首页 > 最新文献

Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal最新文献

英文 中文
Editor's Note 编者按
IF 1.4 4区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-07-02 DOI: 10.1353/ken.2023.a931049
Quill R. Kukla
<span><span>In lieu of</span> an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:</span><p> <ul> <li><!-- html_title --> Editor's Note <!-- /html_title --></li> <li> Quill R. Kukla </li> </ul> <p>This issue of the <em>Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal</em> offers three articles that encourage readers to think in different ways about how we use and share medical facts and information. Communication and information-sharing in medicine are never value-neutral processes, and there is never an objective answer to what information should be shared or how. What information we have access to, what information we take as relevant, and how we share that information are always vexed issues. This is because medical information is inherently socially charged, value-laden, and uncertain, and sharing it is bound up with norms of privacy, principles of relevance and empirical reasoning, and the complexities of health communication. All three essays in this issue, in taking up these issues, work at the intersection of ethics and social epistemology.</p> <p>In "The Goals of Medicine: Debate and Disagreements Around Contraceptive Side Effects," Ilvie Prince argues that our framing of the benefits, risks, and side effects of hormonal contraception is shaped by a specific understanding of the purpose and nature of medicine. This framing, she argues, ends up harming people who can become pregnant. While it is common to point out that contraceptive and reproductive health care are distorted by sexism, Prince argues that there are yet deeper distortions at work in our understanding of contraceptive side effects. When the primary goal of medicine is understood as the prevention of disease and dysfunction, narrowly construed, this obscures our ability to properly weigh and articulate the harms of both pregnancy and contraception. Since women are disproportionately the ones who bear the burdens and risks of both reproduction and contraception, this obfuscation has sexist results, as it disproportionately harms women. Prince also argues that once we understand the goals of medicine more broadly, we cannot avoid the uncomfortable fact that doctors must address social harms and benefits—and not just narrowly biological ones—despite the risk that this kind of intervention can serve politically nefarious ends. Prince's rich piece draws on her deep understanding of bioethics, as well as the history and science of reproductive medicine. <strong>[End Page vii]</strong></p> <p>Benjamin Chin-Yee's tightly argued paper—"Generalizations in Clinical Trials: Do Generics Help or Harm?"—digs into the details of the language of health communication and its epistemic and ethical perils. He points out that generalizations in biomedical science (statements about what is generally true) often take the form of <em>generics</em>. Generics are general statements that contain implicit generalizations, but don't actually use quantificational language, such as "Drug A cures condition C" or "Peop
以下是内容的简要摘录,以代替摘要: 编者按 Quill R. Kukla 本期《肯尼迪伦理学研究所杂志》刊登了三篇文章,鼓励读者以不同的方式思考我们如何使用和分享医学事实与信息。医学中的交流和信息共享从来都不是价值中立的过程,对于应该共享什么信息或如何共享信息从来都没有一个客观的答案。我们可以获取哪些信息,我们认为哪些信息是相关的,以及我们如何共享这些信息,这些问题始终令人困扰。这是因为医疗信息本身就具有社会性、价值性和不确定性,而共享这些信息又与隐私规范、相关性原则和经验推理以及复杂的健康传播息息相关。本期的三篇文章在讨论这些问题时,都在伦理学和社会认识论的交叉点上开展工作。在 "医学的目标:围绕避孕药副作用的争论与分歧》一文中,伊尔维-普林斯(Ilvie Prince)认为,我们对荷尔蒙避孕药的益处、风险和副作用的界定,是由对医学目的和性质的特定理解所决定的。她认为,这种观点最终伤害了可能怀孕的人。尽管指出避孕和生殖保健被性别歧视扭曲是司空见惯的事,但普林斯认为,我们对避孕副作用的理解还存在更深层次的扭曲。当医学的首要目标被狭隘地理解为预防疾病和功能障碍时,这就掩盖了我们正确权衡和阐述怀孕和避孕危害的能力。由于妇女不成比例地承担着生育和避孕的负担和风险,这种混淆视听的做法产生了性别歧视的结果,因为它不成比例地伤害了妇女。普林斯还认为,一旦我们更广泛地理解了医学的目标,我们就无法回避一个令人不安的事实,即医生必须解决社会危害和利益问题,而不仅仅是狭隘的生物学问题,尽管这种干预有可能服务于政治上的邪恶目的。普林斯的这篇内容丰富的文章汲取了她对生命伦理学以及生殖医学历史和科学的深刻理解。[本杰明-钱-易(Benjamin Chin-Yee)的论文 "临床试验中的泛化:Do Generics Help or Harm?" - 深入探讨了健康交流语言的细节及其认识论和伦理学危险。他指出,生物医学科学中的概括(关于什么是普遍真实的陈述)通常采用泛指的形式。通用语是包含隐含概括的一般性陈述,但实际上并不使用量化语言,如 "药物 A 能治疗病情 C "或 "疾病 D 患者有症状 S"。这与明确的量化概括形成鲜明对比,如 "药物 A 通常能治愈病情 C "或 "疾病 D 患者 85% 的情况下都会出现症状 S"。语言哲学家们已经指出了泛指具有价值负载和潜在歧义的方式。Chin-Yee 借鉴了这些讨论,并证明在公共健康传播中,通用语既常见又可能产生误导。他还认为,非专利药偷渡了在典型的公共传播语境中无法挖掘或批判性审视的价值观。虽然非专利药在认识论上有好处,但他认为其认识论上的危害大于这些好处,并建议生物医学家在与公众交流时避免使用非专利药。最后,Michiel De Proost 在 "Data Solidarity Disrupted:对数据驱动医学中被忽视的互助作用的思考 "一文中,探讨了伦理学与认识论交汇处的一个新问题,即医学数据共享。数据共享对医学知识的发展非常重要,但也很容易被公司或个人利用。德普洛斯特认为,通常情况下,我们认为数据共享是病人利他的行为,是为了实现非直接属于自己的目标,如研究或提供公共服务。但这种模式几乎无法解决剥削、结构性不公正或精英俘获等问题。相反,德普洛斯特借鉴了经典的无政府主义理论以及无政府主义的团结互助概念,提出了一种自下而上的数据团结与共享模式。[End Page viii] Copyright © 2024 约翰-霍普金斯大学...
{"title":"Editor's Note","authors":"Quill R. Kukla","doi":"10.1353/ken.2023.a931049","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ken.2023.a931049","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;span&gt;&lt;span&gt;In lieu of&lt;/span&gt; an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:&lt;/span&gt;\u0000&lt;p&gt; &lt;ul&gt; &lt;li&gt;&lt;!-- html_title --&gt; Editor's Note &lt;!-- /html_title --&gt;&lt;/li&gt; &lt;li&gt; Quill R. Kukla &lt;/li&gt; &lt;/ul&gt; &lt;p&gt;This issue of the &lt;em&gt;Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal&lt;/em&gt; offers three articles that encourage readers to think in different ways about how we use and share medical facts and information. Communication and information-sharing in medicine are never value-neutral processes, and there is never an objective answer to what information should be shared or how. What information we have access to, what information we take as relevant, and how we share that information are always vexed issues. This is because medical information is inherently socially charged, value-laden, and uncertain, and sharing it is bound up with norms of privacy, principles of relevance and empirical reasoning, and the complexities of health communication. All three essays in this issue, in taking up these issues, work at the intersection of ethics and social epistemology.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;In \"The Goals of Medicine: Debate and Disagreements Around Contraceptive Side Effects,\" Ilvie Prince argues that our framing of the benefits, risks, and side effects of hormonal contraception is shaped by a specific understanding of the purpose and nature of medicine. This framing, she argues, ends up harming people who can become pregnant. While it is common to point out that contraceptive and reproductive health care are distorted by sexism, Prince argues that there are yet deeper distortions at work in our understanding of contraceptive side effects. When the primary goal of medicine is understood as the prevention of disease and dysfunction, narrowly construed, this obscures our ability to properly weigh and articulate the harms of both pregnancy and contraception. Since women are disproportionately the ones who bear the burdens and risks of both reproduction and contraception, this obfuscation has sexist results, as it disproportionately harms women. Prince also argues that once we understand the goals of medicine more broadly, we cannot avoid the uncomfortable fact that doctors must address social harms and benefits—and not just narrowly biological ones—despite the risk that this kind of intervention can serve politically nefarious ends. Prince's rich piece draws on her deep understanding of bioethics, as well as the history and science of reproductive medicine. &lt;strong&gt;[End Page vii]&lt;/strong&gt;&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;Benjamin Chin-Yee's tightly argued paper—\"Generalizations in Clinical Trials: Do Generics Help or Harm?\"—digs into the details of the language of health communication and its epistemic and ethical perils. He points out that generalizations in biomedical science (statements about what is generally true) often take the form of &lt;em&gt;generics&lt;/em&gt;. Generics are general statements that contain implicit generalizations, but don't actually use quantificational language, such as \"Drug A cures condition C\" or \"Peop","PeriodicalId":46167,"journal":{"name":"Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal","volume":"7 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-07-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141510820","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Contributors 贡献者
IF 1.4 4区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-07-02 DOI: 10.1353/ken.2023.a931053
In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:

