course, contracts are neither costless to write nor to enforce. And what is particularly important in the context of a corporation is that the various stakeholders have a potentially broad range of (often conflicting) preferences about corporate decisions, and the associated size and risk of the resulting payoffs. For example, whereas lower-level employees are likely to favor low-risk operating policies that reduce the probability of job losses (even those with lower expected returns), well-diversified shareholders may well favor higher-risk policies with higher expected returns. Faced with such a wide set of stakeholders with different interests and preferences, large organizations would find it very costly indeed to try to accommodate this range of preferences by writing separate, highly customized contracts (although some of this no doubt goes on in some companies).</p><p>But the bottom line is that the public corporate organizational form that prevails in most developed economies today can and should be viewed as the solution to this contracting problem—a solution that has evolved, and continues to evolve, over time to maximize the productive output of the corporate form while minimizing the contracting costs inherent in it.</p><p>The dominant form of today's public corporation has three important features worth noting in this context. First, most stakeholders that are also factors of production (notably, employees and suppliers, as well as creditors) have contracts that specify <i>fixed</i> promised payoffs or incentive payoffs that are tied to very specific performance outcomes and metrics. However, the fact that most such contracts have fixed promised payoffs does not mean that the payoffs are without risk. Each of these parties effectively assumes some risk that is tied to the priority structure of the payoffs and that is reflected in the size of the fixed promised payoff. So, for example, because creditors are paid only after employees’ claims are taken care of, the promised payment to creditors includes a “premium” to compensate them for the risk of default on their payments.</p><p>Second, after the claims of all the other stakeholders have been satisfied, the remaining, or residual, risk of the corporation is borne by one set of stakeholders—the shareholders—who have contracted to receive the net cash flows, those that remain after all other claimants to those cash flows have received their promised payment.</p><p>Third, decision rights are vested in shareholders, the parties who bear the residual risk. Moreover, because these decision rights are exercised by the corporation's top executive team acting as agents of the shareholders, corporate boards have evolved as a governance mechanism that monitors the behavior of these agents to ensure their decisions are made in the best interest of shareholders.</p><p>Understood in these terms, then, shareholder primacy represents a competitive solution to the problem of maximizing the collective stakeholder welfare in a way that minimizes the various contracting costs associated with so doing. There is nothing that forces corporations to be organized this way. Other possible forms of business organization that have long been, and can still be, observed in the United States and elsewhere are private partnerships owned and managed by their main capital providers, mutual organizations owned and run by their largest customers (most notably in the insurance industry), and <i>cooperatives</i>, like the local Agway, in which the big investment and distribution decisions are made by boards representing and composed entirely of local customers and employees.</p><p>But, again, the fact that the public corporation has come to dominate commercial activity in all of the world's developed economies suggests that it has been found to be the most economically efficient for most large-scale business enterprise.</p><p>And this brings us to one important, and widespread, misconception about shareholder primacy and the corporate form of organization—namely, that the interests of stakeholders other than the stockholders are routinely ignored or taken for granted. The reality, as we have just seen, is that such stakeholder groups explicitly contract for their payoff <i>upfront</i>, in most cases ensuring their senior-most priority among corporate distributions. And so whatever controversy continues to surround the corporate treatment of its non-investor stakeholders, the controversy is ultimately about not the existence, but the adequacy, of those payoffs they have already contracted for.</p><p>How do these distinctive features of the public corporation—fixed, high-priority payoffs to stakeholders, and residual risk bearing and decision-making by shareholders (and boards)—work to make the resulting organizational form the most efficient? The work of Fama and Jensen cited earlier offers several insights. First, by allowing for most of the risk of the company to be borne by shareholders, this structure makes possible specialization and efficiencies in risk-bearing by effectively ensuring that the people who supply the bulk of the savings for corporate capital investment are not the same ones making the organization-specific commitments that are required of and made by, say, the company's employees or suppliers. Precisely because a company's shareholders can more effectively diversify their personal risk than can its managers or employees, it will generally turn out to be more efficient to have them bear the residual risk of the firm.</p><p>Second, by limiting the risks faced by most corporate stakeholders, the costs associated with writing and monitoring (and, when necessary, modifying) the firm's contracts with those stakeholders (say, in response to changes in those risks) are kept to a minimum.</p><p>Third, these lower contracting costs both increase the company's net cash flows and, in so doing, contribute to corporate staying power by enabling companies to deliver their products at lower prices (while providing higher shareholder returns and collective payoffs to non-investor stakeholders) than would otherwise be possible.</p><p>But now let us turn to the main subject of this paper: If investors’ preferences are now reflecting today's greater demand for CSR, does this change anything about the efficient contractual structure of the firm? To address that question, it is useful to start by considering the possible effects of CSR policies on corporate decision-making and shareholders.</p><p>Some policies that fall under the CSR umbrella arguably can be expected to increase the present value of corporate net cash flows and therefore the value of shareholders’ claims. For example, think about sustainable production processes (e.g., free-range chickens) for which there is high consumer demand. To the extent consumers are willing to pay a premium price that exceeds the marginal costs of providing that sustainable production process, it is clearly in the interests of shareholders to adopt such a policy.</p><p>A second possibility, however, is CSR policies that reduce the present value of the firm's net cash flows while failing to improve the welfare of any of the firm's stakeholders. For example, some commentators have argued that the recent climate disclosure rules promulgated by the Securities and Exchange Commission (SEC) impose significant costs on companies and their shareholders without any offsetting benefits in limiting climate change.5</p><p>A third category of CSR policies includes those that are arguably the most interesting from a public policy standpoint: those that are expected to reduce the present value of corporate net cash flows while increasing the welfare of some stakeholders—and possibly even some shareholders themselves. Such cases involve a sacrifice, or tradeoff, of shareholder for stakeholder value for some allegedly greater social good. But the question is, which party gets to make that decision, and how do they justify it to the shareholders who are being asked to make the sacrifice? An example of this type of CSR policy might be green energy solutions that raise the company's overall cost of production.</p><p>With these categories in mind, the question then becomes whether an objective function such as stakeholder primacy would do a better job than the traditional shareholder primacy of sorting among these different CSR policies.</p><p>Although I have already suggested that increased demand for CSR does not alter the conclusion that shareholder primacy is part of an efficient organizational contracting structure, it is important to note that this does not mean that stakeholder preferences for CSR are simply ignored. In fact, quite the contrary. Such preferences are directly captured and reflected in the fixed payoffs, or market prices, that stakeholders contract for when negotiating with the firm. In this sense, even under shareholder primacy, market forces can be seen as pushing companies to meet stakeholder demands for CSR.</p><p><b>Customers</b>. Let us start with the case of product markets and how they reflect the preferences of consumers. A company's customers have often shown themselves willing to pay price premiums for products made by companies that adopt what consumers view as more socially responsible policies. In a recent survey of its consumers, Whole Foods found that nearly two-thirds of millennials view transparency in food sourcing as informing their food purchases. Expressing a commitment to work more plant-based and unprocessed foods into their diet, and to consider the effects of these choices on the environment, millennials also indicated their willingness to pay more for “high-quality” foods.7 If this price premium is large enough, a company like Whole Foods is more than willing to meet this particular CSR demand, with the expectation in so doing of maximizing its own long-run shareholder and firm value.</p><p><b>Employees</b>. In the case of labor markets, employees demand higher wages to work for companies they view as less socially responsible—or alternatively, they willingly accept lower wages to work for companies that are better aligned with their CSR goals. One often cited example is Patagonia, where employees are notoriously low-paid, but nonetheless appear happy to work for a company whose mission includes doing good for the planet. Similarly, Tesla and SpaceX are known to have employee pay that is low relative to tech industry standards, but nonetheless have employees with high rates of job satisfaction who describe their work as “highly meaningful.”8</p><p>As another example, the shoe manufacturer Allbirds requires its suppliers to adhere to a “Supplier Code of Conduct” that specifies the company's social and environmental standards.11 All of the company's Tier 1 suppliers are enrolled in its Social Audit and Environmental Programs, and the firm's stated goal is to have 100% of its Tier 2 suppliers in the programs as well.</p><p><b>Communities</b>. Communities generally make any subsidies they offer corporations contingent on socially responsible policies by the corporation. For example, Tesla received a subsidy of at least 1 billion euros from the German government in 2021 to construct a battery cell factory in Berlin. The government chose to subsidize Tesla to support its production of electric vehicle batteries and help reduce German imports from Chinese suppliers, who were deemed to be less socially responsible, and to support the shift away from fossil fuels.12</p><p><b>Shareholders</b>. Even shareholders themselves might be willing to accept lower returns in exchange for certain CSR policies. A number of different academic models suggest the possibility that sufficient investor demand for CSR could increase the market value of companies perceived to be socially responsible, effectively reducing the companies’ cost of equity capital. Consistent with this possibility, recent academic studies provide evidence of an association between higher CSR and lower costs of equity capital that is accomplished through a tilting of the investor base.13</p><p>The bottom line, then, is that under an organizational design that features shareholder primacy as its objective function, companies will continue to respond to stakeholder demands for CSR that are reflected in the prices at which they contract with the firm. And as long as the costs to the firm of supplying that CSR are lower than the benefits—in the form of higher product prices, lower employee costs, better and more lucrative supplier arrangements, greater community subsidies, and lower costs of capital—CSR policies are likely to benefit shareholders, too.</p><p>Up to this point, I have argued that market forces operating by means of and within the corporate contracting structure led public companies to supply CSR policies that are valued and, in some cases, fully expected and demanded by their stakeholders. But what about CSR for which there is no clear stakeholder demand from within the firm? A reasonable critique of my argument to this point is that not all of the costs and benefits of CSR-related activities are realized (or “internalized”) by the firm and its internal stakeholders. To the extent that a company's stream of profits and the value of its stock reflect the costs, but do not capture all projected CSR benefits, firms will tend to invest less in CSR and, therefore, could be imposing net costs on society that reduce general social welfare.</p><p>The most prominent and commonly cited example of this type of negative economic externality is damage to the environment through, say, pollution generated by a firm's manufacturing process. Because companies bear the full cost of limiting this pollution but share the benefits with society, a policy of maximizing shareholder value will lead them to pollute more than what society would deem to be the optimal level.</p><p>Economists have long recognized that government regulators are generally in the best position to address these types of economic externalities and, in so doing, find the socially most efficient position. However, as noted earlier, the increased demand for corporate action, or CSR, could be interpreted as a byproduct of a general view that governments have not been particularly effective in addressing these externalities. To the extent that is the case, corporate management could be justified in taking a more stakeholder-oriented point of view in which the social impact of corporate policies becomes an explicit part of the corporate objective function.</p><p>But, again, there is a major obstacle to implementing this solution without first securing some kind of general mandate from shareholders—namely the difficulty of taking a purely stakeholder-driven approach to environmental challenges arising from the sheer variety of stakeholders’ preferences themselves with respect to individual CSR policies. As the French “yellow vest” protests might suggest, there are likely to be limits to employees’ willingness to make economic sacrifices for larger social benefits, especially those not expected to materialize in the near future. Put differently, if a company imposes externalities on society when the maximization of shareholder wealth is the objective function, it is probably at least as likely to do so under a stakeholder primacy regime.</p><p>If we cannot count on government regulators to address problems of externalities effectively, and a general stakeholder primacy approach is no better than shareholder primacy in providing the socially optimal CSR policies, what about the possibility that companies simply delegate this role to corporate managers? Such delegation would be broadly consistent with current practices in which managers are already afforded considerable discretion in choosing corporate policies for the purpose of maximizing shareholder wealth. Under this alternative, CEOs would essentially be CSR central planners who, under the business judgment rule, would be granted wide latitude in choosing policies that meet some vaguely specified target of social responsibility.</p><p>Again, however, it is difficult to see how this would work. Delegating to individuals decisions that have already proven too complicated and costly to address through voluntary contracting does not seem at all promising or workable. CEOs are chosen for their specialized expertise in how to produce products demanded by consumers at the lowest price—not for their experience or wisdom in identifying or formulating effective social policy or adjudicating tradeoffs among different stakeholder groups. These are tough decisions even for law-givers and -makers, and to entrust them to corporate managers is a prescription, as Jensen pointed out, for organizational confusion.</p><p>And as Tom Gosling demonstrates in the immediately preceding article about the Walgreens-Boots living wage campaign, asking corporate CEOs to ignore or override labor market pricing when determining what constitutes a “living wage” for the majority of their employees is an invitation to misrule and competitive failure. Such arrogation by top corporate executives of functions normally provided by labor and other factor markets would greatly expand the scope for agency conflicts—or, arguably, open a veritable Pandora's box of them—in which corporate managers would be tempted to use their discretion to make decisions that while making their own lives easier, end up hurting their shareholders and other stakeholders.