档案伦理与档案事业职业化

Q2 Arts and Humanities Journal of Information Ethics Pub Date : 2013-09-01 DOI:10.3172/JIE.22.2.46
Ron Houston
{"title":"档案伦理与档案事业职业化","authors":"Ron Houston","doi":"10.3172/JIE.22.2.46","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"IntroductionArchivists ride the horns of dilemmas, constantly juggling priorities to minimize conflict. Such dilemmas include* the need to conserve versus the need to handle delicate items,* the need to acquire versus lack of storage space,* privacy rights versus the public's right to know,* the need for financial patronage versus the need for autonomy,* an item's enduring value versus the cost of its conservation requirements, and* the lure of new preservation technologies versus their unproven lon - gevity.To choose the lemma, that \"horn\" upon which to ride, archivists use intuition, judgment based on training, institutional guidelines, and documents such as the Core Values of Archivists and the Code of Ethics for Archivists (Society of American Archivists, 2011, 2012, 2012). These two documents purport to guide the behavior of archivists who master their 2,300 words. Their histories, found, for example, in Horn (1989, pp. 65 -66) and Cox (2008, pp. 1128-1129), show that committees repeatedly refined these documents, rather than defining fundamental concepts such as \"ethics,\" \"trust,\" and \"profession.\"I suggest that such codes prevent archivists from acting ethically in any sense other than a circular \"according to the code of ethics.\" Karl Popper (1966, p. 552) presented a similar position, excerpted in van Meijl (2000, p. 74) and Wallace (2010, p. 178):What does it [scientific ethics] aim at? At telling us what we ought to do, i.e., at constructing a code of norms upon a scientific basis, so that we need only look up the index of the code if we are faced with a difficult moral decision? This clearly would be absurd; quite apart from the fact that if it could be achieved, it would destroy all personal responsibility and therefore all ethics.Hauptman and Hill (1991, p. 43) also discussed ethical codes with respect to responsibility:[C]ommentators have come to the individual's defense in this context by insisting that since individual members of an organization only do part of a job or only follow instructions (orders) or, by extension, only adhere to an ethical code [emphasis added], they really cannot be held responsible for general negative results.I suggest a somewhat different standard based in part on new or re-worded principal precepts. The bulk of this paper explains the need and derivation of these precepts followed by suggestions for implementation, and the conclusion restates the precepts. Please note that this paper discusses archival enterprise as practiced in the U.S., although the concepts also should apply to archives worldwide. Broader and deeper discussions of archival codes of ethics, per se, occur in Neazor (2007) and Dingwall (2004). Any discussion of ethics, however, requires us archivists to ride our lemmas boldly through several quandaries.First Quandary\"[W]e [philosophers] have first rais'd a Dust, and then complain, we cannot see\" (Berkeley, 1734). Many wits denigrate philosophy through this quotation, and frankly, I agree. Philosophy has, however, given form to some aspects of information science, and we overcome our first quandary, the morass of philosophy, by limiting our exploration of philosophy to one set of forms, those discussing moral philosophy, or ethics. Further, we will limit inquiry to normative ethics, and to only three branches of normative ethics:1. Virtue ethics (Are your intentions moral?)2. Deontology (Do you follow the rules?)3. Teleological ethics, or, Consequentialism (Do the ends justify the means?)4. Pragmatic ethics (not used as such in this paper because of its imprecision).Second QuandaryIn this paper, ethics refers to conceptualizations of right and wrong behavior and frequently finds expression in dictums about what we should and should not do: \"Lying is wrong!\" Such dictums are doomed, however, without prior definition of right and wrong, and each person has a unique definition of right and wrong. …","PeriodicalId":39913,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Information Ethics","volume":"22 1","pages":"46-60"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2013-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"3","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Archival Ethics and the Professionalization of Archival Enterprise\",\"authors\":\"Ron Houston\",\"doi\":\"10.3172/JIE.22.2.46\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"IntroductionArchivists ride the horns of dilemmas, constantly juggling priorities to minimize conflict. Such dilemmas include* the need to conserve versus the need to handle delicate items,* the need to acquire versus lack of storage space,* privacy rights versus the public's right to know,* the need for financial patronage versus the need for autonomy,* an item's enduring value versus the cost of its conservation requirements, and* the lure of new preservation technologies versus their unproven lon - gevity.To choose the lemma, that \\\"horn\\\" upon which to ride, archivists use intuition, judgment based on training, institutional guidelines, and documents such as the Core Values of Archivists and the Code of Ethics for Archivists (Society of American Archivists, 2011, 2012, 2012). These two documents purport to guide the behavior of archivists who master their 2,300 words. Their histories, found, for example, in Horn (1989, pp. 65 -66) and Cox (2008, pp. 1128-1129), show that committees repeatedly refined these documents, rather than defining fundamental concepts such as \\\"ethics,\\\" \\\"trust,\\\" and \\\"profession.