首页 > 最新文献

Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology最新文献

英文 中文
Philosophers, Carers, and Psychodramatic Games 哲学家、照顾者和心理戏剧游戏
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-01 DOI: 10.1353/ppp.2023.a908274
Corinne Gal, Alexandre Chapy, Marielle Fau, Muriel Guaveia
Philosophers, Carers, and Psychodramatic Games Corinne Gal (bio), Alexandre Chapy (bio), Marielle Fau (bio), and Muriel Guaveia (bio) Dear Jonathan D. Moreno, Thank you for the honor of taking the time to comment on the work we do. It is very meaningful for us to be able to talk with you. We, too, see a big difference between philosophers and carers (in the broadest sense) who deal with the suffering of patients and try to find methods to help them. But, if theory is at the service of the clinic, it becomes a formidable asset to refine our therapeutic methods and better understand what is happening to our patients. Indeed, patients suffering from psychosis, severe neurosis … are difficult to accompany and “recalcitrant to therapy by word alone” to use your terms. It is on this point that Ludwig Binswanger distanced himself from psychoanalysis. Binswanger ran a sanatorium in Switzerland (the Bellevue Clinic) and took in patients suffering from this type of psychological pathology. Aware that “the divan” and the analysis of the transference (unconscious) made little progress, he sought other ways of understanding his patients. The work of Edmund Husserl, the founder of the phenomenological movement, and then the work of Martin Heidegger1 fascinated him because they attempted to answer fundamental questions about being. The patients we work with ask themselves and us the same question: What is being? How can we feel existence within ourselves? Binswanger then created daseinsanalysis as an analysis of existence in which he was able to develop, among other dimensions, what he called “artists’ gestures,” including the possibility of (physical) contact with the patients. The body regained existential importance in the therapy. There are also strong similarities between psychiatric phenomenology and the work of Jacob Levy Moreno (2014, p. 214). We would like to quote your work: “ Nonetheless, there were links between them. Heidegger and J.L. shared preoccupation with personal authenticity and meaning [End Page 230] just enough to be considered part of the trends that led to postwar existentialism and fueled the new humanistic psychology, NTL, and encounter groups.” Jacob Levy Moreno’s working methods are much more powerful, allowing us to work as closely as possible with bodily feelings, since the body involved in the action is so present in psychodrama. Because, to this question of being posed by our patients, is linked the body as a felt, sensing body: the body that I am (which differs from the object body). Schizophrenic patients often express, and this is a terrible suffering, that they no longer feel anything, that they no longer feel they exist, that they no longer feel emotions or feelings. They do not know how to be in the world and with others. For us it is a fundamental symptom, as much as hallucinations. We link it to the loss of natural evidence (Blankenburg, 1991), the loss of contact with reality (Minkowski, 1929). Most of the time, in psyc
Corinne Gal(个人简介),Alexandre Chapy(个人简介),Marielle Fau(个人简介)和Muriel Guaveia(个人简介)亲爱的Jonathan D. Moreno,感谢您抽出时间评论我们所做的工作。能和你谈话对我们来说很有意义。我们也看到了哲学家和护理人员(广义上)之间的巨大差异,后者处理病人的痛苦,并试图找到帮助他们的方法。但是,如果理论是为临床服务的,它就会成为完善我们的治疗方法和更好地了解我们病人身上发生的事情的强大资产。的确,患有精神病和严重神经症的病人很难陪伴,用你的话来说,他们“不愿单靠言语治疗”。正是在这一点上,路德维希·宾斯旺格与精神分析拉开了距离。宾斯旺格在瑞士开了一家疗养院(贝尔维尤诊所),收留患有这种心理疾病的病人。意识到“沙发”和移情(无意识)分析几乎没有进展,他寻求其他方法来理解他的病人。现象学运动的创始人埃德蒙·胡塞尔和马丁·海德格尔的作品都使他着迷,因为他们试图回答关于存在的基本问题。我们治疗的病人会问他们自己和我们同样的问题:什么是存在?我们怎样才能感受到自身的存在?宾斯旺格随后创造了daseinsanalysis,作为一种对存在的分析,在这种分析中,他能够在其他维度中发展他所谓的“艺术家的姿态”,包括与病人(身体)接触的可能性。身体在治疗中重新获得了存在的重要性。精神病学现象学与Jacob Levy Moreno (2014, p. 214)的作品也有很强的相似之处。我们想引用你的作品:“尽管如此,他们之间还是有联系的。海德格尔和J.L.对个人真实性和意义的共同关注,足以被认为是导致战后存在主义的趋势的一部分,并推动了新的人文主义心理学、NTL和相遇团体。”雅各布·利维·莫雷诺(Jacob Levy Moreno)的工作方法更加强大,允许我们尽可能地与身体感觉密切合作,因为参与动作的身体在心理剧中是如此的存在。因为,我们的病人提出的这个问题,是把身体作为一个感觉的,感知的身体联系起来的:我的身体(它不同于客体身体)。精神分裂症患者经常表达,这是一种可怕的痛苦,他们不再有任何感觉,他们不再觉得自己存在,他们不再有情绪或感觉。他们不知道如何生活在这个世界上,如何与他人相处。对我们来说,这是一种基本症状,就像幻觉一样。我们将其与自然证据的丧失(Blankenburg, 1991)、与现实的接触的丧失(Minkowski, 1929)联系起来。大多数时候,在心理剧中,我们“外化”患者在玩家扮演的不同角色中的感受,这使我们能够在每个人的互动中遇到困难的核心。安妮·安塞琳·施岑伯格(Anne Ancelin schzenberger)对我们进行了心理剧的训练,我们有一套技巧来支持心理剧的表达,这是一种“工具箱”。根据情境,病人的时刻,我们自己的状态,我们打开我们的工具箱,尝试选择和使用最适合游戏需求的技术,以及我们对主角或团队难度的理解。我们不做任何系统的事情,我们是工匠。我们选择呈现一个非常简单的游戏,没有使用任何技术,除了最初的独白,一个稳定的病人患有无症状的精神分裂症。这是为了证明相遇的可能性,构成了存在,是心理剧的一个基本维度。我们感谢你为我们提供的例子,它们将成为灵感的源泉,并将充实我们的工具箱。致约翰·诺尔特:我们非常感谢您的评论,这使我们感到荣幸。这篇文章的目的是展示在……