  • Contributors

Michiel De Proost is a postdoctoral researcher at the Department of Philosophy and Moral Sciences at Ghent University and is affiliated with the Bioethics Institute Ghent and the METAMEDICA consortium.

Benjamin Chin-Yee is a hematologist in the Division of Hematology, Western University, Canada, and a doctoral student in the Department of History and Philosophy of Science at the University of Cambridge. His research interests span philosophy of medicine, values in science, and the ethics of scientific and clinical communication.

Ilvie Prince is a doctoral candidate at Leibniz University Hannover. Her work focuses on the complex relationship between ethics and epistemology in medicine, with a particular interest in medical practices that challenge established concepts and methods.

Megan A. Dean is an assistant professor in the Philosophy Department at Michigan State University and the North American coordinator of Culinary Mind: Center for Philosophy of Food. She works in feminist bioethics with a focus on the ethics of eating.

Jonathan Ichikawa is a professor and department head in philosophy at the University of British Columbia. His research interests center around epistemology, feminist philosophy, ethics, and the philosophy of language, especially the points at which those philosophical subfields interact with one another.

Copyright © 2024 Johns Hopkins University Press ...

以下是内容的简要摘录,以代替摘要: 作者 Michiel De Proost 是根特大学哲学与道德科学系的博士后研究员,隶属于根特生命伦理学研究所和 METAMEDICA 联盟。Benjamin Chin-Yee 是加拿大西部大学血液科的一名血液病学家,也是剑桥大学科学史与科学哲学系的一名博士生。他的研究兴趣包括医学哲学、科学价值以及科学和临床交流伦理。Ilvie Prince 是汉诺威莱布尼茨大学的博士生。她的研究重点是医学伦理学和认识论之间的复杂关系,尤其关注挑战既定概念和方法的医学实践。Megan A. Dean 是密歇根州立大学哲学系助理教授,也是 Culinary Mind 的北美协调员:食品哲学中心 "的北美协调人。她从事女性主义生命伦理学研究,重点关注饮食伦理学。Jonathan Ichikawa 是不列颠哥伦比亚大学哲学系教授兼系主任。他的研究兴趣集中在认识论、女性主义哲学、伦理学和语言哲学,尤其是这些哲学分支领域之间的相互作用。Copyright © 2024 约翰斯-霍普金斯大学出版社 ...
{"title":"Contributors","authors":"","doi":"10.1353/ken.2023.a931053","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ken.2023.a931053","url":null,"abstract":"<span><span>In lieu of</span> an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:</span>\u0000<p> <ul> <li><!-- html_title --> Contributors <!-- /html_title --></li> </ul> <p>Michiel De Proost is a postdoctoral researcher at the Department of Philosophy and Moral Sciences at Ghent University and is affiliated with the Bioethics Institute Ghent and the METAMEDICA consortium.</p> <p>Benjamin Chin-Yee is a hematologist in the Division of Hematology, Western University, Canada, and a doctoral student in the Department of History and Philosophy of Science at the University of Cambridge. His research interests span philosophy of medicine, values in science, and the ethics of scientific and clinical communication.</p> <p>Ilvie Prince is a doctoral candidate at Leibniz University Hannover. Her work focuses on the complex relationship between ethics and epistemology in medicine, with a particular interest in medical practices that challenge established concepts and methods.</p> <p>Megan A. Dean is an assistant professor in the Philosophy Department at Michigan State University and the North American coordinator of Culinary Mind: Center for Philosophy of Food. She works in feminist bioethics with a focus on the ethics of eating.</p> <p>Jonathan Ichikawa is a professor and department head in philosophy at the University of British Columbia. His research interests center around epistemology, feminist philosophy, ethics, and the philosophy of language, especially the points at which those philosophical subfields interact with one another.</p> Copyright © 2024 Johns Hopkins University Press ... </p>","PeriodicalId":46167,"journal":{"name":"Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal","volume":"13 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-07-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141510819","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Data Solidarity Disrupted: Musings On the Overlooked Role of Mutual Aid in Data-Driven Medicine 被打乱的数据团结:关于数据驱动医学中被忽视的互助作用的思考
IF 1.4 4区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-07-02 DOI: 10.1353/ken.2023.a931052
Michiel De Proost

Several suggestions have been made to embolden and reorient the concept of solidarity given the emergence of data-driven medicine. Recently, the European Union introduced a new consent model for so-called data altruism to motivate people to make their data available for purposes such as scientific research or improving public services. Others have introduced the alternative concept of data solidarily, which assumes that people's interests in data sharing result from a collective commitment to assist others. What those perspectives have in common is a focus on top-down organizational structures to deal with data-driven medicine. In this article, I offer an alternative reading of data solidarity, drawing on anarchist theory that highlights the disposition of mutual aid as a broader characteristic of solidarity. I begin by briefly indicating how the existing approaches to data solidarity in healthcare remain legalistic and state-centered without thoroughly considering socially critical notions of solidarity that highlight the impact of structural injustices. I then sketch out how an anarchist understanding of mutual aid could inform the conceptualization of solidarity. Finally, I focus on two implications for the practice of data-driven medicine: (1) current proposals of data altruism seem to engender a form of reversed charity; and (2) data solidarity practices could arise from the bottom-up through spontaneous order and direct action.

鉴于数据驱动医学的出现,人们提出了一些建议,以加强和重新定位团结的概念。最近,欧盟为所谓的数据利他主义引入了一种新的同意模式,以激励人们为科学研究或改善公共服务等目的提供自己的数据。还有人提出了另一种数据团结的概念,认为人们对数据共享的兴趣来自于帮助他人的集体承诺。这些观点的共同点是,都侧重于以自上而下的组织结构来处理数据驱动型医学。在本文中,我借鉴了无政府主义理论,对数据团结提出了另一种解读,该理论强调了互助作为团结的更广泛特征的处置方式。首先,我简要说明了医疗保健领域数据团结的现有方法是如何保持法律主义和以国家为中心的,而没有彻底考虑具有社会批判性的团结概念,这些概念强调了结构性不公正的影响。然后,我简要介绍了无政府主义对互助的理解如何为团结的概念化提供参考。最后,我重点阐述了数据驱动型医疗实践的两点意义:(1)当前的数据利他主义建议似乎产生了一种反向慈善形式;(2)数据团结实践可以通过自发秩序和直接行动自下而上地产生。
{"title":"Data Solidarity Disrupted: Musings On the Overlooked Role of Mutual Aid in Data-Driven Medicine","authors":"Michiel De Proost","doi":"10.1353/ken.2023.a931052","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ken.2023.a931052","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Several suggestions have been made to embolden and reorient the concept of solidarity given the emergence of data-driven medicine. Recently, the European Union introduced a new consent model for so-called data altruism to motivate people to make their data available for purposes such as scientific research or improving public services. Others have introduced the alternative concept of data solidarily, which assumes that people's interests in data sharing result from a collective commitment to assist others. What those perspectives have in common is a focus on top-down organizational structures to deal with data-driven medicine. In this article, I offer an alternative reading of data solidarity, drawing on anarchist theory that highlights the disposition of mutual aid as a broader characteristic of solidarity. I begin by briefly indicating how the existing approaches to data solidarity in healthcare remain legalistic and state-centered without thoroughly considering socially critical notions of solidarity that highlight the impact of structural injustices. I then sketch out how an anarchist understanding of mutual aid could inform the conceptualization of solidarity. Finally, I focus on two implications for the practice of data-driven medicine: (1) current proposals of data altruism seem to engender a form of reversed charity; and (2) data solidarity practices could arise from the bottom-up through spontaneous order and direct action.</p></p>","PeriodicalId":46167,"journal":{"name":"Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal","volume":"20 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-07-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141510821","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Generalizations in Clinical Trials—Do Generics Help Or Harm? 临床试验中的概括--仿制药是有益还是有害?
IF 1.4 4区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-07-02 DOI: 10.1353/ken.2023.a931051
Benjamin Chin-Yee