</p><p>Financial economists, to be sure, have long recognized the potential for conflicts of interest to arise in situations in which agents are performing tasks on behalf of principals. In their seminal article—by far the most cited in the corporate finance literature—Michael Jensen and William Meckling applied the theory of agency costs to the specific setting of the modern public corporation in which there is typically a clear separation between ownership and control of the firm.14 One of the article's key insights is that the value lost from agency conflicts of interest and incentives between corporate executives and their shareholders can be limited through the monitoring of executive behavior by corporate boards and, if and when necessary, active outside investors. But the effectiveness of such monitoring is also bound to be limited in large part because the specialized expertise of managers makes it difficult for board members to be able to identify self-interested, value-reducing behavior on the part of managers. The limits of this monitoring will only become more evident when the scope of managerial discretion is enlarged to include the adoption of socially responsible policies and attempts to “balance” their aims with those of long-run value-maximization.</p><p>My bottom line, then, is that it is difficult to make a compelling case for departing from shareholder primacy as an essential element of the corporate objective function. Nonetheless, as demand for corporate social responsibility grows, companies that seek to enhance shareholder value will be prompted to supply CSR policies by the prices at which they contract with other stakeholders. In a world in which consumers volunteer to pay more for products produced in more socially responsible ways and employees demand higher wages to work for companies viewed as less socially responsible, well-thought-out CSR policies have the potential to contribute to the corporate bottom line. Much the same arguments apply to corporate policies vis a vis other stakeholders like suppliers and communities. In the end, as demand for CSR grows, companies aiming to maximize shareholder wealth will find themselves adopting and implementing more CSR policies.</p><p>To be sure, this should not be taken to imply that the market incentives to supply CSR policies will necessarily result in the socially optimal amount of CSR policies. After all, as I noted earlier, the pursuit of shareholder wealth maximization will continue to produce some corporate externalities such as adverse environmental impacts. And to the extent that regulatory solutions continue to prove inadequate, there will still be residual net costs to society.</p><p>But as I have also pointed out, any pronounced shift away from long-run value maximization is unlikely to improve either the state of the environment or the general economy. Neither increased experimentation with stakeholder capitalism nor granting top executives more leeway in enacting social policy is likely to leave shareholders and the other stakeholders that constitute today's largest corporations collectively better off.</p><p>Just as investors care about the risk and return characteristics of their portfolios more than they care about the risks and returns of the individual stocks that make up the portfolio, the aggregate supply of CSR by public (and private) companies should be more important than the supply by individual firms. For that reason, we should also neither expect (nor insist that) the supply of CSR policies by corporations follow a “one-size-fits-all” approach. To the extent that companies continue to respond to market signals (as they have in the past), they will keep supplying CSR policies whose benefits (in the form of higher product prices, or reductions in labor or capital costs) exceed the costs. Some companies are almost certain to have a comparative advantage in supplying CSR policies, if only because their costs of providing such policies and the associated public goods are significantly lower. Similarly, on the demand side, not all stakeholders have the same demand for CSR policies. For example, not all consumers care about sustainable production processes. Accordingly, we would expect those companies that can deliver CSR policies at the lowest cost to specialize in the provision of such policies—while stakeholders with the strongest preferences for CSR policies (and willingness to pay a premium for them) will tend to gravitate toward, and so benefit and help sustain, the companies supplying the public goods associated with such policies.</p>","PeriodicalId":46789,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Applied Corporate Finance","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.7000,"publicationDate":"2024-06-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/jacf.12613","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Corporate social responsibility and the shareholder primacy paradigm\",\"authors\":\"David J. Denis\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/jacf.12613\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>Recent years have witnessed an explosion in the attention paid to the notion of corporate social responsibility (CSR), the idea that corporations have an obligation to consider the impact of their decisions on a broad set of stakeholders that extends well beyond their investors. Such social concerns are by no means new; they were matters for corporate boardroom and top management discussions long before Milton Friedman published his famous editorial on the social responsibility of business.1 Nonetheless, for at least the past decade and since the passing of the Global Financial Crisis, CSR advocates have more vigorously pursued their mission of incorporating social concerns within the purview of corporate decision-making.</p><p>But why so much corporate attention to social matters now? Three possibilities come to mind. First, the urgency of social concerns and the perceived ability of and expectation that corporations will do something about them have increased over time as public companies have become steadily larger and their reach more global. Climate change is the prototype of a social issue whose urgency and scope continue to grow over time. Second is the possibility that, although the social concerns themselves have not changed much over time, individual preferences have changed and various stakeholders have become more sensitive to those concerns than before. A third possibility is that, although social concerns tend to arise from negative “externalities” that most economists assume are best managed through government regulation, growing or widespread skepticism about the ability of government institutions to address these concerns in cost-effective ways could lead to increased demand for corporate investment in addressing social challenges.</p><p>Regardless of the reason for the increased attention to CSR, it is almost invariably accompanied by calls for rethinking the idea of shareholder primacy in the corporate objective function. In this article, I address the question of whether the increased focus on CSR requires a paradigm shift away from the traditional shareholder primacy model toward one that gives more voice to stakeholders. My short answer to this question is no, and for three main reasons:</p><p>First, the increased focus on CSR has virtually nothing to do with the factors that led to the establishment of shareholder primacy as the dominant paradigm. The theory of shareholder primacy which is a cornerstone of modern corporate finance arose as an efficient solution to “contracting” problems faced by corporations that have a diverse set of stakeholders, each of which often has different preferences about what and how certain corporate decisions get made.2 Such contracting problems—which have long been, and will always be, with us—are likely to become even more intractable with the rising demand for CSR. Which leads to the suggestion: if we thought that shareholder primacy was part of an efficient organizational structure before the ascent of CSR, it may well be even more critical to corporate sustainability and success in the future.</p><p>Second, to the extent there is demand for CSR from investors and other stakeholders, market forces work to ensure that such demand is met even when shareholder primacy is an essential element of the corporate objective function. Such market forces take the form of consumer demand, employee preferences, and even investor preferences that lead public companies to devote time and capital to CSR initiatives as part of an overall objective of maximizing the wealth of their stockholders.</p><p>Third, and perhaps most importantly, a widespread corporate movement away from shareholder primacy toward a model dedicated to, say, stakeholder primacy is likely to produce “agency” and other contracting costs that exceed any CSR benefits to investors and other stakeholders.</p><p>The idea of shareholder primacy is rooted in the contracting framework of corporations that was developed by people like Michael Jensen and William Meckling in their seminal study published in the <i>Journal of Financial Economics</i>, as well as a pair of papers published by Jensen and Eugene Fama in the <i>Journal of Law and Economics</i>.3 These finance scholars view the corporation as a legal fiction that is best represented as “a nexus of contracts” among customers and all the different “factors of production,” including suppliers of labor and capital and other stakeholders, that affect, and in turn are affected by, the corporation.</p><p>Given this view of the firm, how companies end up being organized and structured is seen as the outcome of a competitive process in which all kinds of commercial enterprises, from sole proprietorships to global multinationals, attempt to supply the products demanded by customers at the lowest possible prices while covering all the costs incurred. Among such costs are those involved in managing the contracts among all the different parties to the firm.</p><p>The contracting structure that emerges from what amounts to a society-wide process of negotiation ends up specifying two things: (1) the payoffs to all stakeholders—that is, who gets what and when; and (2) the distribution of “decision rights”—who gets to make what decisions inside the firm. The goal of this process is to find and implement the contractual set-up that enables the firm to compete most effectively in the marketplace. And barring the case of externalities (which we take up later), the conclusion of most economists and (free-market) policymakers is that such competition ends up leading to the socially optimal use of the resources—notably, people and capital—involved.</p><p>How does such a process lead to shareholder primacy as the dominant paradigm? Corporations, as already noted, are best viewed as temporary, or at least finite-lived, associations among many different stakeholder groups—customers, suppliers, creditors, labor, communities, stockholders—with economic interests in and claims on the firm. In a widely cited paper published in 1960 titled “The Problem of Social Cost,” Nobel laureate Ronald Coase showed that when the writing and enforcement of contracts are assumed to be costless, the optimal decision rule in such a situation is to aim to maximize the <i>combined welfare</i> of <i>all</i> the major stakeholder groups. Having identified the corporate objective as maximizing the size of the aggregate payoffs (or the “total pie,” if you will) that can be divided among them, the function of the contracts is then the most efficient distribution of the resulting wealth among the various stakeholders—and by “most efficient” we mean the one that leads most predictably to the highest collective outcome.4</p><p>In practice, of course, contracts are neither costless to write nor to enforce. And what is particularly important in the context of a corporation is that the various stakeholders have a potentially broad range of (often conflicting) preferences about corporate decisions, and the associated size and risk of the resulting payoffs. For example, whereas lower-level employees are likely to favor low-risk operating policies that reduce the probability of job losses (even those with lower expected returns), well-diversified shareholders may well favor higher-risk policies with higher expected returns. Faced with such a wide set of stakeholders with different interests and preferences, large organizations would find it very costly indeed to try to accommodate this range of preferences by writing separate, highly customized contracts (although some of this no doubt goes on in some companies).</p><p>But the bottom line is that the public corporate organizational form that prevails in most developed economies today can and should be viewed as the solution to this contracting problem—a solution that has evolved, and continues to evolve, over time to maximize the productive output of the corporate form while minimizing the contracting costs inherent in it.</p><p>The dominant form of today's public corporation has three important features worth noting in this context. First, most stakeholders that are also factors of production (notably, employees and suppliers, as well as creditors) have contracts that specify <i>fixed</i> promised payoffs or incentive payoffs that are tied to very specific performance outcomes and metrics. However, the fact that most such contracts have fixed promised payoffs does not mean that the payoffs are without risk. Each of these parties effectively assumes some risk that is tied to the priority structure of the payoffs and that is reflected in the size of the fixed promised payoff. So, for example, because creditors are paid only after employees’ claims are taken care of, the promised payment to creditors includes a “premium” to compensate them for the risk of default on their payments.</p><p>Second, after the claims of all the other stakeholders have been satisfied, the remaining, or residual, risk of the corporation is borne by one set of stakeholders—the shareholders—who have contracted to receive the net cash flows, those that remain after all other claimants to those cash flows have received their promised payment.</p><p>Third, decision rights are vested in shareholders, the parties who bear the residual risk. Moreover, because these decision rights are exercised by the corporation's top executive team acting as agents of the shareholders, corporate boards have evolved as a governance mechanism that monitors the behavior of these agents to ensure their decisions are made in the best interest of shareholders.</p><p>Understood in these terms, then, shareholder primacy represents a competitive solution to the problem of maximizing the collective stakeholder welfare in a way that minimizes the various contracting costs associated with so doing. There is nothing that forces corporations to be organized this way. Other possible forms of business organization that have long been, and can still be, observed in the United States and elsewhere are private partnerships owned and managed by their main capital providers, mutual organizations owned and run by their largest customers (most notably in the insurance industry), and <i>cooperatives</i>, like the local Agway, in which the big investment and distribution decisions are made by boards representing and composed entirely of local customers and employees.</p><p>But, again, the fact that the public corporation has come to dominate commercial activity in all of the world's developed economies suggests that it has been found to be the most economically efficient for most large-scale business enterprise.</p><p>And this brings us to one important, and widespread, misconception about shareholder primacy and the corporate form of organization—namely, that the interests of stakeholders other than the stockholders are routinely ignored or taken for granted. The reality, as we have just seen, is that such stakeholder groups explicitly contract for their payoff <i>upfront</i>, in most cases ensuring their senior-most priority among corporate distributions. And so whatever controversy continues to surround the corporate treatment of its non-investor stakeholders, the controversy is ultimately about not the existence, but the adequacy, of those payoffs they have already contracted for.</p><p>How do these distinctive features of the public corporation—fixed, high-priority payoffs to stakeholders, and residual risk bearing and decision-making by shareholders (and boards)—work to make the resulting organizational form the most efficient? The work of Fama and Jensen cited earlier offers several insights. First, by allowing for most of the risk of the company to be borne by shareholders, this structure makes possible specialization and efficiencies in risk-bearing by effectively ensuring that the people who supply the bulk of the savings for corporate capital investment are not the same ones making the organization-specific commitments that are required of and made by, say, the company's employees or suppliers. Precisely because a company's shareholders can more effectively diversify their personal risk than can its managers or employees, it will generally turn out to be more efficient to have them bear the residual risk of the firm.