首页 > 最新文献

Argumenta Philosophica最新文献

英文 中文
Il linguaggio come collante tra menti individuali e socialità umana 语言是人与人之间的纽带
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-07-27 DOI: 10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0
Filippo Batisti
The pragmatist tradition in philosophy has left a sound legacy in many contemporary research fields. John Dewey’s continuist and emergentist approach to the nature-or-nurture problem in relation to the individual human mind has been regained lately in evolutionist psychology and related disciplines. For Dewey, language plays a fundamental role in creating and maintaining this continuity between the individual mind and the social and physical environment humans inhabit. The present article will focus on a few contemporary lines of research that identify language as the ‘glue’ that bonds each individual to one another and to society, with a decisive impact on the development of one’s own mind.
哲学中的实用主义传统在许多当代研究领域留下了良好的遗产。约翰·杜威的持续主义和涌现主义的方法来解决与人类个体心灵有关的先天或后天问题,最近在进化心理学和相关学科中重新得到了应用。对于杜威来说,语言在创造和保持个人思想与人类所居住的社会和物质环境之间的连续性方面起着基本作用。本文将集中讨论一些当代的研究,这些研究认为语言是将每个人与他人和社会联系在一起的“粘合剂”,对一个人的思想发展有着决定性的影响。
{"title":"Il linguaggio come collante tra menti individuali e socialità umana","authors":"Filippo Batisti","doi":"10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0","url":null,"abstract":"The pragmatist tradition in philosophy has left a sound legacy in many contemporary research fields. John Dewey’s continuist and emergentist approach to the nature-or-nurture problem in relation to the individual human mind has been regained lately in evolutionist psychology and related disciplines. For Dewey, language plays a fundamental role in creating and maintaining this continuity between the individual mind and the social and physical environment humans inhabit. The present article will focus on a few contemporary lines of research that identify language as the ‘glue’ that bonds each individual to one another and to society, with a decisive impact on the development of one’s own mind.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":"28 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-07-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"84301125","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Fear as a Destructive Pain 恐惧是一种破坏性的痛苦
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-07-27 DOI: 10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/003
Gaia Bagnati
In the discussion on bravery in Eth. Eud., III, 1 Aristotle determines the objects that are absolutely dreadful by means of an explicit reference to ‘human nature’. This reference has not received much consideration from scholars in the field. The present paper argues that the reference under discussion entails a notion of ‘human nature’ that corresponds to a human being’s psychological disposition to endure fearful emotions – that is to say, painful emotions that imply the representation of a pain capable of destroying a human being – up to a certain degree of intensity. Furthermore, this article claims that the same notion of ‘human nature’ is implied in Eth. Eud., II, 8 in the discussion of involuntariness concerning the cases of mixed actions where Aristotle refers to the ‘nature’ of the agent as a criterion to determine the involuntariness of an action.
在对勇敢的讨论中。Eud。亚里士多德通过明确提及“人性”来确定绝对可怕的对象。这一参考文献没有得到该领域学者的充分考虑。本文认为,所讨论的参考需要一个“人性”的概念,这个概念对应于一个人的心理倾向,即忍受可怕的情绪,也就是说,痛苦的情绪暗示着一种能够摧毁一个人的痛苦的表征,直到一定程度的强度。此外,这篇文章声称,同样的“人性”概念也隐含在以太坊中。Eud。在讨论关于混合行为的非自愿性时,亚里士多德将行为主体的“性质”作为决定行为非自愿性的标准。
{"title":"Fear as a Destructive Pain","authors":"Gaia Bagnati","doi":"10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/003","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/003","url":null,"abstract":"In the discussion on bravery in Eth. Eud., III, 1 Aristotle determines the objects that are absolutely dreadful by means of an explicit reference to ‘human nature’. This reference has not received much consideration from scholars in the field. The present paper argues that the reference under discussion entails a notion of ‘human nature’ that corresponds to a human being’s psychological disposition to endure fearful emotions – that is to say, painful emotions that imply the representation of a pain capable of destroying a human being – up to a certain degree of intensity. Furthermore, this article claims that the same notion of ‘human nature’ is implied in Eth. Eud., II, 8 in the discussion of involuntariness concerning the cases of mixed actions where Aristotle refers to the ‘nature’ of the agent as a criterion to determine the involuntariness of an action.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":"5 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-07-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"84769502","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Descartes aux limites du naturalisme 笛卡尔在自然主义的极限
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-07-27 DOI: 10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/007
Denis Kambouchner
In order to appreciate the distance between the Cartesian theory of man and a naturalistic programme, it is necessary to ask what exactly Descartes means by “the soul’s power to move the body”. A precise examination of the Cartesian texts, especially the Treatise on Man and The Passions of the Soul, will lead to the exclusion of any direct action of the soul on the body. All the action of the soul goes through the formation of certain images in the brain, which determine certain flows of animal spirits, and as for the passions, the effectiveness of this action is mainly a matter of habit. The spontaneity of thought does not preclude considering the ‘force of the soul’ as associated with the ‘disposition of the brain’. Conversely, nothing in the Cartesian texts allows us to eliminate this spontaneity where we experience it.