Generalizations in medical research can be informative, but also misleading. Building on recent work in the philosophy of science and ethics of communication, I offer a novel analysis of common generalizations in clinical trials as generics in natural language. Generics, which express generalizations without terms of quantification, have attracted considerable attention from philosophers, psychologists, and linguists. My analysis draws on probabilistic and contextual features of generics to diagnose how these generalizations function and malfunction across communicative contexts in medicine. Given a high risk of misinterpretation ("slippage"), I recommend avoidance of generic claims about medical interventions in public contexts, exemplified by clinical trials and medical research more generally. Generics should only be used with vigilance in private contexts, exemplified by the physician–patient encounter. My analysis provides tools to support vigilance when communicating with generics, suggests new norms for public science communication, and raises deeper questions in the ethics of clinical communication.

医学研究中的概括可以提供信息,但也可能产生误导。在科学哲学和传播伦理学近期研究的基础上,我对临床试验中常见的概括进行了新颖的分析,将其视为自然语言中的泛指。概括语是一种不用量化术语来表达概括的语言,已经引起了哲学家、心理学家和语言学家的广泛关注。我的分析借鉴了概括语的概率和语境特征,以诊断这些概括语在医学交际语境中是如何发挥作用和失灵的。鉴于误解("失误")的风险很高,我建议避免在公共语境中对医疗干预措施进行泛指,临床试验和医学研究就是更普遍的例子。只有在私下场合,例如医生与患者的接触中,才应警惕地使用通用语。我的分析提供了在传播非专利药时保持警惕的工具,提出了公共科学传播的新规范,并提出了临床传播伦理方面更深层次的问题。
{"title":"Generalizations in Clinical Trials—Do Generics Help Or Harm?","authors":"Benjamin Chin-Yee","doi":"10.1353/ken.2023.a931051","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ken.2023.a931051","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Generalizations in medical research can be informative, but also misleading. Building on recent work in the philosophy of science and ethics of communication, I offer a novel analysis of common generalizations in clinical trials as generics in natural language. Generics, which express generalizations without terms of quantification, have attracted considerable attention from philosophers, psychologists, and linguists. My analysis draws on probabilistic and contextual features of generics to diagnose how these generalizations function and malfunction across communicative contexts in medicine. Given a high risk of misinterpretation (\"slippage\"), I recommend avoidance of generic claims about medical interventions in public contexts, exemplified by clinical trials and medical research more generally. Generics should only be used with vigilance in private contexts, exemplified by the physician–patient encounter. My analysis provides tools to support vigilance when communicating with generics, suggests new norms for public science communication, and raises deeper questions in the ethics of clinical communication.</p></p>","PeriodicalId":46167,"journal":{"name":"Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal","volume":"36 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-07-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141530283","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Green Light Ethics: A Theory of Permissive Consent and its Moral Metaphysics by Hallie Liberto (review) 绿灯伦理:允许同意理论及其道德形而上学》,作者 Hallie Liberto(评论)
IF 1.4 4区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-07-02 DOI: 10.1353/ken.2023.a931054
Jonathan Ichikawa
<span><span>In lieu of</span> an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:</span><p> <span>Reviewed by:</span> <ul> <li><!-- html_title --> <em>Green Light Ethics: A Theory of Permissive Consent and its Moral Metaphysics</em> by Hallie Liberto <!-- /html_title --></li> <li> Jonathan Ichikawa (bio) </li> </ul> Review of Hallie Liberto, <em>Green Light Ethics: A Theory of Permissive Consent and its Moral Metaphysics</em> (Oxford University Press, 2022) <p>Hallie Liberto's <em>Green Light Ethics</em> offers a framework for conceptualizing permissive consent. The book is a philosopher's work of philosophy. Although it touches on non-ideal social realities, especially sexism, it is most centrally a contribution to a quite abstract literature in normative ethics, following in the tradition of scholars like David Owens, Heidi Hurd, Alan Wertheimer, and Tom Dougherty—it may have a few too many Φs and abstractions to be accessible to and comfortable for many people outside the analytic philosophical tradition. The central approach to permission and consent is general—not specific to sexual consent—although some discussions are specific to sex.</p> <p>I have always appreciated and learned from Liberto's work on this topic, and I was excited to read her new book. As I'd hoped, it exhibits fresh and interesting moral and philosophical instincts, and advances plausible and interesting ideas. I did feel, however, that it was sometimes more difficult than one might hope to identify exactly what those ideas are. At key points, I found myself wanting more precision or explanation. I am not the kind of philosopher who shuns abstraction—I value both the concrete/non-ideal and the theoretical/abstract. And I'm not afraid of all those Φs. But as I see it, the point of writing in that mode—the reason it can be worth the cost in accessibility and style—is the ability to express and examine complex ideas with a high degree of precision. As I was reading this book, I found that much of my own intellectual contribution centered around attempts to interpret Liberto's ideas and technicalities before I was in a good position to learn from them. This was a bit of a shame, because there <em>are</em> intriguing ideas in this book, well worthy of consideration. I'll give my own reconstruction of a few of them below, along with some critical engagement.</p> <h2><small>1. domain authority</small></h2> <p>Liberto posits that there are certain domains over which people hold a special kind of moral authority, which she calls "domain authority" (38). Someone would wrong you if they acted in your domains outside of your normative control. For example, you have domain authority over sexual contact with your body; any actions by others within that domain must <strong>[End Page 429]</strong> be in accordance with your moral control, or they are violative. Liberto typically uses the following abbreviations to discuss domain authority: <em>S</em> is a person who may or may not be g
以下是内容的简要摘录,以代替摘要:审稿人: 绿灯伦理:哈莉-利贝托著的《许可同意理论及其道德形而上学》 乔纳森-市川(Jonathan Ichikawa)(简历) 哈莉-利贝托著的《绿光伦理学》评论:Hallie Liberto 的《绿灯伦理学》为 "许可同意 "的概念化提供了一个框架。该书是一部哲学家的哲学著作。虽然它涉及了非理想的社会现实,尤其是性别歧视,但它最核心的是对规范伦理学中相当抽象的文献的贡献,继承了大卫-欧文斯、海蒂-赫德、艾伦-韦特海默和汤姆-多尔蒂等学者的传统--它可能有一些太多的Φ和抽象概念,让许多分析哲学传统之外的人难以理解和接受。关于许可和同意的核心方法是一般性的,而不是专门针对性同意的,尽管有些讨论是专门针对性的。我一直很欣赏利贝托在这一主题上的工作,也从她那里学到了很多东西,所以我很高兴能读到她的新书。正如我所希望的那样,这本书展现了新颖有趣的道德和哲学本能,提出了合理有趣的观点。然而,我确实感觉到,有时要确定这些观点到底是什么比想象中要困难得多。在一些关键点上,我发现自己需要更精确的解释或说明。我不是那种回避抽象的哲学家,我既重视具体/非理想,也重视理论/抽象。我也不惧怕那些Φ。但在我看来,以这种模式写作的意义--它之所以值得在易读性和风格上付出代价--在于能够高度精确地表达和审视复杂的观点。在读这本书的过程中,我发现自己的大部分知识贡献都集中在试图解释利贝托的观点和技术细节上,而我还没有来得及从中学到东西。这有点遗憾,因为这本书中的观点耐人寻味,非常值得思考。我将在下文中对其中几个观点进行重构,并提出一些批评意见。1. 领域权威 利贝托认为,在某些领域,人们拥有一种特殊的道德权威,她称之为 "领域权威"(38)。如果有人在你的规范控制之外的领域行事,他就会错怪你。例如,你对与自己身体的性接触拥有领域权威;他人在该领域内的任何行为都必须 [完 第 429 页] 符合你的道德控制,否则就是侵犯。利伯托通常使用以下缩写来讨论领域权威:S 是一个人,他可能允许或不允许 P 执行 Φ,而 Φ 是 P 可能执行的潜在行动。这里的 Φ 总是 D(S 的道德权威的特定领域)范围内的行动。由于 Φ 是在 D 的范围内,如果 P 在没有得到 S 的适当授权的情况下实施了 Φ,那么 Φ 就会使 S 感到错误。就性领域权而言,D 是 S 的身体性领域;如果 P 在 S 的授权之外在该领域内实施某种行为 Φ,就会对 S 造成伤害。(例如,Φ 可能是对 S 进行性插入。D 可以是我的家,而 Φ 可以代表在我家里的潜在行为,任何 S 都需要得到我的许可:比如说,进入我家,或者在墙上钻个洞。我将沿用利贝托对这些缩写的用法。请注意,Φ 总是指 S 的领域 D 内的行为。利伯托框架的一个更独特的贡献是,她坚持认为主体保留其领域权威,即使他们行使权威允许在其领域内的行为(42)。利伯托说,当 S 同意 Φ 时,S 并没有放弃任何针对 Φ 的权利。如果放弃了,Φ 就不再是 S 的权威领域 D 的一部分了。但利伯托认为,许可同意的情况则完全不同(61)。如果我邀请 P 进入我的家,或允许 P 对我进行性接触,他们可以这样做而不违反......
{"title":"Green Light Ethics: A Theory of Permissive Consent and its Moral Metaphysics by Hallie Liberto (review)","authors":"Jonathan Ichikawa","doi":"10.1353/ken.2023.a931054","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ken.2023.a931054","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;span&gt;&lt;span&gt;In lieu of&lt;/span&gt; an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:&lt;/span&gt;\u0000&lt;p&gt; &lt;span&gt;Reviewed by:&lt;/span&gt; &lt;ul&gt; &lt;li&gt;&lt;!-- html_title --&gt; &lt;em&gt;Green Light Ethics: A Theory of Permissive Consent and its Moral Metaphysics&lt;/em&gt; by Hallie Liberto &lt;!-- /html_title --&gt;&lt;/li&gt; &lt;li&gt; Jonathan Ichikawa (bio) &lt;/li&gt; &lt;/ul&gt; Review of Hallie Liberto, &lt;em&gt;Green Light Ethics: A Theory of Permissive Consent and its Moral Metaphysics&lt;/em&gt; (Oxford University Press, 2022) &lt;p&gt;Hallie Liberto's &lt;em&gt;Green Light Ethics&lt;/em&gt; offers a framework for conceptualizing permissive consent. The book is a philosopher's work of philosophy. Although it touches on non-ideal social realities, especially sexism, it is most centrally a contribution to a quite abstract literature in normative ethics, following in the tradition of scholars like David Owens, Heidi Hurd, Alan Wertheimer, and Tom Dougherty—it may have a few too many Φs and abstractions to be accessible to and comfortable for many people outside the analytic philosophical tradition. The central approach to permission and consent is general—not specific to sexual consent—although some discussions are specific to sex.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;I have always appreciated and learned from Liberto's work on this topic, and I was excited to read her new book. As I'd hoped, it exhibits fresh and interesting moral and philosophical instincts, and advances plausible and interesting ideas. I did feel, however, that it was sometimes more difficult than one might hope to identify exactly what those ideas are. At key points, I found myself wanting more precision or explanation. I am not the kind of philosopher who shuns abstraction—I value both the concrete/non-ideal and the theoretical/abstract. And I'm not afraid of all those Φs. But as I see it, the point of writing in that mode—the reason it can be worth the cost in accessibility and style—is the ability to express and examine complex ideas with a high degree of precision. As I was reading this book, I found that much of my own intellectual contribution centered around attempts to interpret Liberto's ideas and technicalities before I was in a good position to learn from them. This was a bit of a shame, because there &lt;em&gt;are&lt;/em&gt; intriguing ideas in this book, well worthy of consideration. I'll give my own reconstruction of a few of them below, along with some critical engagement.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;h2&gt;&lt;small&gt;1. domain authority&lt;/small&gt;&lt;/h2&gt; &lt;p&gt;Liberto posits that there are certain domains over which people hold a special kind of moral authority, which she calls \"domain authority\" (38). Someone would wrong you if they acted in your domains outside of your normative control. For example, you have domain authority over sexual contact with your body; any actions by others within that domain must &lt;strong&gt;[End Page 429]&lt;/strong&gt; be in accordance with your moral control, or they are violative. Liberto typically uses the following abbreviations to discuss domain authority: &lt;em&gt;S&lt;/em&gt; is a person who may or may not be g","PeriodicalId":46167,"journal":{"name":"Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal","volume":"28 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-07-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141510823","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Goals of Medicine: Debate and Disagreements Around Contraceptive Side Effects 医学的目标:围绕避孕药副作用的争论与分歧
IF 1.4 4区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-07-02 DOI: 10.1353/ken.2023.a931050
Ilvie Prince