\\\"I suggest that such codes prevent archivists from acting ethically in any sense other than a circular \\\"according to the code of ethics.\\\" Karl Popper (1966, p. 552) presented a similar position, excerpted in van Meijl (2000, p. 74) and Wallace (2010, p. 178):What does it [scientific ethics] aim at? At telling us what we ought to do, i.e., at constructing a code of norms upon a scientific basis, so that we need only look up the index of the code if we are faced with a difficult moral decision? This clearly would be absurd; quite apart from the fact that if it could be achieved, it would destroy all personal responsibility and therefore all ethics.Hauptman and Hill (1991, p. 43) also discussed ethical codes with respect to responsibility:[C]ommentators have come to the individual's defense in this context by insisting that since individual members of an organization only do part of a job or only follow instructions (orders) or, by extension, only adhere to an ethical code [emphasis added], they really cannot be held responsible for general negative results.I suggest a somewhat different standard based in part on new or re-worded principal precepts. The bulk of this paper explains the need and derivation of these precepts followed by suggestions for implementation, and the conclusion restates the precepts. Please note that this paper discusses archival enterprise as practiced in the U.S., although the concepts also should apply to archives worldwide. Broader and deeper discussions of archival codes of ethics, per se, occur in Neazor (2007) and Dingwall (2004). Any discussion of ethics, however, requires us archivists to ride our lemmas boldly through several quandaries.First Quandary\\\"[W]e [philosophers] have first rais'd a Dust, and then complain, we cannot see\\\" (Berkeley, 1734). Many wits denigrate philosophy through this quotation, and frankly, I agree. Philosophy has, however, given form to some aspects of information science, and we overcome our first quandary, the morass of philosophy, by limiting our exploration of philosophy to one set of forms, those discussing moral philosophy, or ethics. Further, we will limit inquiry to normative ethics, and to only three branches of normative ethics:1. Virtue ethics (Are your intentions moral?)2. Deontology (Do you follow the rules?)3. Teleological ethics, or, Consequentialism (Do the ends justify the means?)4. Pragmatic ethics (not used as such in this paper because of its imprecision).Second QuandaryIn this paper, ethics refers to conceptualizations of right and wrong behavior and frequently finds expression in dictums about what we should and should not do: \\\"Lying is wrong!\\\" Such dictums are doomed, however, without prior definition of right and wrong, and each person has a unique definition of right and wrong. …\",\"PeriodicalId\":39913,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Journal of Information Ethics\",\"volume\":\"22 1\",\"pages\":\"46-60\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2013-09-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"3\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Journal of Information Ethics\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.3172/JIE.22.2.46\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q2\",\"JCRName\":\"Arts and Humanities\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Information Ethics","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.3172/JIE.22.2.46","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q2","JCRName":"Arts and Humanities","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3

摘要

档案保管员在两难的境地中挣扎,不断调整优先级,以尽量减少冲突。这些难题包括:需要保存还是需要处理脆弱的物品;需要获取还是缺乏存储空间;隐私权还是公众知情权;需要经济资助还是需要自治;物品的持久价值还是保存要求的成本;为了选择引理,即“号角”,档案工作者使用直觉、基于培训的判断、制度指南和文件,如档案工作者的核心价值观和档案工作者的道德准则(美国档案工作者协会,2011年,2012年,2012年)。这两份文件旨在指导掌握2300字的档案工作者的行为。例如,在Horn(1989年,第65 -66页)和Cox(2008年,第1128-1129页)中发现,他们的历史表明,委员会反复修改这些文件,而不是定义诸如“道德”、“信任”和“职业”等基本概念。"我认为这样的规范可以阻止档案保管员在任何意义上的道德行为,除非"根据道德规范"发出通告。"卡尔·波普尔(1966年,第552页)提出了类似的立场,摘自van Meijl(2000年,第74页)和Wallace(2010年,第178页):它[科学伦理学]的目标是什么?告诉我们应该做什么,也就是说,在科学的基础上构建一套规范,这样当我们面临一个困难的道德决定时,我们只需要查阅规范的索引?这显然是荒谬的;更不用说,如果它能够实现,它将摧毁所有的个人责任,从而摧毁所有的道德规范。Hauptman和Hill(1991,第43页)也讨论了道德准则与责任的关系:[C]在这种情况下,评论者为个人辩护,他们坚持认为,由于组织中的个人成员只完成工作的一部分,或者只遵循指示(命令),或者延伸到只遵守道德准则[强调添加],他们真的不能对一般的负面结果负责。我建议采用一种不同的标准,部分基于新的或重新措辞的主要规则。本文的大部分内容解释了这些戒律的必要性和来源,随后提出了实施建议,结论部分重申了这些戒律。请注意,本文讨论的是美国的档案企业实践,尽管这些概念也应该适用于全球的档案。就档案伦理规范本身而言,更广泛、更深入的讨论发生在Neazor(2007)和Dingwall(2004)中。然而,任何关于伦理的讨论都要求我们这些档案保管员大胆地驾驭我们的引理,穿越几个困境。“我们[哲学家]先扬起一团尘埃,然后抱怨说,我们看不见”(伯克利,1734)。许多智者通过这句话诋毁哲学,坦率地说,我同意。然而,哲学已经为信息科学的某些方面提供了形式,我们克服了我们的第一个困境,哲学的泥潭,通过将我们对哲学的探索限制在一组形式,即那些讨论道德哲学或伦理学的形式。此外,我们将限制对规范伦理学的探究,并且仅限于规范伦理学的三个分支:1。美德伦理(你的意图是否道德?)义务论(你遵守规则吗?)目的论伦理学,或结果主义(目的证明手段是正当的吗?)实用伦理学(由于其不精确,本文未使用此术语)。在这篇论文中,伦理学指的是对与错的行为的概念化,经常表现为我们应该做什么和不应该做什么:“撒谎是错误的!”然而,如果没有事先对对与错的定义,这样的论断是注定要失败的,每个人对对与错都有自己独特的定义。…