{"title":"Philosophers, Carers, and Psychodramatic Games","authors":"Corinne Gal, Alexandre Chapy, Marielle Fau, Muriel Guaveia","doi":"10.1353/ppp.2023.a908274","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2023.a908274","url":null,"abstract":"Philosophers, Carers, and Psychodramatic Games Corinne Gal (bio), Alexandre Chapy (bio), Marielle Fau (bio), and Muriel Guaveia (bio) Dear Jonathan D. Moreno, Thank you for the honor of taking the time to comment on the work we do. It is very meaningful for us to be able to talk with you. We, too, see a big difference between philosophers and carers (in the broadest sense) who deal with the suffering of patients and try to find methods to help them. But, if theory is at the service of the clinic, it becomes a formidable asset to refine our therapeutic methods and better understand what is happening to our patients. Indeed, patients suffering from psychosis, severe neurosis … are difficult to accompany and “recalcitrant to therapy by word alone” to use your terms. It is on this point that Ludwig Binswanger distanced himself from psychoanalysis. Binswanger ran a sanatorium in Switzerland (the Bellevue Clinic) and took in patients suffering from this type of psychological pathology. Aware that “the divan” and the analysis of the transference (unconscious) made little progress, he sought other ways of understanding his patients. The work of Edmund Husserl, the founder of the phenomenological movement, and then the work of Martin Heidegger1 fascinated him because they attempted to answer fundamental questions about being. The patients we work with ask themselves and us the same question: What is being? How can we feel existence within ourselves? Binswanger then created daseinsanalysis as an analysis of existence in which he was able to develop, among other dimensions, what he called “artists’ gestures,” including the possibility of (physical) contact with the patients. The body regained existential importance in the therapy. There are also strong similarities between psychiatric phenomenology and the work of Jacob Levy Moreno (2014, p. 214). We would like to quote your work: “ Nonetheless, there were links between them. Heidegger and J.L. shared preoccupation with personal authenticity and meaning [End Page 230] just enough to be considered part of the trends that led to postwar existentialism and fueled the new humanistic psychology, NTL, and encounter groups.” Jacob Levy Moreno’s working methods are much more powerful, allowing us to work as closely as possible with bodily feelings, since the body involved in the action is so present in psychodrama. Because, to this question of being posed by our patients, is linked the body as a felt, sensing body: the body that I am (which differs from the object body). Schizophrenic patients often express, and this is a terrible suffering, that they no longer feel anything, that they no longer feel they exist, that they no longer feel emotions or feelings. They do not know how to be in the world and with others. For us it is a fundamental symptom, as much as hallucinations. We link it to the loss of natural evidence (Blankenburg, 1991), the loss of contact with reality (Minkowski, 1929). Most of the time, in psyc","PeriodicalId":45397,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","volume":"41 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135588281","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Understanding First: Exploring Its Scope and Testing Its Limits 理解第一:探索其范围并测试其极限
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-01 DOI: 10.1353/ppp.2023.a908268
Marga Reimer
Understanding First: Exploring Its Scope and Testing Its Limits Marga Reimer, PhD (bio) I thoroughly enjoyed reading and reflecting on this provocative, engagingly written, and persuasively argued paper. My commentary focuses on the authors’ “understanding first” principle. I begin by exploring that principle’s scope by appeal to aesthetic analogues to the moral cases of Pete and Jacob; I then explore its limits by appeal to cases involving agents struggling with maladaptive traits that are more self-destructive than antisocial. According to the authors, when attempting to eliminate or reduce a maladaptive trait, it is important that the agent begin with a non-moralizing understanding of that trait’s “root cause.” In this way, the agent avoids some of the epistemically distorting and otherwise counterproductive effects associated with an approach that begins with a moralizing assessment of the problematic trait. They can then proceed with a reason-based “dispensation” of that trait. The cases of Pete and Jacob make these points vivid and lend them considerable credence. Moreover, the authors’ “understanding first principle” arguably exemplifies a more general, and no less plausible, principle concerning the remediation of virtually any problem. Who would deny that an objective, non-normative, understanding of a problem’s “root cause” might be useful in addressing that problem? Who would deny that normativizing a problem before understanding its origin might prevent a deeper understanding of that problem and therewith its maximally effective “treatment”? One way to showcase the intuitiveness of the authors’ “understanding first” principle would be to explore the applicability of an analogous principle to problems beyond those involving “moral matters.” Problems involving aesthetics might prove particularly illuminating in this regard insofar as aesthetics, like morality, is inherently