Since the invention of hormonal contraceptives, there has been disagreement between users and providers about the existence of side effects and their implications for care. The lack of consideration for cisgender women, and other people who may become pregnant, has often been explained by sexist bias in the philosophy of medicine. My goal is to contribute additional elements to this discussion. I will argue that there are structurally embedded assumptions about the responsibilities and goals of medicine that open the door to this sexism in the first place. While we tend to accept that contraception is part of medicine for pragmatic reasons, we do not exhibit the same form of pragmatism when it comes to dealing with side effects. This is an unjustified double standard that fails to recognize the goals of contraception and the fact that it relies on medical expertise to achieve them.

自荷尔蒙避孕药发明以来,使用者和医疗服务提供者一直对副作用的存在及其对护理的影响存在分歧。医学哲学中的性别歧视偏见常常被解释为对顺性别女性和其他可能怀孕的人缺乏考虑。我的目标是为这一讨论贡献更多内容。我将论证,医学的责任和目标存在着结构性的假设,这些假设首先为性别歧视敞开了大门。虽然出于实用主义的原因,我们倾向于接受避孕是医学的一部分,但在处理副作用时,我们却没有表现出同样的实用主义。这是一种毫无道理的双重标准,它没有认识到避孕的目的,也没有认识到避孕是依靠医学专业知识来实现的。
{"title":"The Goals of Medicine: Debate and Disagreements Around Contraceptive Side Effects","authors":"Ilvie Prince","doi":"10.1353/ken.2023.a931050","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ken.2023.a931050","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Since the invention of hormonal contraceptives, there has been disagreement between users and providers about the existence of side effects and their implications for care. The lack of consideration for cisgender women, and other people who may become pregnant, has often been explained by sexist bias in the philosophy of medicine. My goal is to contribute additional elements to this discussion. I will argue that there are structurally embedded assumptions about the responsibilities and goals of medicine that open the door to this sexism in the first place. While we tend to accept that contraception is part of medicine for pragmatic reasons, we do not exhibit the same form of pragmatism when it comes to dealing with side effects. This is an unjustified double standard that fails to recognize the goals of contraception and the fact that it relies on medical expertise to achieve them.</p></p>","PeriodicalId":46167,"journal":{"name":"Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal","volume":"83 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-07-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141530129","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Allergic Intimacies: Food, Disability, Desire, and Risk by Michael Gill (review) 过敏性亲密关系:食物、残疾、欲望和风险》,迈克尔-吉尔著(评论)
IF 1.4 4区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-07-02 DOI: 10.1353/ken.2023.a931055
Megan A. Dean
<span><span>In lieu of</span> an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:</span><p> <span>Reviewed by:</span> <ul> <li><!-- html_title --> <em>Allergic Intimacies: Food, Disability, Desire, and Risk</em> by Michael Gill <!-- /html_title --></li> <li> Megan A. Dean (bio) </li> </ul> Review of Michael Gill, <em>Allergic Intimacies: Food, Disability, Desire, and Risk</em> (Fordham University Press, 2023) <p>In the early days of the COVID-19 pandemic, the mundane activity of eating with or near others became physically hazardous and normatively fraught. Nourishing oneself outside one's home could raise serious risks to one's health and wellbeing, and was suddenly subject to new policies and prohibitions aimed at minimizing harm and liability. The decision to eat out demanded personal calculations of risk and benefit, as well as interpersonal negotiation, sometimes prompting contentious conversations about the realities of disease transmission and our moral responsibilities. For many people, coming to think about eating outside the home as a pressing and significant threat to health and life was a radical shift. Yet, as Michael Gill's <em>Allergic Intimacies: Food, Disability, Desire, and Risk</em> details, the experience of eating meals as risking lethal consequences, demanding active personal risk management (including knowledge and negotiation of laws and policies), and straining important interpersonal relationships, is quite familiar to those living with food allergies.</p> <p><em>Allergic Intimacies</em> offers a rich and generative exploration of the challenges of living with food allergies in the United States. A disability studies scholar, Gill frames the book as an examination of the "meanings" of food allergy from an intersectional perspective that centers both disability and race (ix). The book analyses various cultural representations of and narratives about food allergy, and traces the health effects of social and institutional structures, policies, and practices, while interweaving these findings with Gill's personal experiences with nut allergies. The focus throughout is on IgE-mediated food allergies, the sort which can cause anaphylaxis and which are exemplified by peanut allergies. The book's central claim is that common individualistic approaches to food allergy—approaches that emphasize personal and familial responsibility for allergy management—are inadequate, failing to address the systemic and structural issues that significantly disadvantage food-allergic people in marginalized groups in the U.S., especially Black people. These structural <strong>[End Page 421]</strong> issues include barriers to accessing not only food and medicine, but also the social and economic resources necessary to advocate for food allergy needs.</p> <p>The book contains a preface, introduction, and brief conclusion, along with four main chapters. The introduction presents a medical and epidemiological overview of food allergies, including va
以下是内容的简要摘录,以代替摘要:评论者: 过敏性亲密关系:Megan A. Dean (bio) Review of Michael Gill, Allergic Intimacies:食物、残疾、欲望与风险》(福特汉姆大学出版社,2023 年)在 COVID-19 大流行的早期,与他人一起或靠近他人进食这一平凡的活动变得既危险又充满规范性。外出就餐可能会给个人的健康和福祉带来严重风险,并突然受到旨在尽量减少伤害和责任的新政策和禁令的约束。外出就餐的决定需要个人对风险和利益进行计算,还需要进行人际谈判,有时会引发关于疾病传播的现实和我们的道德责任的争议性对话。对许多人来说,将外出就餐视为对健康和生命的紧迫而重大的威胁是一种彻底的转变。然而,正如迈克尔-吉尔(Michael Gill)的《过敏性亲密关系》(Allergic Intimacies)一书所言:食物、残疾、欲望和风险》一书中详细描述的那样,对于食物过敏症患者来说,进餐有可能造成致命后果,需要积极的个人风险管理(包括了解和协商法律和政策),并使重要的人际关系变得紧张。过敏性亲密关系》对美国食物过敏患者的生活挑战进行了丰富而有启发性的探讨。作为一名残疾研究学者,吉尔从交叉视角出发,以残疾和种族为中心,对食物过敏的 "意义 "进行了研究(ix)。该书分析了有关食物过敏的各种文化表述和叙事,追溯了社会和制度结构、政策和实践对健康的影响,同时将这些发现与吉尔个人的坚果过敏经历交织在一起。全书的重点是 IgE 介导的食物过敏,这种过敏可导致过敏性休克,以花生过敏为例。该书的核心主张是,针对食物过敏的常见个人主义方法--强调个人和家庭对过敏控制的责任的方法--是不充分的,未能解决系统性和结构性问题,这些问题使美国边缘群体中的食物过敏者,尤其是黑人处于非常不利的地位。这些结构性 [尾页 421]问题不仅包括获得食物和药物的障碍,还包括倡导食物过敏需求所需的社会和经济资源。本书包括序言、导言和简短的结论,以及四个主要章节。导言介绍了食物过敏的医学和流行病学概况,包括近几十年来食物过敏发病率明显上升的各种假设。该书还讨论了四种 "情景",以激发对食物过敏进行超越个人主义、"单轴"(即非交叉)分析的必要性:肾上腺素注射器的使用(8-14)、食品工业过敏原标签做法(14-16)、航空公司食物过敏原政策(16-18)以及《英国烘焙大赛》对食物过敏的处理(18-23)。第一章 "食物过敏、免疫和环境的关系 "探讨了对食物过敏者和其他饮食限制者的责任,讨论了风险管理、身份以及无过敏原空间的伦理和政治等主题,包括共餐、学校和飞机。第二章是 "无坚果松鼠和花生过敏公主":第二章 "无坚果松鼠和花生过敏公主:食物过敏、身份和儿童读物 "对有关食物过敏的儿童读物进行了批判性分析,指出大多数英语儿童读物都以患有花生过敏症的白人男孩为中心,他们的经历反映了经济和社会特权。这些儿童读物在很大程度上忽视了许多边缘化家庭所经历的挑战,例如需要努力争取学校承认和照顾食物过敏,社区成员对提供此类照顾的抵制,以及难以获得不含过敏原的食物。第三章 "液体交换引起的过敏反应 "提出了食物过敏者接吻和性行为的伦理问题。由于过敏原可以通过体液传递,因此食物过敏使 "安全 "的亲密身体接触变得更加复杂(57-58)。吉尔借鉴了米娅-明格斯(Mia Mingus)的 "获取亲密关系 "概念(2011 年),提出了一种相互依存的伦理观,即以沟通和同意为中心,同时为愉悦和自发性留出空间。最后一章 "你吃了什么? 故意、意外和死亡 "探讨了与那些故意...
