数字公共领域的民主责任

Joshua Cohen, Archon Fung
{"title":"数字公共领域的民主责任","authors":"Joshua Cohen,&nbsp;Archon Fung","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12670","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Despite accumulating challenges, digital information and communication technologies retain considerable democratic potential. They have enabled movements, mass protests, and open-data initiatives in cities. But as we have all learned from the failures of an earlier wave of techno-utopianism, the democratic exploitation of technological affordances is deeply contingent—dependent on ethical conviction, political engagement, public regulation, and good design choices. In particular, and in the spirit of Habermas’ remark quoted at the outset, we think that the democratic potential will only be realized if participants in what we will be calling “the digital public sphere” deepen their sense of responsibility for how communication proceeds there.</p><p>A brief clarification: by “the digital public sphere,” we mean a public sphere in which discussion about matters of potentially shared concern is shaped in part by communication on online platforms (intermediaries that store users’ information and enable its public dissemination). Thus, the digital public sphere is neither everything that happens online or on online platforms (much of which is not discussion of matters of shared concern), nor is it only online. It is a public sphere in which communication on platforms plays an important role in shaping public discussion.</p><p>We will begin by sketching an idealized democratic public sphere, which marries inclusion and deliberation. Our current digitalized public sphere is dramatically more inclusive than the post-war mass media public sphere. But this expansion of inclusion has come at a substantial deliberative price. To improve the quality of public discussion, we focus on the responsibilities that participants must take on for the digital public sphere to be more democratically successful.</p><p>To be sure, participant action is insufficient. We and others have offered suggestions for the contributions of regulation, corporate responsibility, and the contributions of researchers, as well as civic and advocacy organizations. The European Union's new regulations on Intermediary Services, for example, the Digital Services Act, include requirements on illegal content and impose due diligence responsibilities on very large online platforms that will need to do audited systematic risk assessments and offer plans for remediation (Husovec &amp; Roche Laguna, <span>2022</span>). This approach has much to be said for it (though with the proliferation of generative models, it may be addressed to last year's problems). But because the digital public sphere has vastly expanded the aperture for contributions to discussion, and because we are uneasy about regulating the substance of public discussion, we are skeptical about proposals to turn public regulators or platforms (or any other agents) into editorial guardians.</p><p>Emphasizing participant responsibilities may give the appearance that we are at once blaming and burdening the victims of degraded public discussion. We resist that characterization. Instead, we focus here on the role of participants because they <i>must</i> become more capable and responsible if we are to retain the democratically attractive qualities of greater inclusion that the digital public sphere has brought. Relying solely on regulatory mechanisms, whether public or private, will create guardians over the practice of public communication. And such guardianship seems to give up on the democratic promise of self-government by consociates.</p><p>We begin with the idea of a democratic society whose free and equal members use their common reason to argue about the substance of public issues and in which the exercise of power is guided by that use. The animating idea is to marry broad opportunities for participation by members with their engagement about the merits of different courses of public action: to combine an inclusive democracy with public reasoning. Thus understood, democratic politics—as a discursive exercise of political autonomy—depends on informal, open-ended, fluid, dispersed public discussions of matters of common concern.</p><p>These conditions, which together describe a structure of equal, substantive communicative freedom, have far-reaching political, social, and economic implications. Equal standing in public reasoning requires favorable social background conditions, including limits on socioeconomic inequality and the dependencies associated with it. Similarly, the conjunction of rights and expression is in tension with concentrated private control of communicative opportunities.</p><p>These conditions are demanding. We lay them out explicitly in order to consider how the existence of a digitally mediated public sphere—in which platforms provide important informational and communicative infrastructure—bears on these conditions of a well-functioning democratic public sphere.</p><p>As we have argued elsewhere, digitalization of the public sphere has had decidedly mixed effects. In democratic societies and perhaps even in some authoritarian contexts, social media has increased the communicative power of those who previously lacked access to the means of mass communication. We see this inclusion not just in Q-Anon and “Stop the Steal,” but also in the Movement for Black Lives and #MeToo. The opportunities for expression and encountering diverse content have mostly increased with the radical expansion of chances for authorship. But these opportunities for many have constricted because among social media's affordances include the ease of suppressing others’ views through trolling, doxxing, and other forms of attack. Access to reliable information has in some ways increased. But deception, misinformation, and propaganda accompany this informational abundance, and it is not easy to sort between them.</p><p>Building a more democratic public sphere will require concerted action by, among others, governments, private companies, nongovernmental organizations, and citizens themselves. But in the remainder of this contribution, we focus on the responsibilities of individuals and groups who participate in the public sphere as authors, amplifiers, and readers because this aspect has received somewhat less attention. Indeed, many have been skeptical that individuals can rise to meet the challenges of public sphere digitalization or should even be asked or expected to do so.</p><p>Individuals have democratic responsibilities as authors, readers, listeners, viewers, and joiners and participants in collective communicative action. By dramatically reducing the costs of transmitting messages, the digital public sphere has increased the aperture of information and communication. If we wish to avoid reducing opportunities for expression and imposing significant hurdles on access to information, the digital public sphere will impose greater burdens on individuals and groups to distinguish information from manipulation, exercise greater restraint in deciding what to communicate, and sanction others who abuse these norms. Platforms and governments can help to enable that active, affirmative role.