作为证据的证词

Q4 Arts and Humanities Argumenta Philosophica Pub Date : 2006-01-02 DOI:10.21825/philosophica.82190
Sanford C. Goldberg
{"title":"作为证据的证词","authors":"Sanford C. Goldberg","doi":"10.21825/philosophica.82190","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Regarding testimony as evidence fails to predict the sort of epistemic support testimony provides for testimonial belief. As a result, testimony-based belief should not be assimilated into the category of ep istemically inferen tial, evidence-based belief. 1. Reasons, Evidence, and Inference Holmes is trying to determine who committed the murder. His evidence consists of E1, E2, and E3. It occurs to him that he would have these pieces of evidence only if Mustard did it. He concludes that Mustard committed the murder. Here, the basis of Holmes’ conclusion is (a) his belief that his evidence consists of E1, E2, and E3, (b) his belief that he would have these pieces of evidence only if Mustard committed the murder, (c) whatever it is that supports these beliefs, and (d) whatever it is that bears on Holmes’ entitlement to draw the relevant inference from (a) and (b) to the conclusion that Mustard committed the murder. Smith is suffering from some condition that she would like diagnosed. The doctor notes the manifesting symptoms, S1, S2, and S3. On the basis of observing these symptoms, and having good reason to think that a patient manifests S1, S2, and S3 only if she is suffering from disease D, the doctor diagnoses Smith as suffering from D. Here, the basis of the doctor’s diagnosis is (e) his belief that Smith manifests S1, S2, and S3, (f) his belief that one manifests S1, S2, and S3 only if one is suffering from disease D, (g) whatever it is that supports these beliefs, and (h) whatever it is that bears on the doctor’s entitlement to draw the SANFORD C. GOLDBERG 30 relevant inference from (e) and (f) to the conclusion that Smith suffers from D. My description of these two cases is meant to bring out what I regard as an obvious parallel – one that goes to the heart of the epistemic account of inferential, evidence-based belief. In both case, the materials relevant to an epistemic assessment of the conclusion/diagnosis are the same. They consist of (i) the belief(s) that constitute(s) the subject’s evidence, (ii) the belief(s) that constitute(s) the generalization that links this evidence to the target conclusion/diagnosis, (iii) the epistemic support for all of these beliefs, and (iv) the subject’s entitlement to make the transition from these beliefs to the target conclusion/diagnosis itself. If the evidence-involving inference through which the subject acquired the belief is the only source of support for the belief in question, then (i)(iv) are the only materials that are relevant to the epistemic assessment of the belief: these exhaust the belief’s epistemic support. I will call beliefs of this sort Evidence-based beliefs, or E-beliefs for short. E-beliefs are only as epistemically good as the evidence on which they are based, the generalization(s) applied to that evidence, and the subject-drawn inference(s) to the E-belief itself. We can capture the foregoing idea in terms of the notion of supervenience, as follows: (Spv) The epistemic goodness of an E-belief supervenes on considerations (i)-(iv). According to (Spv), there could not be two E-beliefs alike as to (i)-(iv), but different as to the amount of epistemic support they enjoy. Perhaps Gettier considerations will lead one to doubt (Spv). Such a doubt would be based on the idea that there could be two subjects, alike as to (i)-(iv), but differing as to the epistemic goodness enjoyed by their respective E-beliefs, owing to ‘external’ factors regarding which they were non-culpably ignorant. This issue is vexed; a final verdict will depend on the relevant notion of epistemic goodness as well as the nature of Gettier cases. I will return to these topics, briefly, below. Here, however, I propose to circumvent the matter by conditionalizing (Spv), as follows: TESTIMONY AS EVIDENCE 31 1 This is the belief that evidence E1, E2, and E3, would obtain only if Mustard committed the crime. 2 See G oldberg (2007b) where I discuss the epistemology of inferential belief at","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":"56 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2006-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"3","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Testimony as Evidence\",\"authors\":\"Sanford C. Goldberg\",\"doi\":\"10.21825/philosophica.82190\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Regarding testimony as evidence fails to predict the sort of epistemic support testimony provides for testimonial belief. As a result, testimony-based belief should not be assimilated into the category of ep istemically inferen tial, evidence-based belief. 