精神疾病是柔软的自然类型

IF 2.6 0 PHILOSOPHY Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology Pub Date : 2022-09-01 DOI:10.1353/ppp.2022.0037
D. Stein
{"title":"精神疾病是柔软的自然类型","authors":"D. Stein","doi":"10.1353/ppp.2022.0037","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Tilmes concludes his interesting and informative piece with the sentence that “analysis of psychiatric vagueness merits further consideration.” I agree with this point, as well as with his earlier assertion that how one understands psychiatric vagueness may implicate the diagnostic model that one adopts, and the research that one pursues. Fortunately, there has been recent attention to vagueness in psychiatry, addressing both degree-vagueness (e.g., how much depression is required for a diagnosis of depression) and combinatorial vagueness (e.g., what sorts of symptoms are needed for this diagnosis) (Geert, Lara and Rico, 2017). Vagueness in psychiatry is related to a range of nosological debates, including about the value of categorical versus dimensional constructs. Notably, the editors of DSM-5 initially aimed to shift to a more dimensional approach, in keeping with the continuous nature of biological domains of function (Regier, Narrow, Kuhl, & Kupfer, 2009). Nevertheless, dimensional constructs can be reformulated as categories by using cut-points, symptoms of categories can be tallied up to form dimensions, and both categorical and dimensional measures are useful (Kessler, 2002). While many psychiatric traits are continuous, diagnostic categories have considerable clinical utility and were largely retained in the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM)-5 (First, 2005). Tilmes divides theories of vagueness into semantic, epistemic, and ontic ones, and defends the claim that if there is a such a thing as psychiatric vagueness then some cases of such vagueness are least in part semantic. That is, that at least some of this indeterminacy is due to our descriptions of the world, rather than due to the state of the world or what we know about it. While it is entirely reasonable to study the language of diagnosis, I would want to emphasize the complex and intertwined relationships between our concepts and the world, and to point out that many other considerations are at stake here other than the use of language by different communities. It is notable, for example, that the International Classification of Disease (ICD)-11 made the decision to use clinical guidelines that avoid the “pseudo-precision” of the DSM-5 (Reed et al., 2019). Thus, for example, whereas for generalized anxiety disorder DSM-5 specifies that symptoms have lasted for 6 months, ICD-11 refers instead, rather more vaguely, to “several months.” It is not, however, the case that this vagueness indicates means that ICD-11 takes an anti-realist position on mental disorders (Tilmes equates semantic","PeriodicalId":45397,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","volume":"1 1","pages":"183 - 185"},"PeriodicalIF":2.6000,"publicationDate":"2022-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"1","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Psychiatric Disorders Are Soft Natural Kinds\",\"authors\":\"D. Stein\",\"doi\":\"10.1353/ppp.2022.0037\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Tilmes concludes his interesting and informative piece with the sentence that “analysis of psychiatric vagueness merits further consideration.” I agree with this point, as well as with his earlier assertion that how one understands psychiatric vagueness may implicate the diagnostic model that one adopts, and the research that one pursues. Fortunately, there has been recent attention to vagueness in psychiatry, addressing both degree-vagueness (e.g., how much depression is required for a diagnosis of depression) and combinatorial vagueness (e.g., what sorts of symptoms are needed for this diagnosis) (Geert, Lara and Rico, 2017). Vagueness in psychiatry is related to a range of nosological debates, including about the value of categorical versus dimensional constructs. Notably, the editors of DSM-5 initially aimed to shift to a more dimensional approach, in keeping with the continuous nature of biological domains of function (Regier, Narrow, Kuhl, & Kupfer, 2009). Nevertheless, dimensional constructs can be reformulated as categories by using cut-points, symptoms of categories can be tallied up to form dimensions, and both categorical and dimensional measures are useful (Kessler, 2002). While many psychiatric traits are continuous, diagnostic categories have considerable clinical utility and were largely retained in the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM)-5 (First, 2005). Tilmes divides theories of vagueness into semantic, epistemic, and ontic ones, and defends the claim that if there is a such a thing as psychiatric vagueness then some cases of such vagueness are least in part semantic. That is, that at least some of this indeterminacy is due to our descriptions of the world, rather than due to the state of the world or what we know about it. While it is entirely reasonable to study the language of diagnosis, I would want to emphasize the complex and intertwined relationships between our concepts and the world, and to point out that many other considerations are at stake here other than the use of language by different communities. It is notable, for example, that the International Classification of Disease (ICD)-11 made the decision to use clinical guidelines that avoid the “pseudo-precision” of the DSM-5 (Reed et al., 2019). Thus, for example, whereas for generalized anxiety disorder DSM-5 specifies that symptoms have lasted for 6 months, ICD-11 refers instead, rather more vaguely, to “several months.” It is not, however, the case that this vagueness indicates means that ICD-11 takes an anti-realist position on mental disorders (Tilmes equates semantic\",\"PeriodicalId\":45397,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology\",\"volume\":\"1 1\",\"pages\":\"183 - 185\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":2.6000,\"publicationDate\":\"2022-09-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"1\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2022.0037\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"0\",\"JCRName\":\"PHILOSOPHY\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2022.0037","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1