{"title":"Allergic Intimacies: Food, Disability, Desire, and Risk by Michael Gill (review)","authors":"Megan A. Dean","doi":"10.1353/ken.2023.a931055","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ken.2023.a931055","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;span&gt;&lt;span&gt;In lieu of&lt;/span&gt; an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:&lt;/span&gt;\u0000&lt;p&gt; &lt;span&gt;Reviewed by:&lt;/span&gt; &lt;ul&gt; &lt;li&gt;&lt;!-- html_title --&gt; &lt;em&gt;Allergic Intimacies: Food, Disability, Desire, and Risk&lt;/em&gt; by Michael Gill &lt;!-- /html_title --&gt;&lt;/li&gt; &lt;li&gt; Megan A. Dean (bio) &lt;/li&gt; &lt;/ul&gt; Review of Michael Gill, &lt;em&gt;Allergic Intimacies: Food, Disability, Desire, and Risk&lt;/em&gt; (Fordham University Press, 2023) &lt;p&gt;In the early days of the COVID-19 pandemic, the mundane activity of eating with or near others became physically hazardous and normatively fraught. Nourishing oneself outside one's home could raise serious risks to one's health and wellbeing, and was suddenly subject to new policies and prohibitions aimed at minimizing harm and liability. The decision to eat out demanded personal calculations of risk and benefit, as well as interpersonal negotiation, sometimes prompting contentious conversations about the realities of disease transmission and our moral responsibilities. For many people, coming to think about eating outside the home as a pressing and significant threat to health and life was a radical shift. Yet, as Michael Gill's &lt;em&gt;Allergic Intimacies: Food, Disability, Desire, and Risk&lt;/em&gt; details, the experience of eating meals as risking lethal consequences, demanding active personal risk management (including knowledge and negotiation of laws and policies), and straining important interpersonal relationships, is quite familiar to those living with food allergies.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;&lt;em&gt;Allergic Intimacies&lt;/em&gt; offers a rich and generative exploration of the challenges of living with food allergies in the United States. A disability studies scholar, Gill frames the book as an examination of the \"meanings\" of food allergy from an intersectional perspective that centers both disability and race (ix). The book analyses various cultural representations of and narratives about food allergy, and traces the health effects of social and institutional structures, policies, and practices, while interweaving these findings with Gill's personal experiences with nut allergies. The focus throughout is on IgE-mediated food allergies, the sort which can cause anaphylaxis and which are exemplified by peanut allergies. The book's central claim is that common individualistic approaches to food allergy—approaches that emphasize personal and familial responsibility for allergy management—are inadequate, failing to address the systemic and structural issues that significantly disadvantage food-allergic people in marginalized groups in the U.S., especially Black people. These structural &lt;strong&gt;[End Page 421]&lt;/strong&gt; issues include barriers to accessing not only food and medicine, but also the social and economic resources necessary to advocate for food allergy needs.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;The book contains a preface, introduction, and brief conclusion, along with four main chapters. The introduction presents a medical and epidemiological overview of food allergies, including va","PeriodicalId":46167,"journal":{"name":"Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal","volume":"37 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-07-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141510822","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Minding Brain Injury, Consciousness, and Ethics: Discourse and Deliberations 关注脑损伤、意识和伦理:讨论与审议
IF 1.4 4区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-01-24 DOI: 10.1353/ken.2023.a917928
Joseph J. Fins, James Giordano
<span><span>In lieu of</span> an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:</span><p> <ul> <li><!-- html_title --> Minding Brain Injury, Consciousness, and Ethics: <span>Discourse and Deliberations</span> <!-- /html_title --></li> <li> Joseph J. Fins (bio) and James Giordano (bio) </li> </ul> <p><strong>T</strong>he annual John Collins Harvey Lecture at the Georgetown University’s Pellegrino Center for Clinical Bioethics is a forum for addressing contemporary topics at the intersection of medicine and bioethics. This year, in marking the decadal anniversary of the launch of the Brain Research through Advancing Innovative Neurotechnology (BRAIN) Initiative, the Harvey Lecture provided an interactive discussion with renowned clinician, researcher, scholar, and author, Joseph J. Fins, MD—who is the E. William Davis, Jr., MD Professor of Medical Ethics, Chief of the Division of Medical Ethics, and a Professor of Medicine at Weill Cornell Medical College—conducted by James Giordano, PhD, MPhil—who is a Professor of Neurology and Biochemistry, and Chief of the Pellegrino Center’s Neuroethics Studies Program at the Georgetown University Medical Center. The discourse focused upon the topic of covert consciousness, and the ways in which current and developing brain science technologies, together with revised practices of medicine, in general, may afford new opportunities in patient care, but may also give rise to issues, questions, challenges, and opportunities for neuroethics.</p> <strong>Prof. James GIORDANO:</strong> <p>Prof. Fins, your most recent book, <em>Rights Come to Mind: Brain Injury, Ethics, and the Struggle for Consciousness</em> (Fins 2015), addresses your ongoing work to employ current and emerging neurological approaches to reveal conscious functions in patients with profound brain injury and disease. To be sure, the destination—if you will—is to talk about covert consciousness. But in commencing this discussion, I’d like to propose a route, which traces your professional journey to this point in your career, and how it led you on your search to reveal consciousness in those patients who lack expressive capability. You went into palliative care first, and that brought you to where you are today. <strong>[End Page 227]</strong></p> <strong>Prof. Joseph J. FINS:</strong> <p>First, let me thank you and the Pellegrino Center for the honor of giving the John Harvey Collins Lecture in such an interactive manner. The forefront of neurological care—and the neuroethical issues and methods focal to such practice—wasn’t what I initially intended to do professionally, but I think that therein is a good lesson for young people’s career aspirations. Simply put, one doesn’t always know where they’ll end up at the beginning of the journey, and as Kierkegaard said, life is lived forward, but is understood backwards (Kierkegaard 1843).</p> <p>In the nineties and the early 2000s, I was trying to help improve the quality of care of people at the end o