normative and yet it lies beyond the scope of morality proper. If an “understanding first” principle can be shown to be applicable to certain types of aesthetic problems, then the authors’ already strong case for the applicability of such a principle to certain types of moral problems would be further strengthened. In the cases of Pete and Jacob, the problems are unambiguously moral: the patently antisocial behaviors of these two individuals are paradigmatically “bad” and their premature assessment as [End Page 205] such can be epistemically distorting and otherwise counterproductive. Consider now analogous cases involving aesthetic problems. Pete and Lucie are getting ready for the holidays and are expecting family from out of town. But there are a couple of problems. Pete notices an “ugly” stain on the living room carpet and Lucie notices a subtle but decidedly “nasty” odor permeating the entire house. Neither Pete nor Lucie know where the stain came from, nor where the odor is coming from. But both the stain and the odor are “pretty gross” and so they need to “get
首先理解:探索它的范围和测试它的极限Marga Reimer博士(生物)我非常喜欢阅读和思考这篇具有挑衅性的、引人入胜的、有说服力的论文。我的评论集中在作者的“理解第一”原则上。我首先通过皮特和雅各布的道德案例的美学类比来探索这一原则的范围;然后,我通过一些案例来探讨它的局限性,这些案例涉及的是与自我毁灭而非反社会的适应不良特征作斗争的代理人。根据作者的说法,当试图消除或减少一种适应不良的特征时,重要的是,代理人首先要对该特征的“根本原因”有一个非道德化的理解。通过这种方式,行为人避免了一些认知扭曲和其他适得其反的影响,这些影响与对有问题的特征进行道德评估的方法有关。然后,他们可以对这种特质进行基于理性的“分配”。皮特和雅各布的案例使这些观点生动,并使他们相当可信。此外,作者的“理解第一原则”可以说是一个更普遍的、同样合理的原则,它涉及到几乎任何问题的补救。谁会否认客观、非规范地理解问题的“根本原因”可能有助于解决问题呢?谁会否认,在理解问题的根源之前将问题正常化,可能会阻碍对问题的更深入理解,从而阻碍对问题进行最有效的“治疗”?要展示作者“理解第一”原则的直观性,一种方法是探索一个类似原则在涉及“道德问题”以外的问题上的适用性。涉及美学的问题可能在这方面特别具有启发性,因为美学,就像道德一样,本质上是规范的,但它超出了道德本身的范围。如果“理解第一”的原则可以被证明适用于某些类型的美学问题,那么作者已经强有力地证明了这种原则适用于某些类型的道德问题,这将进一步得到加强。在皮特和雅各布的案例中,问题无疑是道德的:这两个人明显的反社会行为是典型的“坏”,他们过早的评估可能会在认知上扭曲,否则会适得其反。现在考虑涉及美学问题的类似案例。皮特和露西正在为假期做准备,他们正在等外地来的家人。但是有几个问题。皮特注意到客厅地毯上有一个“丑陋”的污点,露西注意到一种微妙但明显“讨厌”的气味弥漫了整个房子。皮特和露西都不知道污渍是从哪里来的,也不知道气味是从哪里来的。但污渍和气味都“非常恶心”,所以他们需要在家人到来之前“除掉”它们。没有时间去调查“根本原因”。皮特擦洗污渍,直到污渍下面的那部分地毯已经磨破了;露西买了三种不同的除臭剂,都能消除气味,但只是暂时的。如果皮特和露西明白了“丑陋”污渍和“难闻”气味的根本原因,他们的治疗方法可能会有所不同,而且更重要的是,会更有效。这种污渍原来是由红酒引起的,很容易治疗,不会留下明显的“秃斑”。这种挥之不去的气味来自一个很容易解决的管道问题,尽管这个问题需要更广泛(也更昂贵)的工作。皮特和露西的审美评价(“丑陋”、“讨厌”),加上对“根本原因”缺乏理解,结果可想而知:他们对一些“相当恶心”的问题的控制能力大大降低了。同样地,对于适应不良的特征(“坏的”、“错误的”)的道德评价,加上对“根本原因”的缺乏理解。正如作者所表明的那样,这样的评估可能会在认知上扭曲,否则会适得其反,结果是代理对有问题特征的控制大大降低。进一步的美学类比很容易发展,甚至可能更具启发性。想象一下,皮特和露西本周晚些时候就要生孩子了,他们出现了呼吸系统和胃肠道的症状,“有点恶心”。就像皮特和雅各布的不适应特征一样,在这种情况下,有问题的特征实际上是“在”代理人(相对于……)
{"title":"Understanding First: Exploring Its Scope and Testing Its Limits","authors":"Marga Reimer","doi":"10.1353/ppp.2023.a908268","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2023.a908268","url":null,"abstract":"Understanding First: Exploring Its Scope and Testing Its Limits Marga Reimer, PhD (bio) I thoroughly enjoyed reading and reflecting on this provocative, engagingly written, and persuasively argued paper. My commentary focuses on the authors’ “understanding first” principle. I begin by exploring that principle’s scope by appeal to aesthetic analogues to the moral cases of Pete and Jacob; I then explore its limits by appeal to cases involving agents struggling with maladaptive traits that are more self-destructive than antisocial. According to the authors, when attempting to eliminate or reduce a maladaptive trait, it is important that the agent begin with a non-moralizing understanding of that trait’s “root cause.” In this way, the agent avoids some of the epistemically distorting and otherwise counterproductive effects associated with an approach that begins with a moralizing assessment of the problematic trait. They can then proceed with a reason-based “dispensation” of that trait. The cases of Pete and Jacob make these points vivid and lend them considerable credence. Moreover, the authors’ “understanding first principle” arguably exemplifies a more general, and no less plausible, principle concerning the remediation of virtually any problem. Who would deny that an objective, non-normative, understanding of a problem’s “root cause” might be useful in addressing that problem? Who would deny that normativizing a problem before understanding its origin might prevent a deeper understanding of that problem and therewith its maximally effective “treatment”? One way to showcase the intuitiveness of the authors’ “understanding first” principle would be to explore the applicability of an analogous principle to problems beyond those involving “moral matters.” Problems involving aesthetics might prove particularly illuminating in this regard insofar as aesthetics, like morality, is inherently normative and yet it lies beyond the scope of morality proper. If an “understanding first” principle can be shown to be applicable to certain types of aesthetic problems, then the authors’ already strong case for the applicability of such a principle to certain types of moral problems would be further strengthened. In the cases of Pete and Jacob, the problems are unambiguously moral: the patently antisocial behaviors of these two individuals are paradigmatically “bad” and their premature assessment as [End Page 205] such can be epistemically distorting and otherwise counterproductive. Consider now analogous cases involving aesthetic problems. Pete and Lucie are getting ready for the holidays and are expecting family from out of town. But there are a couple of problems. Pete notices an “ugly” stain on the living room carpet and Lucie notices a subtle but decidedly “nasty” odor permeating the entire house. Neither Pete nor Lucie know where the stain came from, nor where the odor is coming from. But both the stain and the odor are “pretty gross” and so they need to “get","PeriodicalId":45397,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135588279","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Limits of Self-Constitution 自我构成的极限
