绿灯伦理:允许同意理论及其道德形而上学》,作者 Hallie Liberto(评论)

IF 1.1 4区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal Pub Date : 2024-07-02 DOI:10.1353/ken.2023.a931054
Jonathan Ichikawa
{"title":"绿灯伦理:允许同意理论及其道德形而上学》,作者 Hallie Liberto(评论)","authors":"Jonathan Ichikawa","doi":"10.1353/ken.2023.a931054","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<span><span>In lieu of</span> an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:</span>\n<p> <span>Reviewed by:</span> <ul> <li><!-- html_title --> <em>Green Light Ethics: A Theory of Permissive Consent and its Moral Metaphysics</em> by Hallie Liberto <!-- /html_title --></li> <li> Jonathan Ichikawa (bio) </li> </ul> Review of Hallie Liberto, <em>Green Light Ethics: A Theory of Permissive Consent and its Moral Metaphysics</em> (Oxford University Press, 2022) <p>Hallie Liberto's <em>Green Light Ethics</em> offers a framework for conceptualizing permissive consent. The book is a philosopher's work of philosophy. Although it touches on non-ideal social realities, especially sexism, it is most centrally a contribution to a quite abstract literature in normative ethics, following in the tradition of scholars like David Owens, Heidi Hurd, Alan Wertheimer, and Tom Dougherty—it may have a few too many Φs and abstractions to be accessible to and comfortable for many people outside the analytic philosophical tradition. The central approach to permission and consent is general—not specific to sexual consent—although some discussions are specific to sex.</p> <p>I have always appreciated and learned from Liberto's work on this topic, and I was excited to read her new book. As I'd hoped, it exhibits fresh and interesting moral and philosophical instincts, and advances plausible and interesting ideas. I did feel, however, that it was sometimes more difficult than one might hope to identify exactly what those ideas are. At key points, I found myself wanting more precision or explanation. I am not the kind of philosopher who shuns abstraction—I value both the concrete/non-ideal and the theoretical/abstract. And I'm not afraid of all those Φs. But as I see it, the point of writing in that mode—the reason it can be worth the cost in accessibility and style—is the ability to express and examine complex ideas with a high degree of precision. As I was reading this book, I found that much of my own intellectual contribution centered around attempts to interpret Liberto's ideas and technicalities before I was in a good position to learn from them. This was a bit of a shame, because there <em>are</em> intriguing ideas in this book, well worthy of consideration. I'll give my own reconstruction of a few of them below, along with some critical engagement.</p> <h2><small>1. domain authority</small></h2> <p>Liberto posits that there are certain domains over which people hold a special kind of moral authority, which she calls \"domain authority\" (38). Someone would wrong you if they acted in your domains outside of your normative control. For example, you have domain authority over sexual contact with your body; any actions by others within that domain must <strong>[End Page 429]</strong> be in accordance with your moral control, or they are violative. Liberto typically uses the following abbreviations to discuss domain authority: <em>S</em> is a person who may or may not be giving <em>P</em> permission to Φ, which is a potential action that <em>P</em> might perform. Φ here is always an action within <em>D</em>, a particular domain of <em>S</em>'s moral authority. Since Φ is within <em>D</em>, Φ would wrong <em>S</em> if <em>P</em> Φ'd without <em>S</em>'s appropriate authorization.</p> <p>In the case of sexual domain rights, <em>D</em> is <em>S</em>'s bodily sexual domain; <em>P</em> would wrong <em>S</em> by performing some act Φ within that domain outside of <em>S</em>'s authority. (Φ might be sexually penetrating <em>S</em>, for example.) The framework generalizes. <em>D</em> might be my home, and Φ could stand for potential actions within my home for which any <em>S</em> would need my permission: entering it, say, or drilling a hole in the wall. I'll follow Liberto's use for these abbreviations. Note that Φ will always refer to an act within <em>S</em>'s domain <em>D</em>.</p> <p>One of the more distinctive contributions of Liberto's framework is her insistence that subjects <em>retain</em> their domain authority, even as they exercise it to permit action within their domains (42). When <em>S</em> consents to Φ, Liberto says, <em>S</em> does not <em>waive any rights against</em> Φ. If they did, Φ would no longer be part of <em>S</em>'s domain of authority <em>D</em>. It is possible to waive rights in this way—this is what happens with property transfers. But Liberto argues that things are quite different for permissive consent (61). If I invite <em>P</em> into my home, or permit <em>P</em> to touch me sexually, they may do so without violating...</p> </p>","PeriodicalId":46167,"journal":{"name":"Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.1000,"publicationDate":"2024-07-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Green Light Ethics: A Theory of Permissive Consent and its Moral Metaphysics by Hallie Liberto (review)\",\"authors\":\"Jonathan Ichikawa\",\"doi\":\"10.1353/ken.2023.a931054\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<span><span>In lieu of</span> an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:</span>\\n<p> <span>Reviewed by:</span> <ul> <li><!