</p><p>Many of the democratic benefits of the mass media public sphere depended on journalists who embraced democratic norms and responsibilities (Hamilton, <span>2018</span>). The organizations that employed them—as well as professional organizations—sometimes rewarded those democratic norms. Although the analogy of citizens and groups with professional journalists is very imperfect, internet companies should help users behave as citizens by designing their platforms to foster participants’ democratic orientation. They can also take responsibility for enhancing digital literacy by more explicitly recognizing that some sources are negligent about truth, by spreading habits of checking, and by encouraging users to encounter diverse perspectives.</p><p>But design is not enough; we will also need bottom-up efforts that elicit the right kind of engagement and content generation from users. Focusing, then, on truth and the common good, what do these norms imply for communicative responsibilities?</p><p>In both spheres of mass media and the digital public, the truth-seeking norm requires citizens (including in their role as authors) to be media literate in the sense that they can distinguish information from propaganda. The proliferation of sources and content makes that task more challenging and also more important. Aiding others’ opportunities for access to reliable information requires making some effort to check on the veracity of stories before liking or forwarding them and a disposition to resist amplifying messages that lack truth or undermine civility, even when that amplification is self-satisfying, in-group reinforcing, or profitable. Platforms can help by promoting content from reliable sources, offering tools that enable users to assess the veracity and trustworthiness of specific content and of their information diets in general, by rewarding—and enabling users to reward—truth-seeking behavior on their platforms and also by instructing users about the importance of epistemic humility. Teachers, as well as students of information and communication, could help by developing updated methods (such as attention to the quality of sources, cross-checking assertions, and awareness of confirmation bias) that enable citizens to better discern reliability and relevance in the digital environment.</p><p>Alternatively, consider the commitment to the common good. Although citizens disagree about what justice requires or the ends that society ought to pursue, a commitment to the common good requires citizens to resolve these differences on a basis that respects the equal importance of others.</p><p>Projecting this broad commitment into the digital public sphere, a common good orientation will often require citizens to avoid narrow news diets (Guess, <span>2021</span>). It also requires citizens to be attentive to a broader array of information in order to be able to form views and make appropriate judgments. Doing that, in turn, requires learning about the interests, perspectives, and pain of others. A commitment to the common good thus requires citizens to inhabit parts of the digital public sphere that are common in the sense that they encounter information from diverse perspectives. Citizens should help create these common spaces by putting forth views and perspectives that appeal to across, as well as within, the bounds of identity, ideology, and community.</p><p>A range of other actors, including nongovernmental organizations, can contribute as well. Formal and popular education could help spread those methods widely. Second, such normative and prescriptive accounts ought to be part of civic education and socialization. Clear rules of thumb and expectations would help individuals direct their own attention and offer them an important ethical dimension of judgment and guide their expressions of approval or disapproval. Moreover, third-party organizations—analogous to independent organizations that have emerged around fake news and open educational resources—might call out content or users that violate norms or demote the priority of such posts on news feeds.</p><p>Some media critics suggest that the “golden age” of the mass media sphere in the second half of the twentieth century may have been a historical aberration, bracketed by periods of much greater misinformation, conspiracy theory, and uncivil conflict. While that period benefitted democratic governance in many ways, we should remember that it also limited the authors and speakers mostly to professional journalists reporting on political and business elites. And at least in the United States, the gatekeepers defended “consensus” visions of democratic capitalism, anti-communism, and US foreign policy. As the techno-optimists of the 1990s hoped, digitalization has broken the gates open, adding many more speakers and perspectives to the public sphere. But the quality is dismal, and it lacks orientations toward truth, common good, or civility.</p><p>Looking forward schematically, we may end up with incremental modifications of the <i>status quo</i> digital public sphere. Large platform companies would continue to dominate the design and policy of social media. Advertising and other business objectives would remain primary, with a little more subscription revenue and some responsiveness to the worst communicative excesses. Or we may end up with more determined regulation of the supply side of the public sphere—perhaps by algorithmically or legally (through requirements on risk assessment and stronger standards on intermediary liability) demoting or taking down stories deemed to be false or harmful and by increasing the proportion of content produced by professional, high-quality sources.</p><p>Whichever direction dominates, we think that fostering participant responsibilities must play a central role in remedying the deficiencies of the digital public sphere in order to capture some of the desirable qualities of the mass media public sphere—in particular production of reliable information and access to it—while preserving the gains in inclusiveness brought by the digital public sphere. This level of public responsibility will not be easy to achieve if it can be achieved at all. But we think it is worth trying because we are not yet ready to sacrifice the democratic ideal of substantively equal communicative freedom that would be lost. Nor do we think that a more expansive guardian role for regulated platforms is the best we can hope for.