1. Reasons, Evidence, and Inference Holmes is trying to determine who committed the murder. His evidence consists of E1, E2, and E3. It occurs to him that he would have these pieces of evidence only if Mustard did it. He concludes that Mustard committed the murder. Here, the basis of Holmes’ conclusion is (a) his belief that his evidence consists of E1, E2, and E3, (b) his belief that he would have these pieces of evidence only if Mustard committed the murder, (c) whatever it is that supports these beliefs, and (d) whatever it is that bears on Holmes’ entitlement to draw the relevant inference from (a) and (b) to the conclusion that Mustard committed the murder. Smith is suffering from some condition that she would like diagnosed. The doctor notes the manifesting symptoms, S1, S2, and S3. On the basis of observing these symptoms, and having good reason to think that a patient manifests S1, S2, and S3 only if she is suffering from disease D, the doctor diagnoses Smith as suffering from D. Here, the basis of the doctor’s diagnosis is (e) his belief that Smith manifests S1, S2, and S3, (f) his belief that one manifests S1, S2, and S3 only if one is suffering from disease D, (g) whatever it is that supports these beliefs, and (h) whatever it is that bears on the doctor’s entitlement to draw the SANFORD C. GOLDBERG 30 relevant inference from (e) and (f) to the conclusion that Smith suffers from D. My description of these two cases is meant to bring out what I regard as an obvious parallel – one that goes to the heart of the epistemic account of inferential, evidence-based belief. In both case, the materials relevant to an epistemic assessment of the conclusion/diagnosis are the same. They consist of (i) the belief(s) that constitute(s) the subject’s evidence, (ii) the belief(s) that constitute(s) the generalization that links this evidence to the target conclusion/diagnosis, (iii) the epistemic support for all of these beliefs, and (iv) the subject’s entitlement to make the transition from these beliefs to the target conclusion/diagnosis itself. If the evidence-involving inference through which the subject acquired the belief is the only source of support for the belief in question, then (i)(iv) are the only materials that are relevant to the epistemic assessment of the belief: these exhaust the belief’s epistemic support. I will call beliefs of this sort Evidence-based beliefs, or E-beliefs for short. E-beliefs are only as epistemically good as the evidence on which they are based, the generalization(s) applied to that evidence, and the subject-drawn inference(s) to the E-belief itself. We can capture the foregoing idea in terms of the notion of supervenience, as follows: (Spv) The epistemic goodness of an E-belief supervenes on considerations (i)-(iv). According to (Spv), there could not be two E-beliefs alike as to (i)-(iv), but different as to the amount of epistemic support they enjoy. Perhaps Gettier considerations will lead one to doubt (Spv). Such a doubt would be based on the idea that there could be two subjects, alike as to (i)-(iv), but differing as to the epistemic goodness enjoyed by their respective E-beliefs, owing to ‘external’ factors regarding which they were non-culpably ignorant. This issue is vexed; a final verdict will depend on the relevant notion of epistemic goodness as well as the nature of Gettier cases. I will return to these topics, briefly, below. Here, however, I propose to circumvent the matter by conditionalizing (Spv), as follows: TESTIMONY AS EVIDENCE 31 1 This is the belief that evidence E1, E2, and E3, would obtain only if Mustard committed the crime. 2 See G oldberg (2007b) where I discuss the epistemology of inferential belief at\",\"PeriodicalId\":36843,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Argumenta Philosophica\",\"volume\":\"56 1\",\"pages\":\"\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2006-01-02\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"3\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Argumenta Philosophica\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.21825/philosophica.82190\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q4\",\"JCRName\":\"Arts and Humanities\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Argumenta Philosophica","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.21825/philosophica.82190","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q4","JCRName":"Arts and Humanities","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3

摘要

将证词视为证据并不能预测证词为证词信仰提供的那种认识论支持。因此,以证言为基础的信仰不应被同化为系统推理、循证信仰的范畴。1. 理由、证据和推论福尔摩斯试图确定是谁犯了谋杀罪。他的证据包括E1, E2和E3。他突然想到,只有芥末做了这件事,他才会有这些证据。他断定马斯塔德是凶手。在这里,福尔摩斯结论的基础是(a)他相信他的证据由E1, E2和E3组成,(b)他相信只有当Mustard犯下谋杀罪时他才会有这些证据,(c)支持这些信念的任何东西,以及(d)任何与福尔摩斯有权从(a)和(b)得出Mustard犯下谋杀罪的结论相关的推论有关的东西。史密斯患有某种疾病,她希望得到诊断。医生记录了S1、S2和S3的明显症状。的基础上,观察这些症状,并有充分的理由认为,病人表现S1, S2和S3只有她是患有疾病D,史密斯医生诊断为患有D,医生的诊断是的基础(e)他相信史密斯体现S1, S2和S3 (f)他相信一个体现S1, S2和S3只有一个是患有疾病D (g)支持这些信仰,不管它是什么以及(h)医生有权从(e)和(f)中得出SANFORD C. GOLDBERG 30的相关推论,从而得出史密斯患有d的结论。我对这两个案例的描述是为了提出一个我认为显而易见的相似之处——它触及了推理、循证信仰的认识论的核心。在这两种情况下,与结论/诊断的认知评估相关的材料是相同的。它们包括(i)构成主体证据的信念,(ii)构成将这些证据与目标结论/诊断联系起来的概括的信念,(iii)对所有这些信念的认知支持,以及(iv)主体从这些信念过渡到目标结论/诊断本身的权利。如果主体通过涉及证据的推理获得信念是支持所讨论的信念的唯一来源,那么(i)和(iv)是与信念的认知评估相关的唯一材料:这些耗尽了信念的认知支持。我把这种信念称为基于证据的信念,简称e信念。电子信念只有在它们所基于的证据、应用于该证据的概括以及主体对电子信念本身的推断的认识论上是正确的。我们可以根据监督的概念来捕捉上述概念,如下:(Spv)电子信仰的认知良善监督于考虑(i)-(iv)。根据(Spv),就(i)-(iv)而言,不可能有两个相同的e信念,但它们所享有的认知支持的数量不同。也许更深层的考虑会让人产生怀疑(Spv)。这样的怀疑将基于这样的想法,即可能有两个主体,就(i)-(iv)而言是相同的,但由于他们各自的e信仰所享有的认知善,由于“外部”因素,他们无可指责地无知。这个问题很棘手;最终的判决将取决于相关的认知善的概念以及格蒂埃案例的性质。我将在下面简要地回到这些话题。然而,在这里,我建议通过条件化(Spv)来规避这个问题,如下所示:证词作为证据31这是一种信念,即证据E1, E2和E3只有在Mustard犯下罪行时才能获得。2见G oldberg (2007b),我在其中讨论了推理信仰的认识论