-- html_title --> <em>Green Light Ethics: A Theory of Permissive Consent and its Moral Metaphysics</em> by Hallie Liberto <!-- /html_title --></li> <li> Jonathan Ichikawa (bio) </li> </ul> Review of Hallie Liberto, <em>Green Light Ethics: A Theory of Permissive Consent and its Moral Metaphysics</em> (Oxford University Press, 2022) <p>Hallie Liberto's <em>Green Light Ethics</em> offers a framework for conceptualizing permissive consent. The book is a philosopher's work of philosophy. Although it touches on non-ideal social realities, especially sexism, it is most centrally a contribution to a quite abstract literature in normative ethics, following in the tradition of scholars like David Owens, Heidi Hurd, Alan Wertheimer, and Tom Dougherty—it may have a few too many Φs and abstractions to be accessible to and comfortable for many people outside the analytic philosophical tradition. The central approach to permission and consent is general—not specific to sexual consent—although some discussions are specific to sex.</p> <p>I have always appreciated and learned from Liberto's work on this topic, and I was excited to read her new book. As I'd hoped, it exhibits fresh and interesting moral and philosophical instincts, and advances plausible and interesting ideas. I did feel, however, that it was sometimes more difficult than one might hope to identify exactly what those ideas are. At key points, I found myself wanting more precision or explanation. I am not the kind of philosopher who shuns abstraction—I value both the concrete/non-ideal and the theoretical/abstract. And I'm not afraid of all those Φs. But as I see it, the point of writing in that mode—the reason it can be worth the cost in accessibility and style—is the ability to express and examine complex ideas with a high degree of precision. As I was reading this book, I found that much of my own intellectual contribution centered around attempts to interpret Liberto's ideas and technicalities before I was in a good position to learn from them. This was a bit of a shame, because there <em>are</em> intriguing ideas in this book, well worthy of consideration. I'll give my own reconstruction of a few of them below, along with some critical engagement.</p> <h2><small>1. domain authority</small></h2> <p>Liberto posits that there are certain domains over which people hold a special kind of moral authority, which she calls \\\"domain authority\\\" (38). Someone would wrong you if they acted in your domains outside of your normative control. For example, you have domain authority over sexual contact with your body; any actions by others within that domain must <strong>[End Page 429]</strong> be in accordance with your moral control, or they are violative. Liberto typically uses the following abbreviations to discuss domain authority: <em>S</em> is a person who may or may not be giving <em>P</em> permission to Φ, which is a potential action that <em>P</em> might perform. Φ here is always an action within <em>D</em>, a particular domain of <em>S</em>'s moral authority. Since Φ is within <em>D</em>, Φ would wrong <em>S</em> if <em>P</em> Φ'd without <em>S</em>'s appropriate authorization.</p> <p>In the case of sexual domain rights, <em>D</em> is <em>S</em>'s bodily sexual domain; <em>P</em> would wrong <em>S</em> by performing some act Φ within that domain outside of <em>S</em>'s authority. (Φ might be sexually penetrating <em>S</em>, for example.) The framework generalizes. <em>D</em> might be my home, and Φ could stand for potential actions within my home for which any <em>S</em> would need my permission: entering it, say, or drilling a hole in the wall. I'll follow Liberto's use for these abbreviations. Note that Φ will always refer to an act within <em>S</em>'s domain <em>D</em>.</p> <p>One of the more distinctive contributions of Liberto's framework is her insistence that subjects <em>retain</em> their domain authority, even as they exercise it to permit action within their domains (42). When <em>S</em> consents to Φ, Liberto says, <em>S</em> does not <em>waive any rights against</em> Φ. If they did, Φ would no longer be part of <em>S</em>'s domain of authority <em>D</em>. It is possible to waive rights in this way—this is what happens with property transfers. But Liberto argues that things are quite different for permissive consent (61). If I invite <em>P</em> into my home, or permit <em>P</em> to touch me sexually, they may do so without violating...</p> </p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":46167,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":1.1000,\"publicationDate\":\"2024-07-02\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"98\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1353/ken.2023.a931054\",\"RegionNum\":4,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"ETHICS\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal","FirstCategoryId":"98","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ken.2023.a931054","RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"ETHICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