</p>","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.2000,"publicationDate":"2023-03-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12670","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Democratic responsibility in the digital public sphere\",\"authors\":\"Joshua Cohen,&nbsp;Archon Fung\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/1467-8675.12670\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>Despite accumulating challenges, digital information and communication technologies retain considerable democratic potential. They have enabled movements, mass protests, and open-data initiatives in cities. But as we have all learned from the failures of an earlier wave of techno-utopianism, the democratic exploitation of technological affordances is deeply contingent—dependent on ethical conviction, political engagement, public regulation, and good design choices. In particular, and in the spirit of Habermas’ remark quoted at the outset, we think that the democratic potential will only be realized if participants in what we will be calling “the digital public sphere” deepen their sense of responsibility for how communication proceeds there.</p><p>A brief clarification: by “the digital public sphere,” we mean a public sphere in which discussion about matters of potentially shared concern is shaped in part by communication on online platforms (intermediaries that store users’ information and enable its public dissemination). Thus, the digital public sphere is neither everything that happens online or on online platforms (much of which is not discussion of matters of shared concern), nor is it only online. It is a public sphere in which communication on platforms plays an important role in shaping public discussion.</p><p>We will begin by sketching an idealized democratic public sphere, which marries inclusion and deliberation. Our current digitalized public sphere is dramatically more inclusive than the post-war mass media public sphere. But this expansion of inclusion has come at a substantial deliberative price. To improve the quality of public discussion, we focus on the responsibilities that participants must take on for the digital public sphere to be more democratically successful.</p><p>To be sure, participant action is insufficient. We and others have offered suggestions for the contributions of regulation, corporate responsibility, and the contributions of researchers, as well as civic and advocacy organizations. The European Union's new regulations on Intermediary Services, for example, the Digital Services Act, include requirements on illegal content and impose due diligence responsibilities on very large online platforms that will need to do audited systematic risk assessments and offer plans for remediation (Husovec &amp; Roche Laguna, <span>2022</span>). This approach has much to be said for it (though with the proliferation of generative models, it may be addressed to last year's problems). But because the digital public sphere has vastly expanded the aperture for contributions to discussion, and because we are uneasy about regulating the substance of public discussion, we are skeptical about proposals to turn public regulators or platforms (or any other agents) into editorial guardians.</p><p>Emphasizing participant responsibilities may give the appearance that we are at once blaming and burdening the victims of degraded public discussion. We resist that characterization. Instead, we focus here on the role of participants because they <i>must</i> become more capable and responsible if we are to retain the democratically attractive qualities of greater inclusion that the digital public sphere has brought. Relying solely on regulatory mechanisms, whether public or private, will create guardians over the practice of public communication. And such guardianship seems to give up on the democratic promise of self-government by consociates.</p><p>We begin with the idea of a democratic society whose free and equal members use their common reason to argue about the substance of public issues and in which the exercise of power is guided by that use. The animating idea is to marry broad opportunities for participation by members with their engagement about the merits of different courses of public action: to combine an inclusive democracy with public reasoning. Thus understood, democratic politics—as a discursive exercise of political autonomy—depends on informal, open-ended, fluid, dispersed public discussions of matters of common concern.</p><p>These conditions, which together describe a structure of equal, substantive communicative freedom, have far-reaching political, social, and economic implications. Equal standing in public reasoning requires favorable social background conditions, including limits on socioeconomic inequality and the dependencies associated with it. Similarly, the conjunction of rights and expression is in tension with concentrated private control of communicative opportunities.</p><p>These conditions are demanding. We lay them out explicitly in order to consider how the existence of a digitally mediated public sphere—in which platforms provide important informational and communicative infrastructure—bears on these conditions of a well-functioning democratic public sphere.</p><p>As we have argued elsewhere, digitalization of the public sphere has had decidedly mixed effects. In democratic societies and perhaps even in some authoritarian contexts, social media has increased the communicative power of those who previously lacked access to the means of mass communication. We see this inclusion not just in Q-Anon and “Stop the Steal,” but also in the Movement for Black Lives and #MeToo. The opportunities for expression and encountering diverse content have mostly increased with the radical expansion of chances for authorship. But these opportunities for many have constricted because among social media's affordances include the ease of suppressing others’ views through trolling, doxxing, and other forms of attack. Access to reliable information has in some ways increased. But deception, misinformation, and propaganda accompany this informational abundance, and it is not easy to sort between them.</p><p>Building a more democratic public sphere will require concerted action by, among others, governments, private companies, nongovernmental organizations, and citizens themselves. But in the remainder of this contribution, we focus on the responsibilities of individuals and groups who participate in the public sphere as authors, amplifiers, and readers because this aspect has received somewhat less attention. Indeed, many have been skeptical that individuals can rise to meet the challenges of public sphere digitalization or should even be asked or expected to do so.</p><p>Individuals have democratic responsibilities as authors, readers, listeners, viewers, and joiners and participants in collective communicative action. By dramatically reducing the costs of transmitting messages, the digital public sphere has increased the aperture of information and communication. If we wish to avoid reducing opportunities for expression and imposing significant hurdles on access to information, the digital public sphere will impose greater burdens on individuals and groups to distinguish information from manipulation, exercise greater restraint in deciding what to communicate, and sanction others who abuse these norms. Platforms and governments can help to enable that active, affirmative role.