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-01 DOI: 10.1353/ppp.2023.a908269
James Phillips
The Limits of Self-Constitution James Phillips, MD (bio) I am in general agreement with the authors that a psychoanalytic or psychodynamic approach is a good response to simple pruning procedures. That said, however, I do have questions about how they develop their argument. I was surprised at the very notion of pruning, and quite surprised that it is as popular as the authors suggest. The idea that Pete should deal with his inappropriate outbursts by erasing or pruning that aspect of his personality seems so ridiculous that it beggars belief. It leaves one wondering whether Pete, or anyone agreeing with this argument, is credulous enough to think you can just prune away an undesirable part of yourself. The authors write: Importantly, this expulsion is often thought to be a good thing not simply because the undesirable elements are morally wanting but because in some important sense, they are not really a part of the agent proper. This point many seem extravagantly wishful, but is intuitively plausible. Really, “intuitively plausible” that personality traits are not part of the agent? I can understand that the agent may not grasp his or her involvement in the undesirable trait, but to argue that the trait is in reality not part of agent is a very odd claim on the part of the authors. When the authors write that “It would be difficult to exaggerate the prominence of the pruning view of agential self-constitution in philosophy,” they are strongly connecting the notions of pruning and self-constitution. I am aware that self-constitution is a major theme for philosophers like Korsgaard. The authors strongly embrace this principle in drawing out their arguments. In a footnote to their article the authors claim that various notions of a “true self” imply a pruned self. For Winnicott, an originator of the “true self,” this note of pruning does not hold. Winnicott contrasts the true self, a sense of self based on spontaneous authentic experience and a feeling of being alive, with a false self, a defensive veneer without the vivacity of the true self. The notion of pruning simply does not belong in this discussion. What the authors and their supporting philosophers leave out are two limitations to self-constitution. For the first, let me invoke another philosopher, Martin Heidegger, and his notion of “thrownness”—Geworfenheit. We are “thrown” into the world in the particular circumstances of our birth. We do not self-constitute our beginnings; we are plunged into them. The question then becomes what we make of these beginnings. [End Page 209] If they are undesirable, we can brood over them, or we can attempt to overcome them. And as we all know, if the beginnings are bad enough, we may not be able to overcome them. The second limitation to self-constitution resides in the “self.” Does the individual constitute him or her self, or is it more a matter of the self developing out of dialogic relationship of self and other? Here I invoke another philosopher, P
自我构成的极限詹姆斯·菲利普斯,医学博士(生物)我基本上同意作者的观点,即精神分析或精神动力学方法是对简单修剪程序的一个很好的回应。尽管如此,我还是对他们的论点有疑问。我对修剪的概念感到惊讶,也很惊讶它像作者所说的那样受欢迎。皮特应该通过抹去或修剪他个性的这一方面来处理他不恰当的爆发的想法似乎是如此荒谬,以至于令人难以置信。这让人怀疑,皮特或任何同意这一观点的人是否足够轻信,认为你可以把自己不受欢迎的部分修剪掉。作者写道:重要的是,这种驱逐通常被认为是一件好事,不仅仅是因为不受欢迎的元素在道德上是缺乏的,而是因为在某种重要的意义上,它们并不是真正的主体的一部分。这一点似乎是一厢情愿,但从直觉上讲是合理的。人格特征不是行为人的一部分,这种“直觉上似乎合理”的说法是真的吗?我能理解行为人可能没有意识到他或她参与了不受欢迎的特质,但认为这种特质实际上不是行为人的一部分,这是作者非常奇怪的主张。当作者写道“很难夸大主体自我构成的修剪观点在哲学中的重要性”时,他们将修剪和自我构成的概念紧密地联系在一起。我知道自我构成是像科斯加德这样的哲学家的一个主要主题。作者在阐述他们的论点时强烈地采用了这一原则。在文章的脚注中,作者声称,“真我”的各种概念都暗示着一个被修剪过的自我。对于“真我”的创始人温尼科特来说,这种“修剪”的说法并不成立。温尼科特将真实的自我与虚假的自我进行了对比,真实的自我是一种基于自发的真实体验和活着的感觉的自我意识,虚假的自我是一种缺乏真实自我活力的防御性外表。修剪的概念根本不属于这个讨论。作者和支持他们的哲学家忽略了自我构成的两个限制。首先,让我引用另一位哲学家马丁·海德格尔(Martin Heidegger)和他的“抛掷”概念——geworfenheit。我们是在出生的特殊情况下被“扔”到这个世界上的。我们不能自我构成我们的开端;我们陷入其中。那么问题就变成了我们如何看待这些开端。如果它们是不受欢迎的,我们可以沉思它们,或者我们可以尝试克服它们。我们都知道,如果一开始就很糟糕,我们可能无法克服它们。自我构成的第二个限制在于“自我”。是个体构成了他或她的自我,还是从自我与他人的对话关系中发展出来的自我?在这里,我要引用另一位哲学家保罗·里科,他从多个角度探讨了这个问题。在指示层面上,“我”或自我是一个移位者,根据其上下文具有不同的含义。在语用学的层面上,个体从事于对另一个人的言外之语,简单地说,这意味着我们生活在对话中。与这一讨论更相关的是,Ricoeur注意到自我认识并不是直截了当地的:“自我并没有立即认识自己,而是通过各种各样的文化标志迂回地间接认识自己,这些文化标志使我们说行动是象征性地中介的”(Ricoeur, 2016, p. 240)。最后,Ricoeur主张替代性优先于反身性。“将差异性置于反身性之上进一步推进,一些人会强调个人身份依赖于对……的认同。”英雄、象征人物、模范和教师”(第248页)。为了澄清这一说法,Ricoeur将通过反思的自我构成与自我-他者关系进行了对比,在这种关系中,自我需要他者来构成自己——当然,他是在为后者辩护。虽然我在质疑作者关于……的概念。