为了理解笛卡尔关于人的理论与自然主义纲领之间的差距,有必要问一下笛卡尔所说的“灵魂推动身体的力量”究竟是什么意思。对笛卡尔文本,尤其是《人论》和《灵魂的激情》的精确研究,将导致灵魂对身体的任何直接作用被排除在外。灵魂的一切活动都是通过在头脑中形成某些意象而进行的,这些意象决定了动物精神的某些流动,至于激情,这种活动的有效性主要是一种习惯。思想的自发性并不排除将“灵魂的力量”与“大脑的倾向”联系起来的可能性。相反,笛卡尔文本中没有任何东西允许我们消除我们所经历的这种自发性。
{"title":"Descartes aux limites du naturalisme","authors":"Denis Kambouchner","doi":"10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/007","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/007","url":null,"abstract":"In order to appreciate the distance between the Cartesian theory of man and a naturalistic programme, it is necessary to ask what exactly Descartes means by “the soul’s power to move the body”. A precise examination of the Cartesian texts, especially the Treatise on Man and The Passions of the Soul, will lead to the exclusion of any direct action of the soul on the body. All the action of the soul goes through the formation of certain images in the brain, which determine certain flows of animal spirits, and as for the passions, the effectiveness of this action is mainly a matter of habit. The spontaneity of thought does not preclude considering the ‘force of the soul’ as associated with the ‘disposition of the brain’. Conversely, nothing in the Cartesian texts allows us to eliminate this spontaneity where we experience it.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":"42 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-07-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"90928927","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Il naturalismo oggi 今天的自然主义
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-07-27 DOI: 10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/001
L. Perissinotto
This paper tries to draw a map of the various versions of naturalism to which the current philosophical debate aims – from the most radical, or ‘hard’ ones, to the mildest, or liberal ones – and of the different projects of naturalization that are associated to them. In particular, in the first paragraphs, the present article will consider Timothy Williamson’s and Penelope Maddy’s attempts to inherit the demands of naturalism without declaring to be a naturalist (Williamson), or without making naturalism an empty slogan or a kind of masked first philosophy (Maddy). In the second part, the connections between epistemological naturalism and ontological or metaphysical naturalism will be analysed. The questions will be: (1) is it possible to be naturalist with regard to epistemology without being naturalist with regard to ontology?; (2) is it possible to be ontologically naturalist without being epistemologically naturalist?
本文试图画出当前哲学辩论所针对的各种版本的自然主义的地图——从最激进的,或“强硬的”,到最温和的,或自由的——以及与之相关的不同的归化计划。特别是,在文章的第一段,本文将考虑蒂莫西·威廉姆森和佩内洛普·曼迪试图继承自然主义的要求,而不宣称自己是自然主义者(威廉姆森),或者不使自然主义成为一个空洞的口号或一种蒙面的第一哲学(曼迪)。第二部分将分析认识论自然主义与本体论或形而上学自然主义之间的联系。问题将是:(1)在认识论上成为自然主义者而在本体论上不成为自然主义者是否可能?(2)有可能既成为本体论的自然主义者,又不成为认识论的自然主义者吗?