</p><p>Many of the democratic benefits of the mass media public sphere depended on journalists who embraced democratic norms and responsibilities (Hamilton, <span>2018</span>). The organizations that employed them—as well as professional organizations—sometimes rewarded those democratic norms. Although the analogy of citizens and groups with professional journalists is very imperfect, internet companies should help users behave as citizens by designing their platforms to foster participants’ democratic orientation. They can also take responsibility for enhancing digital literacy by more explicitly recognizing that some sources are negligent about truth, by spreading habits of checking, and by encouraging users to encounter diverse perspectives.</p><p>But design is not enough; we will also need bottom-up efforts that elicit the right kind of engagement and content generation from users. Focusing, then, on truth and the common good, what do these norms imply for communicative responsibilities?</p><p>In both spheres of mass media and the digital public, the truth-seeking norm requires citizens (including in their role as authors) to be media literate in the sense that they can distinguish information from propaganda. The proliferation of sources and content makes that task more challenging and also more important. Aiding others’ opportunities for access to reliable information requires making some effort to check on the veracity of stories before liking or forwarding them and a disposition to resist amplifying messages that lack truth or undermine civility, even when that amplification is self-satisfying, in-group reinforcing, or profitable. Platforms can help by promoting content from reliable sources, offering tools that enable users to assess the veracity and trustworthiness of specific content and of their information diets in general, by rewarding—and enabling users to reward—truth-seeking behavior on their platforms and also by instructing users about the importance of epistemic humility. Teachers, as well as students of information and communication, could help by developing updated methods (such as attention to the quality of sources, cross-checking assertions, and awareness of confirmation bias) that enable citizens to better discern reliability and relevance in the digital environment.</p><p>Alternatively, consider the commitment to the common good. Although citizens disagree about what justice requires or the ends that society ought to pursue, a commitment to the common good requires citizens to resolve these differences on a basis that respects the equal importance of others.</p><p>Projecting this broad commitment into the digital public sphere, a common good orientation will often require citizens to avoid narrow news diets (Guess, <span>2021</span>). It also requires citizens to be attentive to a broader array of information in order to be able to form views and make appropriate judgments. Doing that, in turn, requires learning about the interests, perspectives, and pain of others. A commitment to the common good thus requires citizens to inhabit parts of the digital public sphere that are common in the sense that they encounter information from diverse perspectives. Citizens should help create these common spaces by putting forth views and perspectives that appeal to across, as well as within, the bounds of identity, ideology, and community.</p><p>A range of other actors, including nongovernmental organizations, can contribute as well. Formal and popular education could help spread those methods widely. Second, such normative and prescriptive accounts ought to be part of civic education and socialization. Clear rules of thumb and expectations would help individuals direct their own attention and offer them an important ethical dimension of judgment and guide their expressions of approval or disapproval. Moreover, third-party organizations—analogous to independent organizations that have emerged around fake news and open educational resources—might call out content or users that violate norms or demote the priority of such posts on news feeds.</p><p>Some media critics suggest that the “golden age” of the mass media sphere in the second half of the twentieth century may have been a historical aberration, bracketed by periods of much greater misinformation, conspiracy theory, and uncivil conflict. While that period benefitted democratic governance in many ways, we should remember that it also limited the authors and speakers mostly to professional journalists reporting on political and business elites. And at least in the United States, the gatekeepers defended “consensus” visions of democratic capitalism, anti-communism, and US foreign policy. As the techno-optimists of the 1990s hoped, digitalization has broken the gates open, adding many more speakers and perspectives to the public sphere. But the quality is dismal, and it lacks orientations toward truth, common good, or civility.</p><p>Looking forward schematically, we may end up with incremental modifications of the <i>status quo</i> digital public sphere. Large platform companies would continue to dominate the design and policy of social media. Advertising and other business objectives would remain primary, with a little more subscription revenue and some responsiveness to the worst communicative excesses. Or we may end up with more determined regulation of the supply side of the public sphere—perhaps by algorithmically or legally (through requirements on risk assessment and stronger standards on intermediary liability) demoting or taking down stories deemed to be false or harmful and by increasing the proportion of content produced by professional, high-quality sources.</p><p>Whichever direction dominates, we think that fostering participant responsibilities must play a central role in remedying the deficiencies of the digital public sphere in order to capture some of the desirable qualities of the mass media public sphere—in particular production of reliable information and access to it—while preserving the gains in inclusiveness brought by the digital public sphere. This level of public responsibility will not be easy to achieve if it can be achieved at all. But we think it is worth trying because we are not yet ready to sacrifice the democratic ideal of substantively equal communicative freedom that would be lost. Nor do we think that a more expansive guardian role for regulated platforms is the best we can hope for.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":51578,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":1.2000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-03-30\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12670\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12670\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"POLITICAL SCIENCE\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12670","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"POLITICAL SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