{"title":"The Limits of Self-Constitution","authors":"James Phillips","doi":"10.1353/ppp.2023.a908269","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2023.a908269","url":null,"abstract":"The Limits of Self-Constitution James Phillips, MD (bio) I am in general agreement with the authors that a psychoanalytic or psychodynamic approach is a good response to simple pruning procedures. That said, however, I do have questions about how they develop their argument. I was surprised at the very notion of pruning, and quite surprised that it is as popular as the authors suggest. The idea that Pete should deal with his inappropriate outbursts by erasing or pruning that aspect of his personality seems so ridiculous that it beggars belief. It leaves one wondering whether Pete, or anyone agreeing with this argument, is credulous enough to think you can just prune away an undesirable part of yourself. The authors write: Importantly, this expulsion is often thought to be a good thing not simply because the undesirable elements are morally wanting but because in some important sense, they are not really a part of the agent proper. This point many seem extravagantly wishful, but is intuitively plausible. Really, “intuitively plausible” that personality traits are not part of the agent? I can understand that the agent may not grasp his or her involvement in the undesirable trait, but to argue that the trait is in reality not part of agent is a very odd claim on the part of the authors. When the authors write that “It would be difficult to exaggerate the prominence of the pruning view of agential self-constitution in philosophy,” they are strongly connecting the notions of pruning and self-constitution. I am aware that self-constitution is a major theme for philosophers like Korsgaard. The authors strongly embrace this principle in drawing out their arguments. In a footnote to their article the authors claim that various notions of a “true self” imply a pruned self. For Winnicott, an originator of the “true self,” this note of pruning does not hold. Winnicott contrasts the true self, a sense of self based on spontaneous authentic experience and a feeling of being alive, with a false self, a defensive veneer without the vivacity of the true self. The notion of pruning simply does not belong in this discussion. What the authors and their supporting philosophers leave out are two limitations to self-constitution. For the first, let me invoke another philosopher, Martin Heidegger, and his notion of “thrownness”—Geworfenheit. We are “thrown” into the world in the particular circumstances of our birth. We do not self-constitute our beginnings; we are plunged into them. The question then becomes what we make of these beginnings. [End Page 209] If they are undesirable, we can brood over them, or we can attempt to overcome them. And as we all know, if the beginnings are bad enough, we may not be able to overcome them. The second limitation to self-constitution resides in the “self.” Does the individual constitute him or her self, or is it more a matter of the self developing out of dialogic relationship of self and other? Here I invoke another philosopher, P","PeriodicalId":45397,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","volume":"10 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135588170","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Notes on Psychodramatic Treatment of a Person with Schizophrenia 精神分裂症患者的心理戏剧治疗笔记
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-01 DOI: 10.1353/ppp.2023.a908272
Jonathan D. Moreno
Notes on Psychodramatic Treatment of a Person with Schizophrenia Jonathan D. Moreno, PhD (bio) I have enjoyed reflecting on Mr. Chapy’s account of work in psychodrama with a patient with schizophrenia. Although at one time many years ago I was interested in phenomenological psychiatry, and especially the writings of Ludwig Binswanger and Medard Boss, I am not an authority on dasein-analysis, so I have nothing to add to the discussion. I should say, however, that my father had little interest in this approach, which was far too abstract for his taste. He proceeded from the standpoint of the theater, of action and enactment. He believed that the drama itself provided the insight. For the purposes of this response, I take it as a given that the patient in question has been accurately diagnosed, although in the description of the scene with his father he does not exhibit the usual symptoms, such as auditory hallucinations. People with schizophrenia often find it difficult to manage the voices they are hearing without substantial preparation for a psychodrama. According to psychodramatic method, one way to prepare them is to externalize the voices, allowing a different therapist to take the role of each one as the protagonist instructs them how to play that role. Chair may be set up so that each “voice,” personified by an auxiliary ego, can sit in each chair in an array. This preparation may require a number of sessions. If the scene is to be enacted with a significant other, like