</p><p>Second, by limiting the risks faced by most corporate stakeholders, the costs associated with writing and monitoring (and, when necessary, modifying) the firm's contracts with those stakeholders (say, in response to changes in those risks) are kept to a minimum.</p><p>Third, these lower contracting costs both increase the company's net cash flows and, in so doing, contribute to corporate staying power by enabling companies to deliver their products at lower prices (while providing higher shareholder returns and collective payoffs to non-investor stakeholders) than would otherwise be possible.</p><p>But now let us turn to the main subject of this paper: If investors’ preferences are now reflecting today's greater demand for CSR, does this change anything about the efficient contractual structure of the firm? To address that question, it is useful to start by considering the possible effects of CSR policies on corporate decision-making and shareholders.</p><p>Some policies that fall under the CSR umbrella arguably can be expected to increase the present value of corporate net cash flows and therefore the value of shareholders’ claims. For example, think about sustainable production processes (e.g., free-range chickens) for which there is high consumer demand. To the extent consumers are willing to pay a premium price that exceeds the marginal costs of providing that sustainable production process, it is clearly in the interests of shareholders to adopt such a policy.</p><p>A second possibility, however, is CSR policies that reduce the present value of the firm's net cash flows while failing to improve the welfare of any of the firm's stakeholders. For example, some commentators have argued that the recent climate disclosure rules promulgated by the Securities and Exchange Commission (SEC) impose significant costs on companies and their shareholders without any offsetting benefits in limiting climate change.5</p><p>A third category of CSR policies includes those that are arguably the most interesting from a public policy standpoint: those that are expected to reduce the present value of corporate net cash flows while increasing the welfare of some stakeholders—and possibly even some shareholders themselves. Such cases involve a sacrifice, or tradeoff, of shareholder for stakeholder value for some allegedly greater social good. But the question is, which party gets to make that decision, and how do they justify it to the shareholders who are being asked to make the sacrifice? An example of this type of CSR policy might be green energy solutions that raise the company's overall cost of production.</p><p>With these categories in mind, the question then becomes whether an objective function such as stakeholder primacy would do a better job than the traditional shareholder primacy of sorting among these different CSR policies.</p><p>Although I have already suggested that increased demand for CSR does not alter the conclusion that shareholder primacy is part of an efficient organizational contracting structure, it is important to note that this does not mean that stakeholder preferences for CSR are simply ignored. In fact, quite the contrary. Such preferences are directly captured and reflected in the fixed payoffs, or market prices, that stakeholders contract for when negotiating with the firm. In this sense, even under shareholder primacy, market forces can be seen as pushing companies to meet stakeholder demands for CSR.</p><p><b>Customers</b>. Let us start with the case of product markets and how they reflect the preferences of consumers. A company's customers have often shown themselves willing to pay price premiums for products made by companies that adopt what consumers view as more socially responsible policies. In a recent survey of its consumers, Whole Foods found that nearly two-thirds of millennials view transparency in food sourcing as informing their food purchases. Expressing a commitment to work more plant-based and unprocessed foods into their diet, and to consider the effects of these choices on the environment, millennials also indicated their willingness to pay more for “high-quality” foods.7 If this price premium is large enough, a company like Whole Foods is more than willing to meet this particular CSR demand, with the expectation in so doing of maximizing its own long-run shareholder and firm value.</p><p><b>Employees</b>. In the case of labor markets, employees demand higher wages to work for companies they view as less socially responsible—or alternatively, they willingly accept lower wages to work for companies that are better aligned with their CSR goals. One often cited example is Patagonia, where employees are notoriously low-paid, but nonetheless appear happy to work for a company whose mission includes doing good for the planet. Similarly, Tesla and SpaceX are known to have employee pay that is low relative to tech industry standards, but nonetheless have employees with high rates of job satisfaction who describe their work as “highly meaningful.”8</p><p>As another example, the shoe manufacturer Allbirds requires its suppliers to adhere to a “Supplier Code of Conduct” that specifies the company's social and environmental standards.11 All of the company's Tier 1 suppliers are enrolled in its Social Audit and Environmental Programs, and the firm's stated goal is to have 100% of its Tier 2 suppliers in the programs as well.</p><p><b>Communities</b>. Communities generally make any subsidies they offer corporations contingent on socially responsible policies by the corporation. For example, Tesla received a subsidy of at least 1 billion euros from the German government in 2021 to construct a battery cell factory in Berlin. The government chose to subsidize Tesla to support its production of electric vehicle batteries and help reduce German imports from Chinese suppliers, who were deemed to be less socially responsible, and to support the shift away from fossil fuels.12</p><p><b>Shareholders</b>. Even shareholders themselves might be willing to accept lower returns in exchange for certain CSR policies. A number of different academic models suggest the possibility that sufficient investor demand for CSR could increase the market value of companies perceived to be socially responsible, effectively reducing the companies’ cost of equity capital. Consistent with this possibility, recent academic studies provide evidence of an association between higher CSR and lower costs of equity capital that is accomplished through a tilting of the investor base.13</p><p>The bottom line, then, is that under an organizational design that features shareholder primacy as its objective function, companies will continue to respond to stakeholder demands for CSR that are reflected in the prices at which they contract with the firm. And as long as the costs to the firm of supplying that CSR are lower than the benefits—in the form of higher product prices, lower employee costs, better and more lucrative supplier arrangements, greater community subsidies, and lower costs of capital—CSR policies are likely to benefit shareholders, too.</p><p>Up to this point, I have argued that market forces operating by means of and within the corporate contracting structure led public companies to supply CSR policies that are valued and, in some cases, fully expected and demanded by their stakeholders. But what about CSR for which there is no clear stakeholder demand from within the firm? A reasonable critique of my argument to this point is that not all of the costs and benefits of CSR-related activities are realized (or “internalized”) by the firm and its internal stakeholders. To the extent that a company's stream of profits and the value of its stock reflect the costs, but do not capture all projected CSR benefits, firms will tend to invest less in CSR and, therefore, could be imposing net costs on society that reduce general social welfare.</p><p>The most prominent and commonly cited example of this type of negative economic externality is damage to the environment through, say, pollution generated by a firm's manufacturing process. Because companies bear the full cost of limiting this pollution but share the benefits with society, a policy of maximizing shareholder value will lead them to pollute more than what society would deem to be the optimal level.</p><p>Economists have long recognized that government regulators are generally in the best position to address these types of economic externalities and, in so doing, find the socially most efficient position. However, as noted earlier, the increased demand for corporate action, or CSR, could be interpreted as a byproduct of a general view that governments have not been particularly effective in addressing these externalities. To the extent that is the case, corporate management could be justified in taking a more stakeholder-oriented point of view in which the social impact of corporate policies becomes an explicit part of the corporate objective function.</p><p>But, again, there is a major obstacle to implementing this solution without first securing some kind of general mandate from shareholders—namely the difficulty of taking a purely stakeholder-driven approach to environmental challenges arising from the sheer variety of stakeholders’ preferences themselves with respect to individual CSR policies. As the French “yellow vest” protests might suggest, there are likely to be limits to employees’ willingness to make economic sacrifices for larger social benefits, especially those not expected to materialize in the near future. Put differently, if a company imposes externalities on society when the maximization of shareholder wealth is the objective function, it is probably at least as likely to do so under a stakeholder primacy regime.</p><p>If we cannot count on government regulators to address problems of externalities effectively, and a general stakeholder primacy approach is no better than shareholder primacy in providing the socially optimal CSR policies, what about the possibility that companies simply delegate this role to corporate managers? Such delegation would be broadly consistent with current practices in which managers are already afforded considerable discretion in choosing corporate policies for the purpose of maximizing shareholder wealth. Under this alternative, CEOs would essentially be CSR central planners who, under the business judgment rule, would be granted wide latitude in choosing policies that meet some vaguely specified target of social responsibility.</p><p>Again, however, it is difficult to see how this would work. Delegating to individuals decisions that have already proven too complicated and costly to address through voluntary contracting does not seem at all promising or workable. CEOs are chosen for their specialized expertise in how to produce products demanded by consumers at the lowest price—not for their experience or wisdom in identifying or formulating effective social policy or adjudicating tradeoffs among different stakeholder groups. These are tough decisions even for law-givers and -makers, and to entrust them to corporate managers is a prescription, as Jensen pointed out, for organizational confusion.</p><p>And as Tom Gosling demonstrates in the immediately preceding article about the Walgreens-Boots living wage campaign, asking corporate CEOs to ignore or override labor market pricing when determining what constitutes a “living wage” for the majority of their employees is an invitation to misrule and competitive failure. Such arrogation by top corporate executives of functions normally provided by labor and other factor markets would greatly expand the scope for agency conflicts—or, arguably, open a veritable Pandora's box of them—in which corporate managers would be tempted to use their discretion to make decisions that while making their own lives easier, end up hurting their shareholders and other stakeholders.</p><p>Financial economists, to be sure, have long recognized the potential for conflicts of interest to arise in situations in which agents are performing tasks on behalf of principals. In their seminal article—by far the most cited in the corporate finance literature—Michael Jensen and William Meckling applied the theory of agency costs to the specific setting of the modern public corporation in which there is typically a clear separation between ownership and control of the firm.14 One of the article's key insights is that the value lost from agency conflicts of interest and incentives between corporate executives and their shareholders can be limited through the monitoring of executive behavior by corporate boards and, if and when necessary, active outside investors. But the effectiveness of such monitoring is also bound to be limited in large part because the specialized expertise of managers makes it difficult for board members to be able to identify self-interested, value-reducing behavior on the part of managers. The limits of this monitoring will only become more evident when the scope of managerial discretion is enlarged to include the adoption of socially responsible policies and attempts to “balance” their aims with those of long-run value-maximization.</p><p>My bottom line, then, is that it is difficult to make a compelling case for departing from shareholder primacy as an essential element of the corporate objective function. Nonetheless, as demand for corporate social responsibility grows, companies that seek to enhance shareholder value will be prompted to supply CSR policies by the prices at which they contract with other stakeholders. In a world in which consumers volunteer to pay more for products produced in more socially responsible ways and employees demand higher wages to work for companies viewed as less socially responsible, well-thought-out CSR policies have the potential to contribute to the corporate bottom line. Much the same arguments apply to corporate policies vis a vis other stakeholders like suppliers and communities. In the end, as demand for CSR grows, companies aiming to maximize shareholder wealth will find themselves adopting and implementing more CSR policies.</p><p>To be sure, this should not be taken to imply that the market incentives to supply CSR policies will necessarily result in the socially optimal amount of CSR policies. After all, as I noted earlier, the pursuit of shareholder wealth maximization will continue to produce some corporate externalities such as adverse environmental impacts. And to the extent that regulatory solutions continue to prove inadequate, there will still be residual net costs to society.</p><p>But as I have also pointed out, any pronounced shift away from long-run value maximization is unlikely to improve either the state of the environment or the general economy. Neither increased experimentation with stakeholder capitalism nor granting top executives more leeway in enacting social policy is likely to leave shareholders and the other stakeholders that constitute today's largest corporations collectively better off.</p><p>Just as investors care about the risk and return characteristics of their portfolios more than they care about the risks and returns of the individual stocks that make up the portfolio, the aggregate supply of CSR by public (and private) companies should be more important than the supply by individual firms. For that reason, we should also neither expect (nor insist that) the supply of CSR policies by corporations follow a “one-size-fits-all” approach. To the extent that companies continue to respond to market signals (as they have in the past), they will keep supplying CSR policies whose benefits (in the form of higher product prices, or reductions in labor or capital costs) exceed the costs. Some companies are almost certain to have a comparative advantage in supplying CSR policies, if only because their costs of providing such policies and the associated public goods are significantly lower. Similarly, on the demand side, not all stakeholders have the same demand for CSR policies. For example, not all consumers care about sustainable production processes. Accordingly, we would expect those companies that can deliver CSR policies at the lowest cost to specialize in the provision of such policies—while stakeholders with the strongest preferences for CSR policies (and willingness to pay a premium for them) will tend to gravitate toward, and so benefit and help sustain, the companies supplying the public goods associated with such policies.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":46789,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Journal of Applied Corporate Finance\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.7000,\"publicationDate\":\"2024-06-11\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/jacf.12613\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Journal of Applied Corporate Finance\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/jacf.12613\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q4\",\"JCRName\":\"BUSINESS, FINANCE\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Applied Corporate Finance","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/jacf.12613","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q4","JCRName":"BUSINESS, FINANCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