尽管挑战不断积累,数字信息和通信技术仍具有相当大的民主潜力。它们促成了城市中的运动、大规模抗议和开放数据倡议。但是,正如我们从早期技术乌托邦主义浪潮的失败中学到的那样,对技术支持的民主利用是非常偶然的——依赖于道德信念、政治参与、公共监管和良好的设计选择。特别是,在哈贝马斯一开始引用的评论精神中,我们认为民主的潜力只有在我们称之为“数字公共领域”的参与者加深他们对如何在那里进行交流的责任感时才能实现。简单澄清一下:所谓“数字公共领域”,我们指的是一个公共领域,在这个公共领域中,关于潜在共同关心的问题的讨论部分是由在线平台(存储用户信息并使其公开传播的中介)上的交流形成的。因此,数字公共领域既不是发生在网上或在线平台上的一切(其中大部分不是对共同关心的问题的讨论),也不仅仅是在线的。这是一个公共领域,平台上的交流在塑造公共讨论方面发挥着重要作用。我们将从描绘一个理想化的民主公共领域开始,它将包容和审议结合在一起。我们当前的数字化公共领域比战后的大众媒体公共领域更具包容性。但是,这种包容性的扩大已经付出了沉重的代价。为了提高公共讨论的质量,我们关注参与者必须承担的责任,以使数字公共领域在民主方面取得更大的成功。当然,参与者的行动是不够的。我们和其他人就监管、企业责任、研究人员以及市民团体和倡导团体的贡献提出了建议。例如,欧盟关于中介服务的新法规《数字服务法案》(Digital Services Act)包括对非法内容的要求,并对大型在线平台施加尽职调查责任,这些平台需要进行审计的系统性风险评估,并提供补救计划(Husovec &Roche Laguna, 2022)。这种方法有很多值得说的(尽管随着生成模型的扩散,它可能会解决去年的问题)。但是,由于数字公共领域极大地扩大了讨论的贡献范围,而且由于我们对规范公共讨论的实质感到不安,我们对将公共监管机构或平台(或任何其他代理)转变为编辑监护人的提议持怀疑态度。强调参与者的责任可能会给人一种表象,即我们在指责和加重不体面的公共讨论的受害者。我们反对这种描述。相反,我们在这里关注参与者的作用,因为如果我们要保留数字公共领域带来的更大包容性的民主吸引力,他们必须变得更有能力和更负责任。仅仅依靠监管机制,无论是公共的还是私人的,都会对公共传播的实践产生监管。这种监护似乎放弃了联合企业自治的民主承诺。我们从一个民主社会的概念开始,在这个社会中,自由和平等的成员利用他们共同的理性来争论公共问题的实质,在这个社会中,权力的行使受到这种运用的指导。这个充满活力的想法是,将成员广泛参与的机会与他们对不同公共行动方案的优点的参与结合起来:将包容性民主与公共推理结合起来。因此,民主政治——作为一种政治自主的话语练习——依赖于非正式的、开放的、流动的、分散的公众对共同关心的问题的讨论。这些条件共同描述了一个平等的、实质性的交流自由的结构,具有深远的政治、社会和经济影响。在公共推理中的平等地位需要有利的社会背景条件,包括限制社会经济不平等及其相关的依赖。同样,权利和表达的结合与交际机会的集中私人控制是紧张的。这些条件要求很高。我们明确地列出它们,是为了考虑数字媒介公共领域的存在——其中平台提供了重要的信息和交流基础设施——如何影响一个运作良好的民主公共领域的这些条件。正如我们在其他地方讨论过的那样,公共领域的数字化无疑产生了复杂的影响。 在民主社会中,甚至在一些专制环境中,社交媒体增加了那些以前无法获得大众传播手段的人的沟通能力。我们不仅在Q-Anon和“停止偷窃”中看到了这种包容,在“黑人生命运动”和“我也是”运动中也看到了这种包容。表达和接触不同内容的机会大多随着作者身份机会的急剧扩大而增加。但对许多人来说,这些机会已经减少了,因为社交媒体的优点之一是,可以通过钓鱼、钓鱼和其他形式的攻击来轻松压制他人的观点。在某些方面,获得可靠信息的机会有所增加。但是欺骗、错误信息和宣传伴随着信息的丰富,很难在它们之间进行区分。建立一个更加民主的公共领域需要各国政府、私营企业、非政府组织和公民自己采取协调一致的行动。但在这篇文章的其余部分,我们将重点关注作为作者、放大器和读者参与公共领域的个人和团体的责任,因为这方面受到的关注较少。事实上,许多人一直怀疑个人是否能够应对公共领域数字化的挑战,或者是否应该被要求或期望这样做。作为作者、读者、听众、观众以及集体交流行动的参与者,个人负有民主责任。数字公共领域大大降低了传递信息的成本,扩大了信息和通信的范围。如果我们希望避免减少表达的机会,避免对获取信息设置重大障碍,数字公共领域将给个人和团体带来更大的负担,让他们区分信息与操纵,在决定交流什么方面施加更大的克制,并制裁滥用这些规范的人。