the father in this instance, the patient may not be able to warm up to a direct encounter, especially with all the different voices competing for his internal attention. So he may be directed to observe each voice in the encounter with his father, preferably played by a therapist of his choosing and trained for the role, usually by giving the father-player certain lines so that they can learn something about the father and the way he addresses his son. Or consider the patient whose illness manifests itself as delusions, often of a megalomaniac character. They may be a messiah, for example, or the rightful heir of a royal line whose identity is being suppressed by governmental forces. The patient might be invited to choose key therapists to play the roles of key members of their circle, [End Page 225] enacting critical scenes like the sermon on the mount or speeches to their oppressed followers. In this way the patient’s “act hunger” may be to some degree satiated and have a calming effect on their anxiety and irritation with the frustrating world around them that refuses to accept their “authentic” identity and belief system. In these ways, psychodrama therapy can take advantage of one of the remarkable advantages of this method for such patients, who are generally recalcitrant to talk therapy alone and for whom medication is at best modestly effective. Still, these disorders are among the most challenging for psychotherapists. Although the process of treating them may open
Jonathan D. Moreno博士(生物)我很喜欢Chapy先生在精神分裂症患者的心理剧治疗中所做的工作。虽然多年前我一度对现象学精神病学很感兴趣,尤其是路德维希·宾斯旺格和梅达德·博斯的著作,但我并不是客体分析方面的权威,所以我对这个讨论没有什么可补充的。然而,我应该说,我父亲对这种方法不感兴趣,因为对他的口味来说,这种方法太抽象了。他从戏剧的角度出发,从行动和表演的角度出发。他认为戏剧本身提供了洞察力。出于本回答的目的,我认为所讨论的病人得到了准确的诊断,尽管在描述他与父亲的场景时,他并没有表现出通常的症状,例如幻听。精神分裂症患者经常发现,如果没有充分的心理剧准备,他们很难控制自己听到的声音。根据心理戏剧的方法,让他们做好准备的一种方法是将这些声音外化,让不同的治疗师扮演每个人的角色,让主角指导他们如何扮演那个角色。椅子可以被设置成这样,每个“声音”,由一个辅助的自我拟人化,可以以阵列的形式坐在每把椅子上。这种准备工作可能需要若干次会议。如果这个场景是和一个重要的人一起上演的,就像这个例子中的父亲一样,病人可能无法对直接的接触进行热身,尤其是在所有不同的声音都在争夺他内心的注意力的情况下。因此,他可能会被指导去观察与父亲相遇时的每一个声音,最好是由他自己选择并接受过这个角色训练的治疗师来扮演,通常是通过给扮演父亲的人一些台词,这样他们就能了解父亲和他对儿子说话的方式。或者想想病人的疾病表现为妄想,通常是自大狂的特征。例如,他们可能是弥赛亚,或者是被政府压制身份的皇室合法继承人。病人可能会被邀请选择关键的治疗师来扮演他们圈子里的关键成员的角色,上演关键的场景,比如山上的布道或对受压迫的追随者的演讲。通过这种方式,病人的“行为饥饿”可能在某种程度上得到满足,并对他们周围拒绝接受他们“真实”身份和信仰体系的令人沮丧的世界的焦虑和愤怒产生镇静作用。在这些方面,心理剧治疗可以利用这种方法的一个显著优势,对这些患者来说,他们通常不愿单独进行谈话治疗,对他们来说,药物治疗充其量只是适度有效。尽管如此,这些疾病对心理治疗师来说仍然是最具挑战性的。尽管正如Chapy在这篇论文中所追求的那样,治疗他们的过程可能会让我们对人类思维的本质有更深入的了解,但我们仍在等待神经科学的发展,以实现他们和他们的家人所迫切希望的那种长期缓解。[endpage 226] Jonathan D. Moreno宾夕法尼亚大学morenojd@pennmedicine.upenn.edu Jonathan D. Moreno乔纳森D. Moreno是一位哲学家和历史学家,专门研究生物伦理学,文化,科学和国家安全的交叉,并发表了关于生物学和医学的历史,社会学和政治的开创性著作。他是美国国家医学院的当选成员。版权所有©2023约翰霍普金斯大学出版社
{"title":"Notes on Psychodramatic Treatment of a Person with Schizophrenia","authors":"Jonathan D. Moreno","doi":"10.1353/ppp.2023.a908272","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2023.a908272","url":null,"abstract":"Notes on Psychodramatic Treatment of a Person with Schizophrenia Jonathan D. Moreno, PhD (bio) I have enjoyed reflecting on Mr. Chapy’s account of work in psychodrama with a patient with schizophrenia. Although at one time many years ago I was interested in phenomenological psychiatry, and especially the writings of Ludwig Binswanger and Medard Boss, I am not an authority on dasein-analysis, so I have nothing to add to the discussion. I should say, however, that my father had little interest in this approach, which was far too abstract for his taste. He proceeded from the standpoint of the theater, of action and enactment. He believed that the drama itself provided the insight. For the purposes of this response, I take it as a given that the patient in question has been accurately diagnosed, although in the description of the scene with his father he does not exhibit the usual symptoms, such as auditory hallucinations. People with schizophrenia often find it difficult to manage the voices they are hearing without substantial preparation for a psychodrama. According to psychodramatic method, one way to prepare them is to externalize the voices, allowing a different therapist to take the role of each one as the protagonist instructs them how to play that role. Chair may be set up so that each “voice,” personified by an auxiliary ego, can sit in each chair in an array. This preparation may require a number of sessions. If the scene is to be enacted with a significant other, like the father in this instance, the patient may not be able to warm up to a direct encounter, especially with all the different voices competing for his internal attention. So he may be directed to observe each voice in the encounter with his father, preferably played by a therapist of his choosing and trained for the role, usually by giving the father-player certain lines so that they can learn something about the father and the way he addresses his son. Or consider the patient whose illness manifests itself as delusions, often of a megalomaniac character. They may be a messiah, for example, or the rightful heir of a royal line whose identity is being suppressed by governmental forces. The patient might be