如果公司的利润流和股票价值反映了成本,但没有反映企业社会责任的所有预期收益,那么公司将倾向于减少在企业社会责任方面的投资,因此,可能会给社会带来净成本,从而减少总体社会福利。这种负面经济外部性最突出和最常被引用的例子是公司生产过程中产生的污染对环境造成的破坏。经济学家早已认识到,政府监管机构通常最有能力解决这类经济外部性问题,并在此过程中找到最有效的社会定位。然而,如前所述,对企业行动或企业社会责任的需求增加,可以解释为一种普遍观点的副产品,即政府在解决这些外部性问题方面并不特别有效。在这种情况下,企业管理层有理由采取更加以利益相关者为导向的观点,使企业政策的社会影响成为企业目标函数的一个明确部分。但是,如果不首先获得股东的某种普遍授权,要实施这一解决方案同样会遇到重大障碍--即由于利益相关者本身对个别企业社会责任政策的偏好千差万别,因此很难采取纯粹以利益相关者为导向的方法来应对环境挑战。正如法国 "黄背心 "抗议活动所表明的那样,员工愿意为更大的社会效益做出经济牺牲是有限度的,尤其是那些预计不会在短期内实现的社会效益。换句话说,当股东财富最大化是公司的目标函数时,如果公司将外部性强加给社会,那么在利益相关者优先的制度下,公司至少也有可能这样做。如果我们不能指望政府监管机构有效解决外部性问题,而且在提供社会最优企业社会责任政策方面,一般的利益相关者优先方法并不比股东优先方法更好,那么公司将这一角色简单地委托给公司经理人的可能性又如何呢?这种授权与目前的做法大体一致,即管理者在选择公司政策时已被赋予相当大的自由裁量权,以实现股东财富最大化。根据这一替代方案,首席执行官实质上是企业社会责任的中央规划者,根据商业判断规则,他们在选择政策时将被赋予很大的自由度,以达到某种模糊指定的社会责任目标。把那些已经证明过于复杂、成本过高、无法通过自愿签约来解决的决策权下放给个人,似乎根本没有希望,也不可行。之所以选择首席执行官,是因为他们在如何以最低的价格生产消费者所需的产品方面具有专业知识,而不是因为他们在确定或制定有效的社会政策或裁定不同利益相关群体之间的权衡方面具有经验或智慧。正如汤姆-高斯林(Tom Gosling)在前一篇关于沃尔格林-博茨(Walgreens-Boots)"生活工资 "运动的文章中所指出的那样,要求企业首席执行官在决定什么是大多数员工的 "生活工资 "时忽视或凌驾于劳动力市场定价之上,只会导致管理失误和竞争失败。企业高管如此僭越通常由劳动力市场和其他要素市场提供的职能,将极大地扩大代理冲突的范围--或者可以说,打开了一个名副其实的潘多拉盒子--企业管理者将受到诱惑,利用他们的自由裁量权做出决策,虽然使他们自己的生活更轻松,但最终却损害了股东和其他利益相关者的利益。迈克尔-詹森(Michael Jensen)和威廉-梅克林(William Meckling)在他们的开创性文章--也是迄今为止公司财务文献中被引用最多的文章--中将代理成本理论应用于现代上市公司的特定环境中,在这种环境中,公司的所有权和控制权通常是明确分离的。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Corporate social responsibility and the shareholder primacy paradigm