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Archival Ethics and the Professionalization of Archival Enterprise
IntroductionArchivists ride the horns of dilemmas, constantly juggling priorities to minimize conflict. Such dilemmas include* the need to conserve versus the need to handle delicate items,* the need to acquire versus lack of storage space,* privacy rights versus the public's right to know,* the need for financial patronage versus the need for autonomy,* an item's enduring value versus the cost of its conservation requirements, and* the lure of new preservation technologies versus their unproven lon - gevity.To choose the lemma, that "horn" upon which to ride, archivists use intuition, judgment based on training, institutional guidelines, and documents such as the Core Values of Archivists and the Code of Ethics for Archivists (Society of American Archivists, 2011, 2012, 2012). These two documents purport to guide the behavior of archivists who master their 2,300 words. Their histories, found, for example, in Horn (1989, pp. 65 -66) and Cox (2008, pp. 1128-1129), show that committees repeatedly refined these documents, rather than defining fundamental concepts such as "ethics," "trust," and "profession."I suggest that such codes prevent archivists from acting ethically in any sense other than a circular "according to the code of ethics." Karl Popper (1966, p. 552) presented a similar position, excerpted in van Meijl (2000, p. 74) and Wallace (2010, p. 178):What does it [scientific ethics] aim at? At telling us what we ought to do, i.e., at constructing a code of norms upon a scientific basis, so that we need only look up the index of the code if we are faced with a difficult moral decision? This clearly would be absurd; quite apart from the fact that if it could be achieved, it would destroy all personal responsibility and therefore all ethics.Hauptman and Hill (1991, p. 43) also discussed ethical codes with respect to responsibility:[C]ommentators have come to the individual's defense in this context by insisting that since individual members of an organization only do part of a job or only follow instructions (orders) or, by extension, only adhere to an ethical code [emphasis added], they really cannot be held responsible for general negative results.I suggest a somewhat different standard based in part on new or re-worded principal precepts. The bulk of this paper explains the need and derivation of these precepts followed by suggestions for implementation, and the conclusion restates the precepts. Please note that this paper discusses archival enterprise as practiced in the U.S., although the concepts also should apply to archives worldwide. Broader and deeper discussions of archival codes of ethics, per se, occur in Neazor (2007) and Dingwall (2004). Any discussion of ethics, however, requires us archivists to ride our lemmas boldly through several quandaries.First Quandary"[W]e [philosophers] have first rais'd a Dust, and then complain, we cannot see" (Berkeley, 1734). Many wits denigrate philosophy through this quotation, and frankly, I agree. Philosophy has, however, given form to some aspects of information science, and we overcome our first quandary, the morass of philosophy, by limiting our exploration of philosophy to one set of forms, those discussing moral philosophy, or ethics. Further, we will limit inquiry to normative ethics, and to only three branches of normative ethics:1. Virtue ethics (Are your intentions moral?)2. Deontology (Do you follow the rules?)3. Teleological ethics, or, Consequentialism (Do the ends justify the means?)4. Pragmatic ethics (not used as such in this paper because of its imprecision).Second QuandaryIn this paper, ethics refers to conceptualizations of right and wrong behavior and frequently finds expression in dictums about what we should and should not do: "Lying is wrong!" Such dictums are doomed, however, without prior definition of right and wrong, and each person has a unique definition of right and wrong. …
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
Journal of Information Ethics
Journal of Information Ethics Arts and Humanities-Philosophy
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
期刊最新文献
Diversity Matters: Economic Inequality and Policymaking During a Pandemic A Survival Guide to the Misinformation Age: Scientific Habits of Mind Intellectual Privacy: Rethinking Civil Liberties in the Digital Age Hate Crimes in Cyberspace We Believe the Children: A Moral Panic in the 1980s
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1