{"title":"Il naturalismo oggi","authors":"L. Perissinotto","doi":"10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/001","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/001","url":null,"abstract":"This paper tries to draw a map of the various versions of naturalism to which the current philosophical debate aims – from the most radical, or ‘hard’ ones, to the mildest, or liberal ones – and of the different projects of naturalization that are associated to them. In particular, in the first paragraphs, the present article will consider Timothy Williamson’s and Penelope Maddy’s attempts to inherit the demands of naturalism without declaring to be a naturalist (Williamson), or without making naturalism an empty slogan or a kind of masked first philosophy (Maddy). In the second part, the connections between epistemological naturalism and ontological or metaphysical naturalism will be analysed. The questions will be: (1) is it possible to be naturalist with regard to epistemology without being naturalist with regard to ontology?; (2) is it possible to be ontologically naturalist without being epistemologically naturalist?","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":"9 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-07-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"75863444","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Nel tempo e nello spazio. Linguaggio e natura nella filosofia di Ludwig Wittgenstein 在时间和空间上。路德维希·维特根斯坦哲学中的语言与自然
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-07-27 DOI: 10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/010
Alice Morelli
The paper focuses on some naturalistic aspects of Wittgenstein’s later philosophy. Wittgenstein has often been considered a radical anti-naturalist philosopher, mainly because he does not endorse the thesis of the continuity between philosophy and science. However, it will be argued that Wittgenstein’s later philosophy incorporates a kind of naturalism without naturalization, i.e., a liberal naturalism, in virtue of the relation between human nature and language. It will be concluded that Wittgenstein’s liberal naturalism provides an example of a naturalistic perspective on language which avoids the limits of an intellectualist approach without leading to scientism: this is meant to express the irreducibility of naturalism to the mere scientific version.
本文主要探讨维特根斯坦后期哲学的一些自然主义方面。维特根斯坦经常被认为是一个激进的反自然主义哲学家,主要是因为他不赞同哲学与科学之间连续性的论点。然而,我们认为维特根斯坦的后期哲学通过人性与语言的关系,融入了一种没有自然化的自然主义,即自由的自然主义。我们将得出结论,维特根斯坦的自由自然主义提供了一个语言的自然主义视角的例子,它避免了知识主义方法的局限性,而不会导致科学主义:这意味着将自然主义的不可约性表达为纯粹的科学版本。
{"title":"Nel tempo e nello spazio. Linguaggio e natura nella filosofia di Ludwig Wittgenstein","authors":"Alice Morelli","doi":"10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/010","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/010","url":null,"abstract":"The paper focuses on some naturalistic aspects of Wittgenstein’s later philosophy. Wittgenstein has often been considered a radical anti-naturalist philosopher, mainly because he does not endorse the thesis of the continuity between philosophy and science. However, it will be argued that Wittgenstein’s later philosophy incorporates a kind of naturalism without naturalization, i.e., a liberal naturalism, in virtue of the relation between human nature and language. It will be concluded that Wittgenstein’s liberal naturalism provides an example of a naturalistic perspective on language which avoids the limits of an intellectualist approach without leading to scientism: this is meant to express the irreducibility of naturalism to the mere scientific version.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":"21 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-07-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"85282927","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Onnipotenza divina e ordine naturale nel Medioevo 中世纪神圣的全能和自然秩序
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-07-27 DOI: 10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/006
Andrea Possamai
The present essay aims, on the one hand, to recall the reasons of anti-naturalism, intended in a metaphysical perspective, of a large part of medieval philosophical and theological reflection and, on the other hand, to show how the same type of problems, specifically those concerning the possible mutability or immutability of the past, can be employed in favour of various conflicting positions on the matter. To demonstrate this, reference was made to some thinkers who could represent emblematic positions on the theme, in particular: Pliny the Elder for the ancient world, Augustine of Hippo, Peter Damian, Bonaventure and Thomas Aquinas for the medieval era.
本论文的目的,一方面,回顾反自然主义的原因,意在从形而上学的角度,中世纪哲学和神学反思的很大一部分,另一方面,展示如何相同类型的问题,特别是那些关于过去可能的可变性或不可变性的问题,可以被用来支持在这个问题上的各种冲突立场。为了证明这一点,参考了一些可以代表这一主题的象征性立场的思想家,特别是:古代世界的老普林尼,河马的奥古斯丁,彼得达米安,博纳文蒂尔和中世纪的托马斯阿奎那。
{"title":"Onnipotenza divina e ordine naturale nel Medioevo","authors":"Andrea Possamai","doi":"10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/006","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/006","url":null,"abstract":"The present essay aims, on the one hand, to recall the reasons of anti-naturalism, intended in a metaphysical perspective, of a large part of medieval philosophical and theological reflection and, on the other hand, to show how the same type of problems, specifically those concerning the possible mutability or immutability of the past, can be employed in favour of various conflicting positions on the matter. To demonstrate this, reference was made to some thinkers who could represent emblematic positions on the theme, in particular: Pliny the Elder for the ancient world, Augustine of Hippo, Peter Damian, Bonaventure and Thomas Aquinas for the medieval era.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":"11 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-07-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"75866075","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Naturalisme et scepticisme
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-07-27 DOI: 10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/009
Iris Douzant
Hume is qualified as a naturalist in two respects: on the one hand, because he sets himself to observe natural phenomena and more precisely those relating to human nature; on the other hand, because nature refers to a mental activity that eludes the grasp of the thought that tries to seize it. Hume’s dealing with the issue of personal identity creates a tension between these two meanings of naturalism – the power of nature seems to escape the understanding of the philosopher who tries to give reasons for it and both sides of Humian naturalism dissociate themselves. If this tension is not positively resolved, in the opinion of Hume himself, it is reduced through the use of a radical scepticism.