平台和政府可以帮助实现这种积极、积极的作用。大众媒体公共领域的许多民主利益取决于接受民主规范和责任的记者(Hamilton, 2018)。雇佣他们的组织——以及专业组织——有时会奖励这些民主规范。虽然公民和团体与专业记者的类比非常不完善,但互联网公司应该通过设计平台来培养参与者的民主取向,帮助用户表现得像公民一样。他们还可以通过更明确地认识到一些消息来源对真相的忽视、传播检查习惯、鼓励用户接触不同的观点,来承担提高数字素养的责任。但光有设计是不够的;我们还需要自下而上的努力,从用户那里引出正确的参与和内容生成。那么,聚焦于真理和共同利益,这些规范对沟通责任意味着什么?在大众媒体和数字公众这两个领域,寻求真相的规范要求公民(包括他们作为作者的角色)具有媒体素养,即他们能够区分信息和宣传。来源和内容的激增使这项任务更具挑战性,也更加重要。为他人提供获得可靠信息的机会,需要在点赞或转发之前努力核实故事的真实性,并有一种抵制放大缺乏真实性或破坏文明的信息的倾向,即使这种放大是自我满足、强化群体内部或有利可图的。平台可以通过以下方式提供帮助:推广来自可靠来源的内容,提供工具,使用户能够评估特定内容和他们的信息饮食的真实性和可信度,通过奖励(并允许用户奖励)他们平台上的寻求真相的行为,以及通过指导用户认识谦卑的重要性。教师以及信息和传播专业的学生可以通过开发更新的方法(例如关注来源的质量、交叉检查断言和对确认偏差的认识)来提供帮助,使公民能够更好地辨别数字环境中的可靠性和相关性。或者,考虑一下对共同利益的承诺。尽管公民对正义的要求或社会应该追求的目标存在分歧,但对共同利益的承诺要求公民在尊重他人同等重要性的基础上解决这些分歧。将这种广泛的承诺投射到数字公共领域,共同的良好取向通常要求公民避免狭隘的新闻饮食(Guess, 2021)。 它还要求公民关注更广泛的信息,以便能够形成观点并做出适当的判断。反过来,要做到这一点,就需要了解他人的兴趣、观点和痛苦。因此,对共同利益的承诺要求公民居住在数字公共领域的共同部分,因为他们从不同的角度接触信息。公民应该通过提出观点和观点来帮助创造这些公共空间,这些观点和观点既能吸引身份、意识形态和社区的界限,也能吸引内部的界限。包括非政府组织在内的一系列其他行为体也可以作出贡献。正规和普及的教育有助于这些方法的广泛传播。其次,这种规范性和规定性的描述应该成为公民教育和社会化的一部分。明确的经验法则和期望将帮助个人引导自己的注意力,为他们提供一个重要的道德判断维度,并指导他们表达赞成或不赞成。此外,第三方组织——类似于围绕假新闻和开放教育资源出现的独立组织——可能会指出违反规范的内容或用户,或者降低此类帖子在新闻推送中的优先级。一些媒体评论家认为,20世纪下半叶大众媒体领域的“黄金时代”可能是一种历史偏差,其间充斥着更严重的错误信息、阴谋论和非民间冲突。虽然那个时期在许多方面有利于民主治理,但我们应该记住,它也将作者和演讲者主要限制为报道政治和商业精英的专业记者。至少在美国,守门人捍卫民主资本主义、反共主义和美国外交政策的“共识”愿景。正如20世纪90年代技术乐观主义者所希望的那样,数字化已经打开了大门,为公共领域增加了更多的演讲者和观点。但它的质量是令人沮丧的,它缺乏对真理、共同利益或文明的导向。展望未来,我们最终可能会对数字公共领域的现状进行渐进式修改。大型平台公司将继续主导社交媒体的设计和政策。广告和其他商业目标仍将是主要的,订阅收入会多一点,对最糟糕的过度交流也会有一些反应。或者,我们最终可能会对公共领域的供给方进行更坚定的监管——也许是通过算法或法律(通过对风险评估的要求和对中介责任的更严格标准)降级或删除被认为是虚假或有害的故事,并增加专业、高质量来源制作的内容的比例。无论哪个方向占主导地位,我们认为,促进参与者的责任必须在弥补数字公共领域的缺陷方面发挥核心作用,以便获得大众媒体公共领域的一些理想品质——特别是可靠信息的生产和获取——同时保持数字公共领域带来的包容性收益。这种程度的公共责任即使能够实现,也不容易实现。但我们认为这是值得一试的,因为我们还没有准备好牺牲实质上平等的交流自由的民主理想,这种理想可能会失去。我们也不认为受监管平台扮演更广泛的监护人角色是我们所能期待的最好结果。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Democratic responsibility in the digital public sphere