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Testimony as Evidence
Regarding testimony as evidence fails to predict the sort of epistemic support testimony provides for testimonial belief. As a result, testimony-based belief should not be assimilated into the category of ep istemically inferen tial, evidence-based belief. 1. Reasons, Evidence, and Inference Holmes is trying to determine who committed the murder. His evidence consists of E1, E2, and E3. It occurs to him that he would have these pieces of evidence only if Mustard did it. He concludes that Mustard committed the murder. Here, the basis of Holmes’ conclusion is (a) his belief that his evidence consists of E1, E2, and E3, (b) his belief that he would have these pieces of evidence only if Mustard committed the murder, (c) whatever it is that supports these beliefs, and (d) whatever it is that bears on Holmes’ entitlement to draw the relevant inference from (a) and (b) to the conclusion that Mustard committed the murder. Smith is suffering from some condition that she would like diagnosed. The doctor notes the manifesting symptoms, S1, S2, and S3. On the basis of observing these symptoms, and having good reason to think that a patient manifests S1, S2, and S3 only if she is suffering from disease D, the doctor diagnoses Smith as suffering from D. Here, the basis of the doctor’s diagnosis is (e) his belief that Smith manifests S1, S2, and S3, (f) his belief that one manifests S1, S2, and S3 only if one is suffering from disease D, (g) whatever it is that supports these beliefs, and (h) whatever it is that bears on the doctor’s entitlement to draw the SANFORD C. GOLDBERG 30 relevant inference from (e) and (f) to the conclusion that Smith suffers from D. My description of these two cases is meant to bring out what I regard as an obvious parallel – one that goes to the heart of the epistemic account of inferential, evidence-based belief. In both case, the materials relevant to an epistemic assessment of the conclusion/diagnosis are the same. They consist of (i) the belief(s) that constitute(s) the subject’s evidence, (ii) the belief(s) that constitute(s) the generalization that links this evidence to the target conclusion/diagnosis, (iii) the epistemic support for all of these beliefs, and (iv) the subject’s entitlement to make the transition from these beliefs to the target conclusion/diagnosis itself. If the evidence-involving inference through which the subject acquired the belief is the only source of support for the belief in question, then (i)(iv) are the only materials that are relevant to the epistemic assessment of the belief: these exhaust the belief’s epistemic support. I will call beliefs of this sort Evidence-based beliefs, or E-beliefs for short. E-beliefs are only as epistemically good as the evidence on which they are based, the generalization(s) applied to that evidence, and the subject-drawn inference(s) to the E-belief itself. We can capture the foregoing idea in terms of the notion of supervenience, as follows: (Spv) The epistemic goodness of an E-belief supervenes on considerations (i)-(iv). According to (Spv), there could not be two E-beliefs alike as to (i)-(iv), but different as to the amount of epistemic support they enjoy. Perhaps Gettier considerations will lead one to doubt (Spv). Such a doubt would be based on the idea that there could be two subjects, alike as to (i)-(iv), but differing as to the epistemic goodness enjoyed by their respective E-beliefs, owing to ‘external’ factors regarding which they were non-culpably ignorant. This issue is vexed; a final verdict will depend on the relevant notion of epistemic goodness as well as the nature of Gettier cases. I will return to these topics, briefly, below. Here, however, I propose to circumvent the matter by conditionalizing (Spv), as follows: TESTIMONY AS EVIDENCE 31 1 This is the belief that evidence E1, E2, and E3, would obtain only if Mustard committed the crime. 2 See G oldberg (2007b) where I discuss the epistemology of inferential belief at
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
Argumenta Philosophica
Argumenta Philosophica Arts and Humanities-Visual Arts and Performing Arts
CiteScore
0.10
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
期刊最新文献
Naturalisme et scepticisme Naturalismo e cosmopolitismo nell’Antichità Il naturalismo oggi Onnipotenza divina e ordine naturale nel Medioevo La natura e gli stati abituali nell’Etica Nicomachea
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1