Recent years have witnessed an explosion in the attention paid to the notion of corporate social responsibility (CSR), the idea that corporations have an obligation to consider the impact of their decisions on a broad set of stakeholders that extends well beyond their investors. Such social concerns are by no means new; they were matters for corporate boardroom and top management discussions long before Milton Friedman published his famous editorial on the social responsibility of business.1 Nonetheless, for at least the past decade and since the passing of the Global Financial Crisis, CSR advocates have more vigorously pursued their mission of incorporating social concerns within the purview of corporate decision-making.

But why so much corporate attention to social matters now? Three possibilities come to mind. First, the urgency of social concerns and the perceived ability of and expectation that corporations will do something about them have increased over time as public companies have become steadily larger and their reach more global. Climate change is the prototype of a social issue whose urgency and scope continue to grow over time. Second is the possibility that, although the social concerns themselves have not changed much over time, individual preferences have changed and various stakeholders have become more sensitive to those concerns than before. A third possibility is that, although social concerns tend to arise from negative “externalities” that most economists assume are best managed through government regulation, growing or widespread skepticism about the ability of government institutions to address these concerns in cost-effective ways could lead to increased demand for corporate investment in addressing social challenges.

Regardless of the reason for the increased attention to CSR, it is almost invariably accompanied by calls for rethinking the idea of shareholder primacy in the corporate objective function. In this article, I address the question of whether the increased focus on CSR requires a paradigm shift away from the traditional shareholder primacy model toward one that gives more voice to stakeholders. My short answer to this question is no, and for three main reasons:

First, the increased focus on CSR has virtually nothing to do with the factors that led to the establishment of shareholder primacy as the dominant paradigm. The theory of shareholder primacy which is a cornerstone of modern corporate finance arose as an efficient solution to “contracting” problems faced by corporations that have a diverse set of stakeholders, each of which often has different preferences about what and how certain corporate decisions get made.2 Such contracting problems—which have long been, and will always be, with us—are likely to become even more intractable with the rising demand for CSR. Which leads to the suggestion: if we thought that shareholder primacy was part of an efficient organizational structure before the ascent of CSR, it may well be even more critical to corporate sustainability and success in the future.

Second, to the extent there is demand for CSR from investors and other stakeholders, market forces work to ensure that such demand is met even when shareholder primacy is an essential element of the corporate objective function. Such market forces take the form of consumer demand, employee preferences, and even investor preferences that lead public companies to devote time and capital to CSR initiatives as part of an overall objective of maximizing the wealth of their stockholders.

Third, and perhaps most importantly, a widespread corporate movement away from shareholder primacy toward a model dedicated to, say, stakeholder primacy is likely to produce “agency” and other contracting costs that exceed any CSR benefits to investors and other stakeholders.

The idea of shareholder primacy is rooted in the contracting framework of corporations that was developed by people like Michael Jensen and William Meckling in their seminal study published in the Journal of Financial Economics, as well as a pair of papers published by Jensen and Eugene Fama in the Journal of Law and Economics.3 These finance scholars view the corporation as a legal fiction that is best represented as “a nexus of contracts” among customers and all the different “factors of production,” including suppliers of labor and capital and other stakeholders, that affect, and in turn are affected by, the corporation.

Given this view of the firm, how companies end up being organized and structured is seen as the outcome of a competitive process in which all kinds of commercial enterprises, from sole proprietorships to global multinationals, attempt to supply the products demanded by customers at the lowest possible prices while covering all the costs incurred. Among such costs are those involved in managing the contracts among all the different parties to the firm.

The contracting structure that emerges from what amounts to a society-wide process of negotiation ends up specifying two things: (1) the payoffs to all stakeholders—that is, who gets what and when; and (2) the distribution of “decision rights”—who gets to make what decisions inside the firm. The goal of this process is to find and implement the contractual set-up that enables the firm to compete most effectively in the marketplace. And barring the case of externalities (which we take up later), the conclusion of most economists and (free-market) policymakers is that such competition ends up leading to the socially optimal use of the resources—notably, people and capital—involved.

How does such a process lead to shareholder primacy as the dominant paradigm? Corporations, as already noted, are best viewed as temporary, or at least finite-lived, associations among many different stakeholder groups—customers, suppliers, creditors, labor, communities, stockholders—with economic interests in and claims on the firm. In a widely cited paper published in 1960 titled “The Problem of Social Cost,” Nobel laureate Ronald Coase showed that when the writing and enforcement of contracts are assumed to be costless, the optimal decision rule in such a situation is to aim to maximize the combined welfare of all the major stakeholder groups. Having identified the corporate objective as maximizing the size of the aggregate payoffs (or the “total pie,” if you will) that can be divided among them, the function of the contracts is then the most efficient distribution of the resulting wealth among the various stakeholders—and by “most efficient” we mean the one that leads most predictably to the highest collective outcome.4

In practice, of course, contracts are neither costless to write nor to enforce. And what is particularly important in the context of a corporation is that the various stakeholders have a potentially broad range of (often conflicting) preferences about corporate decisions, and the associated size and risk of the resulting payoffs. For example, whereas lower-level employees are likely to favor low-risk operating policies that reduce the probability of job losses (even those with lower expected returns), well-diversified shareholders may well favor higher-risk policies with higher expected returns. Faced with such a wide set of stakeholders with different interests and preferences, large organizations would find it very costly indeed to try to accommodate this range of preferences by writing separate, highly customized contracts (although some of this no doubt goes on in some companies).