以下是内容的简要摘录,以代替摘要: 关注脑损伤、意识和伦理:约瑟夫-J-芬斯(Joseph J. Fins)(简历)和詹姆斯-乔尔达诺(James Giordano)(简历) 乔治敦大学佩莱格里诺临床生物伦理学中心(Pellegrino Center for Clinical Bioethics)一年一度的约翰-柯林斯-哈维讲座(John Collins Harvey Lecture)是探讨医学与生物伦理学交叉领域当代话题的论坛。今年,为纪念 "通过推进创新神经技术进行脑研究(BRAIN)计划 "启动十周年,哈维讲座与著名临床医生、研究员、学者和作家约瑟夫-J-芬斯(Joseph J. Fins)医学博士进行了互动讨论、在乔治敦大学医学中心神经病学和生物化学教授、佩莱格里诺中心神经伦理学研究项目主任 James Giordano 博士的主持下,医学博士、医学伦理学教授、威尔康奈尔医学院医学教授约瑟夫-J-芬斯(Joseph J. Fins)进行了互动讨论。讨论的重点是隐蔽意识这一主题,以及当前和发展中的脑科学技术如何与经过修改的医学实践相结合,为病人护理带来新的机遇,同时也为神经伦理学带来问题、疑问、挑战和机遇。詹姆斯-乔丹诺教授:芬斯教授,您最近出版的新书《权利涌上心头:脑损伤、伦理学和意识之争》(芬斯,2015 年)讲述了您正在开展的工作,即运用当前和新兴的神经学方法揭示深度脑损伤和疾病患者的意识功能。可以肯定的是,如果你愿意的话,我们的目的是讨论隐蔽意识。但在开始讨论时,我想提出一条路线,追溯你职业生涯中走到这一步的专业历程,以及这条路线是如何引导你探索如何揭示那些缺乏表达能力的病人的意识的。你先是从事姑息治疗,然后才有了今天的成就。[约瑟夫-J-芬斯教授:首先,请允许我感谢您和佩莱格里诺中心,让我有幸以这种互动的方式发表约翰-哈维-柯林斯讲座。神经病学护理的最前沿--以及与这种实践相关的神经伦理问题和方法--并不是我最初打算从事的职业,但我认为这对年轻人的职业理想是一个很好的启示。简而言之,一个人在旅途的起点并不总是知道自己的终点在哪里,正如克尔凯郭尔所说,生活是向前的,但理解却是向后的(克尔凯郭尔,1843 年)。在九十年代和二十一世纪初,我曾试图帮助改善临终关怀的质量,并写了一本书,名为《姑息关怀的伦理》(The Palliative Ethic of Care):我写了一本书,名为《姑息治疗的伦理:生命终结时的临床智慧》(Fins,2006 年),在书中我论述了phronesis--实践智慧--的概念,将理论与实践相结合,以改善人们的死亡方式。我对昆兰案(Quinlan,1976 年)和死亡权产生了兴趣,大约在同一时间,我遇到了康奈尔大学的一位同事:尼古拉斯-D-希夫医生。希夫博士是一位神经学家,他是弗雷德-普卢姆(Fred Plum)的门生,弗雷德-普卢姆是早在 1972 年就与布莱恩-詹尼特(Bryan Jennett)共同提出植物人状态概念的鼻祖。弗雷德是我们俩在康奈尔大学的老师。尼科(希夫博士)对意识障碍患者很感兴趣,并开始设想利用脑深部刺激(DBS)来治疗处于微意识状态的患者--我们最终做到了。我意识到,患有这些意识障碍的整个人群在某种程度上被边缘化了,而对他们的忽视本质上可以追溯到对死亡权利的考虑。昆兰案确立了死亡权,因为休斯法官--新泽西州最高法院的主审首席法官--谈到昆兰女士丧失了认知和智能状态,这是她享有死亡权的道德依据,因为这被视为一种徒劳无益的状况。在随后的几年里,我从我在姑息治疗和临终关怀方面的背景中认识到,[1] 我们对 "无用 "的概念过于笼统......
{"title":"Minding Brain Injury, Consciousness, and Ethics: Discourse and Deliberations","authors":"Joseph J. Fins, James Giordano","doi":"10.1353/ken.2023.a917928","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ken.2023.a917928","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;span&gt;&lt;span&gt;In lieu of&lt;/span&gt; an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:&lt;/span&gt;\u0000&lt;p&gt; &lt;ul&gt; &lt;li&gt;&lt;!-- html_title --&gt; Minding Brain Injury, Consciousness, and Ethics: &lt;span&gt;Discourse and Deliberations&lt;/span&gt; &lt;!-- /html_title --&gt;&lt;/li&gt; &lt;li&gt; Joseph J. Fins (bio) and James Giordano (bio) &lt;/li&gt; &lt;/ul&gt; &lt;p&gt;&lt;strong&gt;T&lt;/strong&gt;he annual John Collins Harvey Lecture at the Georgetown University’s Pellegrino Center for Clinical Bioethics is a forum for addressing contemporary topics at the intersection of medicine and bioethics. This year, in marking the decadal anniversary of the launch of the Brain Research through Advancing Innovative Neurotechnology (BRAIN) Initiative, the Harvey Lecture provided an interactive discussion with renowned clinician, researcher, scholar, and author, Joseph J. Fins, MD—who is the E. William Davis, Jr., MD Professor of Medical Ethics, Chief of the Division of Medical Ethics, and a Professor of Medicine at Weill Cornell Medical College—conducted by James Giordano, PhD, MPhil—who is a Professor of Neurology and Biochemistry, and Chief of the Pellegrino Center’s Neuroethics Studies Program at the Georgetown University Medical Center. The discourse focused upon the topic of covert consciousness, and the ways in which current and developing brain science technologies, together with revised practices of medicine, in general, may afford new opportunities in patient care, but may also give rise to issues, questions, challenges, and opportunities for neuroethics.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;strong&gt;Prof. James GIORDANO:&lt;/strong&gt; &lt;p&gt;Prof. Fins, your most recent book, &lt;em&gt;Rights Come to Mind: Brain Injury, Ethics, and the Struggle for Consciousness&lt;/em&gt; (Fins 2015), addresses your ongoing work to employ current and emerging neurological approaches to reveal conscious functions in patients with profound brain injury and disease. To be sure, the destination—if you will—is to talk about covert consciousness. But in commencing this discussion, I’d like to propose a route, which traces your professional journey to this point in your career, and how it led you on your search to reveal consciousness in those patients who lack expressive capability. You went into palliative care first, and that brought you to where you are today. &lt;strong&gt;[End Page 227]&lt;/strong&gt;&lt;/p&gt; &lt;strong&gt;Prof. Joseph J. FINS:&lt;/strong&gt; &lt;p&gt;First, let me thank you and the Pellegrino Center for the honor of giving the John Harvey Collins Lecture in such an interactive manner. The forefront of neurological care—and the neuroethical issues and methods focal to such practice—wasn’t what I initially intended to do professionally, but I think that therein is a good lesson for young people’s career aspirations. Simply put, one doesn’t always know where they’ll end up at the beginning of the journey, and as Kierkegaard said, life is lived forward, but is understood backwards (Kierkegaard 1843).&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;In the nineties and the early 2000s, I was trying to help improve the quality of care of people at the end o","PeriodicalId":46167,"journal":{"name":"Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal","volume":"8 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-01-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139561976","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Theory of Bioethics by David DeGrazia and Joseph Millum (review) 大卫-德格拉西亚和约瑟夫-米勒姆的《生物伦理学理论》(评论)
IF 1.4 4区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-01-24 DOI: 10.1353/ken.2023.a917931
Colin Hoy, Winston Chiong
<span><span>In lieu of</span> an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:</span><p> <span>Reviewed by:</span> <ul> <li><!-- html_title --> <em>A Theory of Bioethics</em> by David DeGrazia and Joseph Millum <!-- /html_title --></li> <li> Colin Hoy (bio) and Winston Chiong (bio) </li> </ul> Review of David DeGrazia and Joseph Millum, <em>A Theory of Bioethics</em> (Cambridge University Press, 2021) <p>David DeGrazia and Joseph Millum’s <em>A Theory of Bioethics</em> 2021 arrives at a curious time for an ambitious effort at systematic theory construction, seemingly out of step with bioethical fashion. At the same time, a prominent group of philosophical bioethicists authored an article, possibly with a touch of defensiveness, to “make the case that philosophy and philosophers still have a very important and meaningful role to play in contemporary bioethics” (Blumenthal-Barby et al. 2021). Meanwhile, the annual meeting of the American Society for Bioethics and Humanities included several expressions of impatience with the historical privileging of philosophy over more empirical, situated, and community-oriented approaches to moral problems in health.