Despite accumulating challenges, digital information and communication technologies retain considerable democratic potential. They have enabled movements, mass protests, and open-data initiatives in cities. But as we have all learned from the failures of an earlier wave of techno-utopianism, the democratic exploitation of technological affordances is deeply contingent—dependent on ethical conviction, political engagement, public regulation, and good design choices. In particular, and in the spirit of Habermas’ remark quoted at the outset, we think that the democratic potential will only be realized if participants in what we will be calling “the digital public sphere” deepen their sense of responsibility for how communication proceeds there.

A brief clarification: by “the digital public sphere,” we mean a public sphere in which discussion about matters of potentially shared concern is shaped in part by communication on online platforms (intermediaries that store users’ information and enable its public dissemination). Thus, the digital public sphere is neither everything that happens online or on online platforms (much of which is not discussion of matters of shared concern), nor is it only online. It is a public sphere in which communication on platforms plays an important role in shaping public discussion.

We will begin by sketching an idealized democratic public sphere, which marries inclusion and deliberation. Our current digitalized public sphere is dramatically more inclusive than the post-war mass media public sphere. But this expansion of inclusion has come at a substantial deliberative price. To improve the quality of public discussion, we focus on the responsibilities that participants must take on for the digital public sphere to be more democratically successful.

To be sure, participant action is insufficient. We and others have offered suggestions for the contributions of regulation, corporate responsibility, and the contributions of researchers, as well as civic and advocacy organizations. The European Union's new regulations on Intermediary Services, for example, the Digital Services Act, include requirements on illegal content and impose due diligence responsibilities on very large online platforms that will need to do audited systematic risk assessments and offer plans for remediation (Husovec & Roche Laguna, 2022). This approach has much to be said for it (though with the proliferation of generative models, it may be addressed to last year's problems). But because the digital public sphere has vastly expanded the aperture for contributions to discussion, and because we are uneasy about regulating the substance of public discussion, we are skeptical about proposals to turn public regulators or platforms (or any other agents) into editorial guardians.

Emphasizing participant responsibilities may give the appearance that we are at once blaming and burdening the victims of degraded public discussion. We resist that characterization. Instead, we focus here on the role of participants because they must become more capable and responsible if we are to retain the democratically attractive qualities of greater inclusion that the digital public sphere has brought. Relying solely on regulatory mechanisms, whether public or private, will create guardians over the practice of public communication. And such guardianship seems to give up on the democratic promise of self-government by consociates.

We begin with the idea of a democratic society whose free and equal members use their common reason to argue about the substance of public issues and in which the exercise of power is guided by that use. The animating idea is to marry broad opportunities for participation by members with their engagement about the merits of different courses of public action: to combine an inclusive democracy with public reasoning. Thus understood, democratic politics—as a discursive exercise of political autonomy—depends on informal, open-ended, fluid, dispersed public discussions of matters of common concern.

These conditions, which together describe a structure of equal, substantive communicative freedom, have far-reaching political, social, and economic implications. Equal standing in public reasoning requires favorable social background conditions, including limits on socioeconomic inequality and the dependencies associated with it. Similarly, the conjunction of rights and expression is in tension with concentrated private control of communicative opportunities.

These conditions are demanding. We lay them out explicitly in order to consider how the existence of a digitally mediated public sphere—in which platforms provide important informational and communicative infrastructure—bears on these conditions of a well-functioning democratic public sphere.

As we have argued elsewhere, digitalization of the public sphere has had decidedly mixed effects. In democratic societies and perhaps even in some authoritarian contexts, social media has increased the communicative power of those who previously lacked access to the means of mass communication. We see this inclusion not just in Q-Anon and “Stop the Steal,” but also in the Movement for Black Lives and #MeToo. The opportunities for expression and encountering diverse content have mostly increased with the radical expansion of chances for authorship. But these opportunities for many have constricted because among social media's affordances include the ease of suppressing others’ views through trolling, doxxing, and other forms of attack. Access to reliable information has in some ways increased. But deception, misinformation, and propaganda accompany this informational abundance, and it is not easy to sort between them.

Building a more democratic public sphere will require concerted action by, among others, governments, private companies, nongovernmental organizations, and citizens themselves. But in the remainder of this contribution, we focus on the responsibilities of individuals and groups who participate in the public sphere as authors, amplifiers, and readers because this aspect has received somewhat less attention. Indeed, many have been skeptical that individuals can rise to meet the challenges of public sphere digitalization or should even be asked or expected to do so.

Individuals have democratic responsibilities as authors, readers, listeners, viewers, and joiners and participants in collective communicative action. By dramatically reducing the costs of transmitting messages, the digital public sphere has increased the aperture of information and communication. If we wish to avoid reducing opportunities for expression and imposing significant hurdles on access to information, the digital public sphere will impose greater burdens on individuals and groups to distinguish information from manipulation, exercise greater restraint in deciding what to communicate, and sanction others who abuse these norms. Platforms and governments can help to enable that active, affirmative role.