But the bottom line is that the public corporate organizational form that prevails in most developed economies today can and should be viewed as the solution to this contracting problem—a solution that has evolved, and continues to evolve, over time to maximize the productive output of the corporate form while minimizing the contracting costs inherent in it.

The dominant form of today's public corporation has three important features worth noting in this context. First, most stakeholders that are also factors of production (notably, employees and suppliers, as well as creditors) have contracts that specify fixed promised payoffs or incentive payoffs that are tied to very specific performance outcomes and metrics. However, the fact that most such contracts have fixed promised payoffs does not mean that the payoffs are without risk. Each of these parties effectively assumes some risk that is tied to the priority structure of the payoffs and that is reflected in the size of the fixed promised payoff. So, for example, because creditors are paid only after employees’ claims are taken care of, the promised payment to creditors includes a “premium” to compensate them for the risk of default on their payments.

Second, after the claims of all the other stakeholders have been satisfied, the remaining, or residual, risk of the corporation is borne by one set of stakeholders—the shareholders—who have contracted to receive the net cash flows, those that remain after all other claimants to those cash flows have received their promised payment.

Third, decision rights are vested in shareholders, the parties who bear the residual risk. Moreover, because these decision rights are exercised by the corporation's top executive team acting as agents of the shareholders, corporate boards have evolved as a governance mechanism that monitors the behavior of these agents to ensure their decisions are made in the best interest of shareholders.

Understood in these terms, then, shareholder primacy represents a competitive solution to the problem of maximizing the collective stakeholder welfare in a way that minimizes the various contracting costs associated with so doing. There is nothing that forces corporations to be organized this way. Other possible forms of business organization that have long been, and can still be, observed in the United States and elsewhere are private partnerships owned and managed by their main capital providers, mutual organizations owned and run by their largest customers (most notably in the insurance industry), and cooperatives, like the local Agway, in which the big investment and distribution decisions are made by boards representing and composed entirely of local customers and employees.

But, again, the fact that the public corporation has come to dominate commercial activity in all of the world's developed economies suggests that it has been found to be the most economically efficient for most large-scale business enterprise.

And this brings us to one important, and widespread, misconception about shareholder primacy and the corporate form of organization—namely, that the interests of stakeholders other than the stockholders are routinely ignored or taken for granted. The reality, as we have just seen, is that such stakeholder groups explicitly contract for their payoff upfront, in most cases ensuring their senior-most priority among corporate distributions. And so whatever controversy continues to surround the corporate treatment of its non-investor stakeholders, the controversy is ultimately about not the existence, but the adequacy, of those payoffs they have already contracted for.

How do these distinctive features of the public corporation—fixed, high-priority payoffs to stakeholders, and residual risk bearing and decision-making by shareholders (and boards)—work to make the resulting organizational form the most efficient? The work of Fama and Jensen cited earlier offers several insights. First, by allowing for most of the risk of the company to be borne by shareholders, this structure makes possible specialization and efficiencies in risk-bearing by effectively ensuring that the people who supply the bulk of the savings for corporate capital investment are not the same ones making the organization-specific commitments that are required of and made by, say, the company's employees or suppliers. Precisely because a company's shareholders can more effectively diversify their personal risk than can its managers or employees, it will generally turn out to be more efficient to have them bear the residual risk of the firm.

Second, by limiting the risks faced by most corporate stakeholders, the costs associated with writing and monitoring (and, when necessary, modifying) the firm's contracts with those stakeholders (say, in response to changes in those risks) are kept to a minimum.

Third, these lower contracting costs both increase the company's net cash flows and, in so doing, contribute to corporate staying power by enabling companies to deliver their products at lower prices (while providing higher shareholder returns and collective payoffs to non-investor stakeholders) than would otherwise be possible.

But now let us turn to the main subject of this paper: If investors’ preferences are now reflecting today's greater demand for CSR, does this change anything about the efficient contractual structure of the firm? To address that question, it is useful to start by considering the possible effects of CSR policies on corporate decision-making and shareholders.

Some policies that fall under the CSR umbrella arguably can be expected to increase the present value of corporate net cash flows and therefore the value of shareholders’ claims. For example, think about sustainable production processes (e.g., free-range chickens) for which there is high consumer demand. To the extent consumers are willing to pay a premium price that exceeds the marginal costs of providing that sustainable production process, it is clearly in the interests of shareholders to adopt such a policy.

A second possibility, however, is CSR policies that reduce the present value of the firm's net cash flows while failing to improve the welfare of any of the firm's stakeholders. For example, some commentators have argued that the recent climate disclosure rules promulgated by the Securities and Exchange Commission (SEC) impose significant costs on companies and their shareholders without any offsetting benefits in limiting climate change.5

A third category of CSR policies includes those that are arguably the most interesting from a public policy standpoint: those that are expected to reduce the present value of corporate net cash flows while increasing the welfare of some stakeholders—and possibly even some shareholders themselves. Such cases involve a sacrifice, or tradeoff, of shareholder for stakeholder value for some allegedly greater social good. But the question is, which party gets to make that decision, and how do they justify it to the shareholders who are being asked to make the sacrifice? An example of this type of CSR policy might be green energy solutions that raise the company's overall cost of production.

With these categories in mind, the question then becomes whether an objective function such as stakeholder primacy would do a better job than the traditional shareholder primacy of sorting among these different CSR policies.

Although I have already suggested that increased demand for CSR does not alter the conclusion that shareholder primacy is part of an efficient organizational contracting structure, it is important to note that this does not mean that stakeholder preferences for CSR are simply ignored. In fact, quite the contrary. Such preferences are directly captured and reflected in the fixed payoffs, or market prices, that stakeholders contract for when negotiating with the firm. In this sense, even under shareholder primacy, market forces can be seen as pushing companies to meet stakeholder demands for CSR.

Customers. Let us start with the case of product markets and how they reflect the preferences of consumers. A company's customers have often shown themselves willing to pay price premiums for products made by companies that adopt what consumers view as more socially responsible policies. In a recent survey of its consumers, Whole Foods found that nearly two-thirds of millennials view transparency in food sourcing as informing their food purchases. Expressing a commitment to work more plant-based and unprocessed foods into their diet, and to consider the effects of these choices on the environment, millennials also indicated their willingness to pay more for “high-quality” foods.7 If this price premium is large enough, a company like Whole Foods is more than willing to meet this particular CSR demand, with the expectation in so doing of maximizing its own long-run shareholder and firm value.

Employees. In the case of labor markets, employees demand higher wages to work for companies they view as less socially responsible—or alternatively, they willingly accept lower wages to work for companies that are better aligned with their CSR goals. One often cited example is Patagonia, where employees are notoriously low-paid, but nonetheless appear happy to work for a company whose mission includes doing good for the planet. Similarly, Tesla and SpaceX are known to have employee pay that is low relative to tech industry standards, but nonetheless have employees with high rates of job satisfaction who describe their work as “highly meaningful.”8

As another example, the shoe manufacturer Allbirds requires its suppliers to adhere to a “Supplier Code of Conduct” that specifies the company's social and environmental standards.11 All of the company's Tier 1 suppliers are enrolled in its Social Audit and Environmental Programs, and the firm's stated goal is to have 100% of its Tier 2 suppliers in the programs as well.