摘要

蒂尔梅斯以“精神病学模糊性的分析值得进一步考虑”这句话结束了这篇有趣且内容丰富的文章。我同意这一点,也同意他之前的断言,即一个人如何理解精神病学的模糊性可能会影响到他所采用的诊断模式,以及他所从事的研究。幸运的是,最近人们开始关注精神病学中的模糊性,解决了程度模糊性(例如,诊断抑郁症需要多少抑郁)和组合模糊性(例如,这种诊断需要哪些症状)(Geert, Lara和Rico, 2017)。精神病学中的模糊性与一系列的病分学争论有关,包括关于分类构念与维度构念的价值。值得注意的是,DSM-5的编辑最初旨在转向更多维的方法,以保持生物功能域的连续性(Regier, Narrow, Kuhl, & Kupfer, 2009)。然而,维度结构可以通过使用切点重新表述为类别,类别的症状可以汇总形成维度,类别和维度测量都是有用的(Kessler, 2002)。虽然许多精神病学特征是连续的,但诊断类别具有相当大的临床实用性,并且在精神疾病诊断和统计手册(DSM)-5(2005年第一版)中保留了很大一部分。蒂尔姆斯将模糊理论分为语义学、认识论和本体论,并为这样一种观点辩护:如果存在精神病学上的模糊,那么某些情况下这种模糊至少部分是语义学上的。也就是说,这种不确定性至少有一部分是由于我们对世界的描述,而不是由于世界的状态或我们对它的了解。虽然研究诊断语言是完全合理的,但我想强调我们的概念和世界之间复杂而交织的关系,并指出除了不同群体对语言的使用之外,还有许多其他考虑因素在这里受到威胁。例如,值得注意的是,国际疾病分类(ICD)-11决定使用临床指南,以避免DSM-5的“伪精度”(Reed等人,2019)。因此,例如,对于广泛性焦虑症,DSM-5规定症状持续了6个月,而ICD-11则更模糊地提到“几个月”。然而,这种模糊性并不意味着ICD-11对精神障碍采取了反现实主义的立场(Tilmes将其等同于语义)
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Psychiatric Disorders Are Soft Natural Kinds
Tilmes concludes his interesting and informative piece with the sentence that “analysis of psychiatric vagueness merits further consideration.” I agree with this point, as well as with his earlier assertion that how one understands psychiatric vagueness may implicate the diagnostic model that one adopts, and the research that one pursues. Fortunately, there has been recent attention to vagueness in psychiatry, addressing both degree-vagueness (e.g., how much depression is required for a diagnosis of depression) and combinatorial vagueness (e.g., what sorts of symptoms are needed for this diagnosis) (Geert, Lara and Rico, 2017). Vagueness in psychiatry is related to a range of nosological debates, including about the value of categorical versus dimensional constructs. Notably, the editors of DSM-5 initially aimed to shift to a more dimensional approach, in keeping with the continuous nature of biological domains of function (Regier, Narrow, Kuhl, & Kupfer, 2009). Nevertheless, dimensional constructs can be reformulated as categories by using cut-points, symptoms of categories can be tallied up to form dimensions, and both categorical and dimensional measures are useful (Kessler, 2002). While many psychiatric traits are continuous, diagnostic categories have considerable clinical utility and were largely retained in the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM)-5 (First, 2005). Tilmes divides theories of vagueness into semantic, epistemic, and ontic ones, and defends the claim that if there is a such a thing as psychiatric vagueness then some cases of such vagueness are least in part semantic. That is, that at least some of this indeterminacy is due to our descriptions of the world, rather than due to the state of the world or what we know about it. While it is entirely reasonable to study the language of diagnosis, I would want to emphasize the complex and intertwined relationships between our concepts and the world, and to point out that many other considerations are at stake here other than the use of language by different communities. It is notable, for example, that the International Classification of Disease (ICD)-11 made the decision to use clinical guidelines that avoid the “pseudo-precision” of the DSM-5 (Reed et al., 2019). Thus, for example, whereas for generalized anxiety disorder DSM-5 specifies that symptoms have lasted for 6 months, ICD-11 refers instead, rather more vaguely, to “several months.” It is not, however, the case that this vagueness indicates means that ICD-11 takes an anti-realist position on mental disorders (Tilmes equates semantic
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
3.60
自引率
4.30%
发文量
40
期刊最新文献
The Limits of Self-Constitution How to Measure Depression: Looking Back on the Making of Psychiatric Assessment Psychodramatic Psychotherapy for Schizophrenic Individuals About the Authors Close Enemies: The Relationship of Psychiatry and Psychology in the Assessment of Mental Disorders
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1