invited to choose key therapists to play the roles of key members of their circle, [End Page 225] enacting critical scenes like the sermon on the mount or speeches to their oppressed followers. In this way the patient’s “act hunger” may be to some degree satiated and have a calming effect on their anxiety and irritation with the frustrating world around them that refuses to accept their “authentic” identity and belief system. In these ways, psychodrama therapy can take advantage of one of the remarkable advantages of this method for such patients, who are generally recalcitrant to talk therapy alone and for whom medication is at best modestly effective. Still, these disorders are among the most challenging for psychotherapists. Although the process of treating them may open ","PeriodicalId":45397,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","volume":"30 1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135588282","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Psychiatric Diagnosis as Recognition in Disorder Identified Individuals 精神病学诊断作为识别障碍的个体
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-01 DOI: 10.1353/ppp.2023.a908279
Chloe Saunders
Abstract: Psychiatric diagnoses are increasingly seen as viable categories around which self and social identities might be drawn. This introduces a new pressure on the “boundary problem” for psychiatry: when members of the public request diagnoses to affirm their self-identities how should we draw the line between mental disorder and normality? If psychiatrists have the authority to recognize and diagnose mental disorder, how can roles as diagnosers and gate-keepers be balanced in a post-stigma era of mental health care? Focusing on the disorder identified would-be patient who would not attract the diagnosis they seek were they not to seek it, this essay explores what it means to have an identity bound to a psychiatric diagnosis and considers a framework for psychiatrists to negotiate clinical encounters that involve the seeking of identity affirming diagnoses.
摘要:精神病学诊断越来越被视为一种可行的类别,可以围绕其绘制自我和社会身份。这给精神病学的“边界问题”带来了新的压力:当公众要求诊断以确认他们的自我认同时,我们应该如何在精神障碍和正常之间划清界限?如果精神科医生有权识别和诊断精神障碍,那么在精神卫生保健的后耻辱时代,作为诊断者和看门人的角色该如何平衡呢?这篇文章关注的是那些如果不寻求诊断就不会得到诊断的潜在患者,探讨了将身份与精神病诊断绑定在一起意味着什么,并考虑了精神科医生在寻求身份确认诊断的临床接触中进行谈判的框架。
{"title":"Psychiatric Diagnosis as Recognition in Disorder Identified Individuals","authors":"Chloe Saunders","doi":"10.1353/ppp.2023.a908279","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2023.a908279","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract: Psychiatric diagnoses are increasingly seen as viable categories around which self and social identities might be drawn. This introduces a new pressure on the “boundary problem” for psychiatry: when members of the public request diagnoses to affirm their self-identities how should we draw the line between mental disorder and normality? If psychiatrists have the authority to recognize and diagnose mental disorder, how can roles as diagnosers and gate-keepers be balanced in a post-stigma era of mental health care? Focusing on the disorder identified would-be patient who would not attract the diagnosis they seek were they not to seek it, this essay explores what it means to have an identity bound to a psychiatric diagnosis and considers a framework for psychiatrists to negotiate clinical encounters that involve the seeking of identity affirming diagnoses.","PeriodicalId":45397,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","volume":"10 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135588422","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Existential Psychodrama: A Way to Incorporate Otherness and Open Up to Existence: A Clinical Approach of Psychosis 存在主义心理剧:一种结合差异性和对存在开放的方式:精神病的临床方法
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-01 DOI: 10.1353/ppp.2023.a908271
Corinne Gal, Alexandre Chapy, Marielle Fau, Muriel Guaveia
Abstract: The authors argue that Morenian-inspired existential psychodrama turns out to be a formidable lever for opening up existence as it allows schizophrenic patients to incorporate the experience of an “absolutely other” on which the foundation of any autonomous self is built. More precisely, by relying on their clinical experiences, the authors show how psycho-dramatic play goes along with an intense movement of original projection which carries psychotic patients externally in relation to themselves. Offset from their pathological world, these patients feel more inclined to “wear someone else’s shoes,” for the duration of the game, and they do so in a manner that is both sensorial and pathic. This surprising and creative “journey,” which allows them to return to the world better attuned to others and to themselves, is merely an enactment of a “true” intersubjective encounter: the very essence of existential psychodrama. By applying phenomenology to this psychodramatic method, notably by relying on the hypothesis of psychosis being a disorder of what Bin Kimura calls the “ aida ,” the authors hope to contribute to the advancement of psychosis’ psychotherapy.