Communities. Communities generally make any subsidies they offer corporations contingent on socially responsible policies by the corporation. For example, Tesla received a subsidy of at least 1 billion euros from the German government in 2021 to construct a battery cell factory in Berlin. The government chose to subsidize Tesla to support its production of electric vehicle batteries and help reduce German imports from Chinese suppliers, who were deemed to be less socially responsible, and to support the shift away from fossil fuels.12

Shareholders. Even shareholders themselves might be willing to accept lower returns in exchange for certain CSR policies. A number of different academic models suggest the possibility that sufficient investor demand for CSR could increase the market value of companies perceived to be socially responsible, effectively reducing the companies’ cost of equity capital. Consistent with this possibility, recent academic studies provide evidence of an association between higher CSR and lower costs of equity capital that is accomplished through a tilting of the investor base.13

The bottom line, then, is that under an organizational design that features shareholder primacy as its objective function, companies will continue to respond to stakeholder demands for CSR that are reflected in the prices at which they contract with the firm. And as long as the costs to the firm of supplying that CSR are lower than the benefits—in the form of higher product prices, lower employee costs, better and more lucrative supplier arrangements, greater community subsidies, and lower costs of capital—CSR policies are likely to benefit shareholders, too.

Up to this point, I have argued that market forces operating by means of and within the corporate contracting structure led public companies to supply CSR policies that are valued and, in some cases, fully expected and demanded by their stakeholders. But what about CSR for which there is no clear stakeholder demand from within the firm? A reasonable critique of my argument to this point is that not all of the costs and benefits of CSR-related activities are realized (or “internalized”) by the firm and its internal stakeholders. To the extent that a company's stream of profits and the value of its stock reflect the costs, but do not capture all projected CSR benefits, firms will tend to invest less in CSR and, therefore, could be imposing net costs on society that reduce general social welfare.

The most prominent and commonly cited example of this type of negative economic externality is damage to the environment through, say, pollution generated by a firm's manufacturing process. Because companies bear the full cost of limiting this pollution but share the benefits with society, a policy of maximizing shareholder value will lead them to pollute more than what society would deem to be the optimal level.

Economists have long recognized that government regulators are generally in the best position to address these types of economic externalities and, in so doing, find the socially most efficient position. However, as noted earlier, the increased demand for corporate action, or CSR, could be interpreted as a byproduct of a general view that governments have not been particularly effective in addressing these externalities. To the extent that is the case, corporate management could be justified in taking a more stakeholder-oriented point of view in which the social impact of corporate policies becomes an explicit part of the corporate objective function.

But, again, there is a major obstacle to implementing this solution without first securing some kind of general mandate from shareholders—namely the difficulty of taking a purely stakeholder-driven approach to environmental challenges arising from the sheer variety of stakeholders’ preferences themselves with respect to individual CSR policies. As the French “yellow vest” protests might suggest, there are likely to be limits to employees’ willingness to make economic sacrifices for larger social benefits, especially those not expected to materialize in the near future. Put differently, if a company imposes externalities on society when the maximization of shareholder wealth is the objective function, it is probably at least as likely to do so under a stakeholder primacy regime.

If we cannot count on government regulators to address problems of externalities effectively, and a general stakeholder primacy approach is no better than shareholder primacy in providing the socially optimal CSR policies, what about the possibility that companies simply delegate this role to corporate managers? Such delegation would be broadly consistent with current practices in which managers are already afforded considerable discretion in choosing corporate policies for the purpose of maximizing shareholder wealth. Under this alternative, CEOs would essentially be CSR central planners who, under the business judgment rule, would be granted wide latitude in choosing policies that meet some vaguely specified target of social responsibility.

Again, however, it is difficult to see how this would work. Delegating to individuals decisions that have already proven too complicated and costly to address through voluntary contracting does not seem at all promising or workable. CEOs are chosen for their specialized expertise in how to produce products demanded by consumers at the lowest price—not for their experience or wisdom in identifying or formulating effective social policy or adjudicating tradeoffs among different stakeholder groups. These are tough decisions even for law-givers and -makers, and to entrust them to corporate managers is a prescription, as Jensen pointed out, for organizational confusion.

And as Tom Gosling demonstrates in the immediately preceding article about the Walgreens-Boots living wage campaign, asking corporate CEOs to ignore or override labor market pricing when determining what constitutes a “living wage” for the majority of their employees is an invitation to misrule and competitive failure. Such arrogation by top corporate executives of functions normally provided by labor and other factor markets would greatly expand the scope for agency conflicts—or, arguably, open a veritable Pandora's box of them—in which corporate managers would be tempted to use their discretion to make decisions that while making their own lives easier, end up hurting their shareholders and other stakeholders.

Financial economists, to be sure, have long recognized the potential for conflicts of interest to arise in situations in which agents are performing tasks on behalf of principals. In their seminal article—by far the most cited in the corporate finance literature—Michael Jensen and William Meckling applied the theory of agency costs to the specific setting of the modern public corporation in which there is typically a clear separation between ownership and control of the firm.14 One of the article's key insights is that the value lost from agency conflicts of interest and incentives between corporate executives and their shareholders can be limited through the monitoring of executive behavior by corporate boards and, if and when necessary, active outside investors. But the effectiveness of such monitoring is also bound to be limited in large part because the specialized expertise of managers makes it difficult for board members to be able to identify self-interested, value-reducing behavior on the part of managers. The limits of this monitoring will only become more evident when the scope of managerial discretion is enlarged to include the adoption of socially responsible policies and attempts to “balance” their aims with those of long-run value-maximization.

My bottom line, then, is that it is difficult to make a compelling case for departing from shareholder primacy as an essential element of the corporate objective function. Nonetheless, as demand for corporate social responsibility grows, companies that seek to enhance shareholder value will be prompted to supply CSR policies by the prices at which they contract with other stakeholders. In a world in which consumers volunteer to pay more for products produced in more socially responsible ways and employees demand higher wages to work for companies viewed as less socially responsible, well-thought-out CSR policies have the potential to contribute to the corporate bottom line. Much the same arguments apply to corporate policies vis a vis other stakeholders like suppliers and communities. In the end, as demand for CSR grows, companies aiming to maximize shareholder wealth will find themselves adopting and implementing more CSR policies.

To be sure, this should not be taken to imply that the market incentives to supply CSR policies will necessarily result in the socially optimal amount of CSR policies. After all, as I noted earlier, the pursuit of shareholder wealth maximization will continue to produce some corporate externalities such as adverse environmental impacts. And to the extent that regulatory solutions continue to prove inadequate, there will still be residual net costs to society.

But as I have also pointed out, any pronounced shift away from long-run value maximization is unlikely to improve either the state of the environment or the general economy. Neither increased experimentation with stakeholder capitalism nor granting top executives more leeway in enacting social policy is likely to leave shareholders and the other stakeholders that constitute today's largest corporations collectively better off.

Just as investors care about the risk and return characteristics of their portfolios more than they care about the risks and returns of the individual stocks that make up the portfolio, the aggregate supply of CSR by public (and private) companies should be more important than the supply by individual firms. For that reason, we should also neither expect (nor insist that) the supply of CSR policies by corporations follow a “one-size-fits-all” approach. To the extent that companies continue to respond to market signals (as they have in the past), they will keep supplying CSR policies whose benefits (in the form of higher product prices, or reductions in labor or capital costs) exceed the costs. Some companies are almost certain to have a comparative advantage in supplying CSR policies, if only because their costs of providing such policies and the associated public goods are significantly lower. Similarly, on the demand side, not all stakeholders have the same demand for CSR policies. For example, not all consumers care about sustainable production processes. Accordingly, we would expect those companies that can deliver CSR policies at the lowest cost to specialize in the provision of such policies—while stakeholders with the strongest preferences for CSR policies (and willingness to pay a premium for them) will tend to gravitate toward, and so benefit and help sustain, the companies supplying the public goods associated with such policies.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
11.10%
发文量
44
期刊最新文献
Michael C. Jensen: Scholar, mentor, colleague Michael Jensen's contributions to the theory of the firm: A tribute in three acts A message from the editor Issue Information - TOC A message from the Editors
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1