</p> <p>DeGrazia and Millum’s work itself reflects the current state of bioethics and how it has changed since the heyday of grand bioethical theory construction in the late twentieth century. To apply Parfit’s philosophical taxonomy (1984), the general frameworks promulgated by theorists like Veatch, Engelhardt, and Gert, as well as Beauchamp and Childress, were by necessity <em>revisionary</em>. These bioethical theories were whole-cloth alternatives to a conventional and paternalistic medical ethos that was already widely acknowledged as unsatisfactory. Today, however, bioethics is a mature and institutionalized field, with well-established practices and a corpus of accepted tenets (alongside matters of ongoing but generally demarcated controversy). A plausible and fruitful contemporary theory of bioethics must be largely <em>descriptive</em>, in Parfit’s sense, providing an intellectual framework that gives coherence and sense to existing practice, while at the same time clarifying matters of confusion.</p> <p>In contemporary bioethics, a central component of this practice is the application of the four principles of biomedical ethics—non-maleficence, beneficence, justice and autonomy—not merely as originally proposed by Beauchamp and Childress (2019), but in their refined form, following decades of exchange, critique, and revision. DeGrazia and Millum’s theory begins with two core values: well-being and respect for rights holders. <strong>[End Page 321]</strong> The bulk of the book then applies the method of reflective equilibrium to specify these two values in terms of the canonical four principles, here treated as “mid-level” constructs with readier application to specific cases than the two core values. Experienced bioethicists may have an uncanny sense of setting off from a new trailhe
以下是内容的简要摘录,以代替摘要:评论者 大卫-德格拉兹亚和约瑟夫-米勒姆的《生命伦理学理论》 Colin Hoy(生物)和 Winston Chiong(生物) 评论大卫-德格拉兹亚和约瑟夫-米勒姆的《生命伦理学理论》(剑桥大学出版社,2021 年) 大卫-德格拉兹亚和约瑟夫-米勒姆的《生命伦理学理论》(剑桥大学出版社,2021 年)问世于一个奇怪的时期,对于一个系统理论建构的雄心勃勃的努力来说,似乎与生命伦理学的时尚格格不入。与此同时,一群著名的哲学生物伦理学家撰写了一篇文章,"论证哲学和哲学家在当代生物伦理中仍然扮演着非常重要和有意义的角色"(Blumenthal-Barby et al.)与此同时,美国生命伦理学与人文科学学会年会也多次表达了对哲学在解决健康领域道德问题方面的历史特权,而非更多的经验、情景和社区导向方法的不耐烦。DeGrazia 和 Millum 的著作本身就反映了生物伦理学的现状,以及自 20 世纪末生物伦理学理论建设的鼎盛时期以来,生物伦理学发生了怎样的变化。套用帕菲特的哲学分类法(1984 年),维奇、恩格尔哈特、格特以及博尚和柴尔德里斯等理论家颁布的总体框架必然是修正性的。这些生命伦理学理论是对传统的、家长式的医学伦理的全面替代。然而,今天的生命伦理学已经是一个成熟的、制度化的领域,有着完善的实践和公认的信条(同时也存在着持续的、但普遍有争议的问题)。按照帕菲特的观点,当代生物伦理学的合理和富有成果的理论必须在很大程度上是描述性的,提供一个知识框架,使现有的实践具有连贯性和合理性,同时澄清混乱的问题。在当代生命伦理学中,这一实践的核心内容是应用生物医学伦理学的四项原则--非恶意、受益、公正和自主--这不仅仅是博尚普和柴尔德里斯(2019)最初提出的原则,而是经过数十年的交流、批判和修订后的完善形式。DeGrazia 和 Millum 的理论始于两个核心价值:福祉和对权利持有者的尊重。[本书的大部分内容都运用了反思平衡的方法,用经典的四项原则来明确这两项价值,这些原则在本书中被视为 "中层 "建构,比这两项核心价值更容易应用于具体案例。有经验的生命伦理学家可能会有一种不可思议的感觉,就像从一个新的小路出发,但最终发现自己走的仍然是一条熟悉的路。不过,这种介绍和阐释四项原则的方式可能更容易为更多读者所接受,包括尚未熟悉博尚和柴尔德里斯讨论中所包含的修订、完善和妥协的高年级本科生和研究生。本书还有两个特点,建议将其作为受训人员和感兴趣的非专业人员加深对生命伦理学理解的资源。首先,本书清晰的风格和组织方法为非专业人士提供了一个值得欢迎的方向。在章节结构上,作者先概述了主要的争论观点,然后根据这些观点阐述了自己的立场。每一章都考虑了广义理论的应用,展示了广义理论如何阐明潜在的候选方法或政策,以及如何在理想和非理想情况下使用伦理分析工具来评估这些建议。这种讲授概念论证与实践之间关系的方法,对于许多最初不熟悉理论或对理论望而生畏的人来说,是可以理解的。其次,值得称赞的是,作者决定以电子版的形式提供该书,这也有可能扩大该著作的影响范围,特别是在资源不足的情况下,让生物伦理讨论中经常被忽视的各方参与进来。如上所述,虽然作者的方法是帕菲特意义上的描述性方法,但并不一定保守。在许多地方,作者强调了他们的理论如何包含了未被广泛接受的元素或得出了未被广泛接受的结论,并按照反思平衡的方法,从广泛的原则和对案例的特定判断两方面为这些立场进行了辩护。这要从他们的双重价值说起。
{"title":"A Theory of Bioethics by David DeGrazia and Joseph Millum (review)","authors":"Colin Hoy, Winston Chiong","doi":"10.1353/ken.2023.a917931","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ken.2023.a917931","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;span&gt;&lt;span&gt;In lieu of&lt;/span&gt; an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:&lt;/span&gt;\u0000&lt;p&gt; &lt;span&gt;Reviewed by:&lt;/span&gt; &lt;ul&gt; &lt;li&gt;&lt;!-- html_title --&gt; &lt;em&gt;A Theory of Bioethics&lt;/em&gt; by David DeGrazia and Joseph Millum &lt;!-- /html_title --&gt;&lt;/li&gt; &lt;li&gt; Colin Hoy (bio) and Winston Chiong (bio) &lt;/li&gt; &lt;/ul&gt; Review of David DeGrazia and Joseph Millum, &lt;em&gt;A Theory of Bioethics&lt;/em&gt; (Cambridge University Press, 2021) &lt;p&gt;David DeGrazia and Joseph Millum’s &lt;em&gt;A Theory of Bioethics&lt;/em&gt; 2021 arrives at a curious time for an ambitious effort at systematic theory construction, seemingly out of step with bioethical fashion. At the same time, a prominent group of philosophical bioethicists authored an article, possibly with a touch of defensiveness, to “make the case that philosophy and philosophers still have a very important and meaningful role to play in contemporary bioethics” (Blumenthal-Barby et al. 2021). Meanwhile, the annual meeting of the American Society for Bioethics and Humanities included several expressions of impatience with the historical privileging of philosophy over more empirical, situated, and community-oriented approaches to moral problems in health.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;DeGrazia and Millum’s work itself reflects the current state of bioethics and how it has changed since the heyday of grand bioethical theory construction in the late twentieth century. To apply Parfit’s philosophical taxonomy (1984), the general frameworks promulgated by theorists like Veatch, Engelhardt, and Gert, as well as Beauchamp and Childress, were by necessity &lt;em&gt;revisionary&lt;/em&gt;. These bioethical theories were whole-cloth alternatives to a conventional and paternalistic medical ethos that was already widely acknowledged as unsatisfactory. Today, however, bioethics is a mature and institutionalized field, with well-established practices and a corpus of accepted tenets (alongside matters of ongoing but generally demarcated controversy). A plausible and fruitful contemporary theory of bioethics must be largely &lt;em&gt;descriptive&lt;/em&gt;, in Parfit’s sense, providing an intellectual framework that gives coherence and sense to existing practice, while at the same time clarifying matters of confusion.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;In contemporary bioethics, a central component of this practice is the application of the four principles of biomedical ethics—non-maleficence, beneficence, justice and autonomy—not merely as originally proposed by Beauchamp and Childress (2019), but in their refined form, following decades of exchange, critique, and revision. DeGrazia and Millum’s theory begins with two core values: well-being and respect for rights holders. &lt;strong&gt;[End Page 321]&lt;/strong&gt; The bulk of the book then applies the method of reflective equilibrium to specify these two values in terms of the canonical four principles, here treated as “mid-level” constructs with readier application to specific cases than the two core values. Experienced bioethicists may have an uncanny sense of setting off from a new trailhe","PeriodicalId":46167,"journal":{"name":"Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal","volume":"199 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-01-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139551470","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The First Smart Pill: Digital Revolution or Last Gasp? 第一颗智能药丸:数字革命还是最后的喘息?
IF 1.4 4区 哲学 Q3 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-01-24 DOI: 10.1353/ken.2023.a917930
Anna K. Swartz, Phoebe Friesen