休谟在两个方面有资格成为博物学家:一方面,因为他致力于观察自然现象,更确切地说,是那些与人性有关的现象;另一方面,因为自然指的是一种精神活动,它逃避了试图抓住它的思想的把握。休谟对个人同一性问题的处理在自然主义的这两种意义之间制造了一种张力自然主义的力量似乎逃避了试图给出原因的哲学家的理解,人类自然主义的两方面都分离了自己。休谟本人认为,如果这种紧张关系没有得到积极的解决,那么通过使用激进的怀疑主义,这种紧张关系就会减少。
{"title":"Naturalisme et scepticisme","authors":"Iris Douzant","doi":"10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/009","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/009","url":null,"abstract":"Hume is qualified as a naturalist in two respects: on the one hand, because he sets himself to observe natural phenomena and more precisely those relating to human nature; on the other hand, because nature refers to a mental activity that eludes the grasp of the thought that tries to seize it. Hume’s dealing with the issue of personal identity creates a tension between these two meanings of naturalism – the power of nature seems to escape the understanding of the philosopher who tries to give reasons for it and both sides of Humian naturalism dissociate themselves. If this tension is not positively resolved, in the opinion of Hume himself, it is reduced through the use of a radical scepticism.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":"105 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-07-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"72751166","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Naturalismo e cosmopolitismo nell’Antichità 古代的自然主义和世界主义
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-07-27 DOI: 10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/004
P. Morel
Cosmopolitanism in Antiquity is especially promoted by the cynics and by the stoics. The Epicurean Garden seems to adopt a very different view, according to which justice and laws depend on what is useful for a given political community at a given time. However, the epicurean Diogenes of Oinoanda (fr. 30 Smith) endorses a sort of cosmopolitanism, which contrasts, at first sight, with the traditional contractualism of his school. Nevertheless, in this paper it is argued that Diogenes’ cosmopolitanism could hardly be seen as a concession to other schools and that it is consistent with the main principles of Epicurus’ political doctrine.
古代的世界主义尤其受到犬儒主义者和斯多葛主义者的推崇。伊壁鸠鲁花园似乎采用了一种非常不同的观点,根据这种观点,正义和法律取决于在特定时间对特定政治团体有用的东西。然而,伊壁鸠鲁派第欧根尼的奥伊诺达(30年史密斯)赞同一种世界主义,这对比,乍一看,与他的学校的传统契约主义。然而,本文认为第欧根尼的世界主义很难被看作是对其他学派的让步,它与伊壁鸠鲁政治学说的主要原则是一致的。
{"title":"Naturalismo e cosmopolitismo nell’Antichità","authors":"P. Morel","doi":"10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/004","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/004","url":null,"abstract":"Cosmopolitanism in Antiquity is especially promoted by the cynics and by the stoics. The Epicurean Garden seems to adopt a very different view, according to which justice and laws depend on what is useful for a given political community at a given time. However, the epicurean Diogenes of Oinoanda (fr. 30 Smith) endorses a sort of cosmopolitanism, which contrasts, at first sight, with the traditional contractualism of his school. Nevertheless, in this paper it is argued that Diogenes’ cosmopolitanism could hardly be seen as a concession to other schools and that it is consistent with the main principles of Epicurus’ political doctrine.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":"42 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-07-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"75115732","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
La natura e gli stati abituali nell’Etica Nicomachea 尼科马契亚伦理的自然和习惯状态
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-07-27 DOI: 10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/002
F. Farina
According to Aristotle, virtue does not arise in us neither by nature nor contrary to nature. ‘Virtue naturalism’, as the possibility to ‘reduce’ virtue and virtues of character to physical or physiological entities and relations, seems consequently impossible. Nature and virtue differ mostly in respect of their relation with contraries.A moral agent can become either virtuous or vicious, while a stone can only move downwards. However moral habits, once acquired by the agent, seem to come close to nature’s uni-directionality.