以下是内容的简要摘录,以代替摘要:审稿人: 绿灯伦理:哈莉-利贝托著的《许可同意理论及其道德形而上学》 乔纳森-市川(Jonathan Ichikawa)(简历) 哈莉-利贝托著的《绿光伦理学》评论:Hallie Liberto 的《绿灯伦理学》为 "许可同意 "的概念化提供了一个框架。该书是一部哲学家的哲学著作。虽然它涉及了非理想的社会现实,尤其是性别歧视,但它最核心的是对规范伦理学中相当抽象的文献的贡献,继承了大卫-欧文斯、海蒂-赫德、艾伦-韦特海默和汤姆-多尔蒂等学者的传统--它可能有一些太多的Φ和抽象概念,让许多分析哲学传统之外的人难以理解和接受。关于许可和同意的核心方法是一般性的,而不是专门针对性同意的,尽管有些讨论是专门针对性的。我一直很欣赏利贝托在这一主题上的工作,也从她那里学到了很多东西,所以我很高兴能读到她的新书。正如我所希望的那样,这本书展现了新颖有趣的道德和哲学本能,提出了合理有趣的观点。然而,我确实感觉到,有时要确定这些观点到底是什么比想象中要困难得多。在一些关键点上,我发现自己需要更精确的解释或说明。我不是那种回避抽象的哲学家,我既重视具体/非理想,也重视理论/抽象。我也不惧怕那些Φ。但在我看来,以这种模式写作的意义--它之所以值得在易读性和风格上付出代价--在于能够高度精确地表达和审视复杂的观点。在读这本书的过程中,我发现自己的大部分知识贡献都集中在试图解释利贝托的观点和技术细节上,而我还没有来得及从中学到东西。这有点遗憾,因为这本书中的观点耐人寻味,非常值得思考。我将在下文中对其中几个观点进行重构,并提出一些批评意见。1. 领域权威 利贝托认为,在某些领域,人们拥有一种特殊的道德权威,她称之为 "领域权威"(38)。如果有人在你的规范控制之外的领域行事,他就会错怪你。例如,你对与自己身体的性接触拥有领域权威;他人在该领域内的任何行为都必须 [完 第 429 页] 符合你的道德控制,否则就是侵犯。利伯托通常使用以下缩写来讨论领域权威:S 是一个人,他可能允许或不允许 P 执行 Φ,而 Φ 是 P 可能执行的潜在行动。这里的 Φ 总是 D(S 的道德权威的特定领域)范围内的行动。由于 Φ 是在 D 的范围内,如果 P 在没有得到 S 的适当授权的情况下实施了 Φ,那么 Φ 就会使 S 感到错误。就性领域权而言,D 是 S 的身体性领域;如果 P 在 S 的授权之外在该领域内实施某种行为 Φ,就会对 S 造成伤害。(例如,Φ 可能是对 S 进行性插入。D 可以是我的家,而 Φ 可以代表在我家里的潜在行为,任何 S 都需要得到我的许可:比如说,进入我家,或者在墙上钻个洞。我将沿用利贝托对这些缩写的用法。请注意,Φ 总是指 S 的领域 D 内的行为。利伯托框架的一个更独特的贡献是,她坚持认为主体保留其领域权威,即使他们行使权威允许在其领域内的行为(42)。利伯托说,当 S 同意 Φ 时,S 并没有放弃任何针对 Φ 的权利。如果放弃了,Φ 就不再是 S 的权威领域 D 的一部分了。但利伯托认为,许可同意的情况则完全不同(61)。如果我邀请 P 进入我的家,或允许 P 对我进行性接触,他们可以这样做而不违反......
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Green Light Ethics: A Theory of Permissive Consent and its Moral Metaphysics by Hallie Liberto (review)
In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:

Reviewed by:

  • Green Light Ethics: A Theory of Permissive Consent and its Moral Metaphysics by Hallie Liberto
  • Jonathan Ichikawa (bio)
Review of Hallie Liberto, Green Light Ethics: A Theory of Permissive Consent and its Moral Metaphysics (Oxford University Press, 2022)

Hallie Liberto's Green Light Ethics offers a framework for conceptualizing permissive consent. The book is a philosopher's work of philosophy. Although it touches on non-ideal social realities, especially sexism, it is most centrally a contribution to a quite abstract literature in normative ethics, following in the tradition of scholars like David Owens, Heidi Hurd, Alan Wertheimer, and Tom Dougherty—it may have a few too many Φs and abstractions to be accessible to and comfortable for many people outside the analytic philosophical tradition. The central approach to permission and consent is general—not specific to sexual consent—although some discussions are specific to sex.

I have always appreciated and learned from Liberto's work on this topic, and I was excited to read her new book. As I'd hoped, it exhibits fresh and interesting moral and philosophical instincts, and advances plausible and interesting ideas. I did feel, however, that it was sometimes more difficult than one might hope to identify exactly what those ideas are. At key points, I found myself wanting more precision or explanation. I am not the kind of philosopher who shuns abstraction—I value both the concrete/non-ideal and the theoretical/abstract. And I'm not afraid of all those Φs. But as I see it, the point of writing in that mode—the reason it can be worth the cost in accessibility and style—is the ability to express and examine complex ideas with a high degree of precision. As I was reading this book, I found that much of my own intellectual contribution centered around attempts to interpret Liberto's ideas and technicalities before I was in a good position to learn from them. This was a bit of a shame, because there are intriguing ideas in this book, well worthy of consideration. I'll give my own reconstruction of a few of them below, along with some critical engagement.

1. domain authority

Liberto posits that there are certain domains over which people hold a special kind of moral authority, which she calls "domain authority" (38). Someone would wrong you if they acted in your domains outside of your normative control. For example, you have domain authority over sexual contact with your body; any actions by others within that domain must [End Page 429] be in accordance with your moral control, or they are violative. Liberto typically uses the following abbreviations to discuss domain authority: S is a person who may or may not be giving P permission to Φ, which is a potential action that P might perform. Φ here is always an action within D, a particular domain of S's moral authority. Since Φ is within D, Φ would wrong S if P Φ'd without S's appropriate authorization.

In the case of sexual domain rights, D is S's bodily sexual domain; P would wrong S by performing some act Φ within that domain outside of S's authority. (Φ might be sexually penetrating S, for example.) The framework generalizes. D might be my home, and Φ could stand for potential actions within my home for which any S would need my permission: entering it, say, or drilling a hole in the wall. I'll follow Liberto's use for these abbreviations. Note that Φ will always refer to an act within S's domain D.

One of the more distinctive contributions of Liberto's framework is her insistence that subjects retain their domain authority, even as they exercise it to permit action within their domains (42). When S consents to Φ, Liberto says, S does not waive any rights against Φ. If they did, Φ would no longer be part of S's domain of authority D. It is possible to waive rights in this way—this is what happens with property transfers. But Liberto argues that things are quite different for permissive consent (61). If I invite P into my home, or permit P to touch me sexually, they may do so without violating...

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
3.00
自引率
0.00%
发文量
19
期刊介绍: The Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal offers a scholarly forum for diverse views on major issues in bioethics, such as analysis and critique of principlism, feminist perspectives in bioethics, the work of the Advisory Committee on Human Radiation Experiments, active euthanasia, genetics, health care reform, and organ transplantation. Each issue includes "Scope Notes," an overview and extensive annotated bibliography on a specific topic in bioethics, and "Bioethics Inside the Beltway," a report written by a Washington insider updating bioethics activities on the federal level.
期刊最新文献
Contributors Editor's Note Data Solidarity Disrupted: Musings On the Overlooked Role of Mutual Aid in Data-Driven Medicine Allergic Intimacies: Food, Disability, Desire, and Risk by Michael Gill (review) Green Light Ethics: A Theory of Permissive Consent and its Moral Metaphysics by Hallie Liberto (review)
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1