Abilify MyCite was granted regulatory approval in 2017, becoming the world’s first “smart pill” that could digitally track whether patients had taken their medication. The new technology was introduced as one that had gained the support of patients and ethicists alike, and could contribute to solving the widespread and costly problem of patient nonadherence. Here, we offer an in-depth exploration of this narrative, through an examination of the origins and development of Abilify, the drug that would later become MyCite. This history illuminates how an antipsychotic can become a top-selling drug and maintain its blockbuster status for more than a decade. It also provides a detailed case study for how knowledge is constructed within the logic of biomedical capitalism, providing impetus to reexamine claims regarding how MyCite addresses patient nonadherence, engenders patient support, and is ethicist-approved.

2017 年,Abilify MyCite 获得监管部门批准,成为世界上首款可数字化追踪患者是否服药的 "智能药片"。这项新技术的推出得到了患者和伦理学家的支持,有助于解决患者普遍存在的不依从性问题,而且成本高昂。在此,我们将通过对后来成为 MyCite 的药物 Abilify 的起源和发展的研究,对这一叙述进行深入探讨。这段历史揭示了一种抗精神病药物是如何成为畅销药物,并将其畅销地位维持了十多年的。它还提供了一个详细的案例研究,说明知识是如何在生物医学资本主义的逻辑中构建起来的,从而推动我们重新审视有关 MyCite 如何解决患者不依从性、吸引患者支持以及获得伦理学家批准的说法。
{"title":"The First Smart Pill: Digital Revolution or Last Gasp?","authors":"Anna K. Swartz, Phoebe Friesen","doi":"10.1353/ken.2023.a917930","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ken.2023.a917930","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Abilify MyCite was granted regulatory approval in 2017, becoming the world’s first “smart pill” that could digitally track whether patients had taken their medication. The new technology was introduced as one that had gained the support of patients and ethicists alike, and could contribute to solving the widespread and costly problem of patient nonadherence. Here, we offer an in-depth exploration of this narrative, through an examination of the origins and development of Abilify, the drug that would later become MyCite. This history illuminates how an antipsychotic can become a top-selling drug and maintain its blockbuster status for more than a decade. It also provides a detailed case study for how knowledge is constructed within the logic of biomedical capitalism, providing impetus to reexamine claims regarding how MyCite addresses patient nonadherence, engenders patient support, and is ethicist-approved.</p></p>","PeriodicalId":46167,"journal":{"name":"Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-01-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139551651","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1