根据亚里士多德的观点,美德既不是自然产生的,也不是与自然相违背的。“美德自然主义”,作为将美德和品格的美德“还原”为物理或生理实体和关系的可能性,因此似乎是不可能的。本性和美德的区别主要在于它们与对立面的关系。一个有道德的人可以变得善良,也可以变得邪恶,而一块石头只能向下移动。然而,道德习惯,一旦被代理人获得,似乎接近于自然的单向性。
{"title":"La natura e gli stati abituali nell’Etica Nicomachea","authors":"F. Farina","doi":"10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/002","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/002","url":null,"abstract":"According to Aristotle, virtue does not arise in us neither by nature nor contrary to nature. ‘Virtue naturalism’, as the possibility to ‘reduce’ virtue and virtues of character to physical or physiological entities and relations, seems consequently impossible. Nature and virtue differ mostly in respect of their relation with contraries.\u0000A moral agent can become either virtuous or vicious, while a stone can only move downwards. However moral habits, once acquired by the agent, seem to come close to nature’s uni-directionality.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":"84 3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-07-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"83445852","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Il naturalismo culturale di Dewey 杜威的文化自然主义
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-07-27 DOI: 10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/011
Roberta Dreon
The essay focuses on John Dewey’s pragmatic naturalism in order to show that the relatively recent naturalizing trend in philosophy should be considered a historically and culturally situated restriction of other forms of naturalism. Dewey’s cultural naturalism is based on a strong continuity between nature and culture, assuming that human intelligent behaviour arises from already existing organic and environmental resources in an entirely contingent manner. This kind of naturalism does not involve physical reductionism: more complex interactions between organisms and their environment, such as human mental behaviour, are seen as innovative, in the sense that they produce forms of organization that, on the one hand, are not reducible to the simple association of pre-existing elements. On the other hand, innovative modes of interaction between human organisms and their naturally social environment have consequence on the natural world: they produce changes within it. The second part of the text presents Dewey’s non-substantive conception of the mind, which has its roots in the non-reversible consequences of the advent of highly communicative and linguistic interactions in the human world as well as in the possibility for human organism to reconsider analytically or reflectively their primarily holistic, qualitatively felt experiences.
本文以杜威的实用主义自然主义为研究对象,指出近代哲学中的自然主义思潮是对其他形式的自然主义的历史和文化限制。杜威的文化自然主义基于自然与文化之间的强烈连续性,假设人类的智能行为以完全偶然的方式产生于已经存在的有机和环境资源。这种自然主义不涉及物理还原论:生物体与其环境之间更复杂的相互作用,如人类的心理行为,被视为创新,因为它们产生的组织形式,一方面不能简化为预先存在的元素的简单关联。另一方面,人类有机体与其自然社会环境之间互动的创新模式对自然界产生了影响:它们在自然界内部产生了变化。本文的第二部分介绍了杜威关于心灵的非实质性概念,其根源在于人类世界中高度交流和语言互动的出现所带来的不可逆转的后果,以及人类有机体分析或反思其主要整体的、定性的感受经验的可能性。
{"title":"Il naturalismo culturale di Dewey","authors":"Roberta Dreon","doi":"10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/011","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.30687/978-88-6969-325-0/011","url":null,"abstract":"The essay focuses on John Dewey’s pragmatic naturalism in order to show that the relatively recent naturalizing trend in philosophy should be considered a historically and culturally situated restriction of other forms of naturalism. Dewey’s cultural naturalism is based on a strong continuity between nature and culture, assuming that human intelligent behaviour arises from already existing organic and environmental resources in an entirely contingent manner. This kind of naturalism does not involve physical reductionism: more complex interactions between organisms and their environment, such as human mental behaviour, are seen as innovative, in the sense that they produce forms of organization that, on the one hand, are not reducible to the simple association of pre-existing elements. On the other hand, innovative modes of interaction between human organisms and their naturally social environment have consequence on the natural world: they produce changes within it. The second part of the text presents Dewey’s non-substantive conception of the mind, which has its roots in the non-reversible consequences of the advent of highly communicative and linguistic interactions in the human world as well as in the possibility for human organism to reconsider analytically or reflectively their primarily holistic, qualitatively felt experiences.","PeriodicalId":36843,"journal":{"name":"Argumenta Philosophica","volume":"41 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-07-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"91247064","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Argumenta Philosophica
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1