Many of the democratic benefits of the mass media public sphere depended on journalists who embraced democratic norms and responsibilities (Hamilton, 2018). The organizations that employed them—as well as professional organizations—sometimes rewarded those democratic norms. Although the analogy of citizens and groups with professional journalists is very imperfect, internet companies should help users behave as citizens by designing their platforms to foster participants’ democratic orientation. They can also take responsibility for enhancing digital literacy by more explicitly recognizing that some sources are negligent about truth, by spreading habits of checking, and by encouraging users to encounter diverse perspectives.

But design is not enough; we will also need bottom-up efforts that elicit the right kind of engagement and content generation from users. Focusing, then, on truth and the common good, what do these norms imply for communicative responsibilities?

In both spheres of mass media and the digital public, the truth-seeking norm requires citizens (including in their role as authors) to be media literate in the sense that they can distinguish information from propaganda. The proliferation of sources and content makes that task more challenging and also more important. Aiding others’ opportunities for access to reliable information requires making some effort to check on the veracity of stories before liking or forwarding them and a disposition to resist amplifying messages that lack truth or undermine civility, even when that amplification is self-satisfying, in-group reinforcing, or profitable. Platforms can help by promoting content from reliable sources, offering tools that enable users to assess the veracity and trustworthiness of specific content and of their information diets in general, by rewarding—and enabling users to reward—truth-seeking behavior on their platforms and also by instructing users about the importance of epistemic humility. Teachers, as well as students of information and communication, could help by developing updated methods (such as attention to the quality of sources, cross-checking assertions, and awareness of confirmation bias) that enable citizens to better discern reliability and relevance in the digital environment.

Alternatively, consider the commitment to the common good. Although citizens disagree about what justice requires or the ends that society ought to pursue, a commitment to the common good requires citizens to resolve these differences on a basis that respects the equal importance of others.

Projecting this broad commitment into the digital public sphere, a common good orientation will often require citizens to avoid narrow news diets (Guess, 2021). It also requires citizens to be attentive to a broader array of information in order to be able to form views and make appropriate judgments. Doing that, in turn, requires learning about the interests, perspectives, and pain of others. A commitment to the common good thus requires citizens to inhabit parts of the digital public sphere that are common in the sense that they encounter information from diverse perspectives. Citizens should help create these common spaces by putting forth views and perspectives that appeal to across, as well as within, the bounds of identity, ideology, and community.

A range of other actors, including nongovernmental organizations, can contribute as well. Formal and popular education could help spread those methods widely. Second, such normative and prescriptive accounts ought to be part of civic education and socialization. Clear rules of thumb and expectations would help individuals direct their own attention and offer them an important ethical dimension of judgment and guide their expressions of approval or disapproval. Moreover, third-party organizations—analogous to independent organizations that have emerged around fake news and open educational resources—might call out content or users that violate norms or demote the priority of such posts on news feeds.

Some media critics suggest that the “golden age” of the mass media sphere in the second half of the twentieth century may have been a historical aberration, bracketed by periods of much greater misinformation, conspiracy theory, and uncivil conflict. While that period benefitted democratic governance in many ways, we should remember that it also limited the authors and speakers mostly to professional journalists reporting on political and business elites. And at least in the United States, the gatekeepers defended “consensus” visions of democratic capitalism, anti-communism, and US foreign policy. As the techno-optimists of the 1990s hoped, digitalization has broken the gates open, adding many more speakers and perspectives to the public sphere. But the quality is dismal, and it lacks orientations toward truth, common good, or civility.

Looking forward schematically, we may end up with incremental modifications of the status quo digital public sphere. Large platform companies would continue to dominate the design and policy of social media. Advertising and other business objectives would remain primary, with a little more subscription revenue and some responsiveness to the worst communicative excesses. Or we may end up with more determined regulation of the supply side of the public sphere—perhaps by algorithmically or legally (through requirements on risk assessment and stronger standards on intermediary liability) demoting or taking down stories deemed to be false or harmful and by increasing the proportion of content produced by professional, high-quality sources.

Whichever direction dominates, we think that fostering participant responsibilities must play a central role in remedying the deficiencies of the digital public sphere in order to capture some of the desirable qualities of the mass media public sphere—in particular production of reliable information and access to it—while preserving the gains in inclusiveness brought by the digital public sphere. This level of public responsibility will not be easy to achieve if it can be achieved at all. But we think it is worth trying because we are not yet ready to sacrifice the democratic ideal of substantively equal communicative freedom that would be lost. Nor do we think that a more expansive guardian role for regulated platforms is the best we can hope for.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
52
期刊最新文献
Issue Information Issue Information Fear of Black Consciousness By Lewis R. Gordon. Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2022 Deparochializing Political Theory By Melissa S. Williams, New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 2020 The Force of Truth: Critique, Genealogy, and Truth-Telling in Michel Foucault By Daniele Lorenzini, Chicago/London: The University of Chicago Press, 2023
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1