摘要:作者认为,莫雷尼启发的存在主义心理剧是打开存在的强大杠杆,因为它允许精神分裂症患者纳入“绝对他者”的经验,而任何自主自我的基础都建立在这种经验之上。更准确地说,依靠他们的临床经验,作者展示了心理戏剧是如何伴随着原始投射的强烈运动的,这种运动将精神病患者与自己联系在一起。与他们的病态世界相抵消,这些患者在游戏过程中更倾向于“穿别人的鞋”,他们这样做的方式是感性的和悲情的。这种令人惊讶和创造性的“旅程”,使他们能够更好地与他人和自己协调一致地回到这个世界,这仅仅是一场“真正的”主体间相遇的表演:存在主义心理剧的本质。通过将现象学应用于这种心理戏剧方法,特别是通过依赖于精神病是一种被木村本称为“aida”的紊乱的假设,作者希望为精神病心理治疗的进步做出贡献。
{"title":"Existential Psychodrama: A Way to Incorporate Otherness and Open Up to Existence: A Clinical Approach of Psychosis","authors":"Corinne Gal, Alexandre Chapy, Marielle Fau, Muriel Guaveia","doi":"10.1353/ppp.2023.a908271","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2023.a908271","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract: The authors argue that Morenian-inspired existential psychodrama turns out to be a formidable lever for opening up existence as it allows schizophrenic patients to incorporate the experience of an “absolutely other” on which the foundation of any autonomous self is built. More precisely, by relying on their clinical experiences, the authors show how psycho-dramatic play goes along with an intense movement of original projection which carries psychotic patients externally in relation to themselves. Offset from their pathological world, these patients feel more inclined to “wear someone else’s shoes,” for the duration of the game, and they do so in a manner that is both sensorial and pathic. This surprising and creative “journey,” which allows them to return to the world better attuned to others and to themselves, is merely an enactment of a “true” intersubjective encounter: the very essence of existential psychodrama. By applying phenomenology to this psychodramatic method, notably by relying on the hypothesis of psychosis being a disorder of what Bin Kimura calls the “ aida ,” the authors hope to contribute to the advancement of psychosis’ psychotherapy.","PeriodicalId":45397,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135588421","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Could Understanding Harm? 理解会造成伤害吗?
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-01 DOI: 10.1353/ppp.2023.a908270
Iskra Fileva, Linda A.W. Brakel
Could Understanding Harm? Iskra Fileva, PhD (bio) and Linda A.W. Brakel, MD (bio) We would like to thank the editors for organizing this symposium and our commentators—Marga Reimer and James Phillips—for the thought-provoking feedback. Although we had thought about the ideas we discuss from many different angles, our commentators raised several interesting issues we had not considered. We are grateful for the opportunity to continue the conversation. Reply to Reimer As Professor Reimer notes, we advocate an approach to self-constitution that we dub “understanding first.” On this approach, non-moral and non-normative understanding of the origin of maladaptive traits must precede moral evaluation and attempts to free oneself—or as we say “prune”—undesirable traits. Professor Reimer presents several interesting cases meant both to extend and test the limits of our proposal. We appreciate this approach and respond to each case in turn. Genes and Alcoholism Suppose Alejandro, an adult raised by adoptive parents, struggles with alcohol addiction. He learns that his biological parents died of alcoholic liver disease and comes to believe that his alcohol problem is caused by a genetic propensity toward alcohol abuse. One can ask: “Does an understanding first approach have the potential to undermine the sense of agency that is necessary for the effective treatment of maladaptive traits?” Answer: It can be explained to Alejandro that genetic proclivities are just that—proclivities—that can be overridden. In fact, behavior can alter our very genes—although not at the sequence level— changes known as “epigenetic.” And the liver disease of the biological parents can serve as a cautionary tale. If even in light of these considerations, Alejandro’s tendency to see genetic propensities as deterministic persists, it is worth asking why. There is no evidence that “genes are destiny,” so the disposition to see them that way must have a psychological explanation. What is the explanation? A self-destructive desire? Fear of freedom? This exploration can itself be empowering. [End Page 211] Adaptive Forgetting Suppose Beata, who has an eating disorder, was molested by her own father when she was a child. Subsequently, her father shot himself and now she has no recollection of the molestation. However, Beata’s eating disorder is largely a result of those experiences. It is quite possible that if Beata were to recall being molested, that would do more harm than good. In this connection, one can ask together with Reimer: “Does an understanding first approach have the potential to undermine an adaptive ‘forgetting’ of root causes of maladaptive traits?” Answer: Here, understanding the history, instead of forgetting it, might allow Beata to gain insight into and empathize with possible motives that may have led to becoming obese. For example, she might have the phantasy that if she had been obese and unattractive, she could have prevented the molestation—hence, become that
理解会造成伤害吗?Iskra Fileva,博士(生物)和Linda A.W. Brakel,医学博士(生物)我们要感谢编辑组织这次研讨会和我们的评论员——marga Reimer和James phillips——为发人深省的反馈。虽然我们从许多不同的角度思考了我们讨论的观点,但我们的评论员提出了几个我们没有考虑到的有趣问题。我们很感激有机会继续对话。正如雷默教授所指出的,我们提倡一种自我建构的方法,我们称之为“理解为先”。在这种方法中,对不适应特征的起源的非道德和非规范的理解必须先于道德评价和试图释放自己——或者正如我们所说的“修剪”——不受欢迎的特征。Reimer教授提出了几个有趣的案例,旨在扩展和测试我们建议的局限性。我们赞赏这种做法,并对每个案件轮流作出回应。假设由养父母抚养长大的成年人亚历杭德罗与酒精成瘾作斗争。他得知他的亲生父母死于酒精性肝病,并开始相信他的酗酒问题是由酗酒的遗传倾向引起的。有人可能会问:“理解第一的方法是否有可能破坏有效治疗适应不良特征所必需的能动性?”回答:可以向亚历杭德罗解释,遗传倾向只是可以被推翻的倾向。事实上,行为可以改变我们的基因——尽管不是在序列水平上——这种改变被称为“表观遗传”。而亲生父母的肝脏疾病可以作为一个警示。即使考虑到这些因素,亚历杭德罗将遗传倾向视为决定性的倾向仍然存在,我们也有必要问一下为什么。没有证据表明“基因决定命运”,所以这样看待它们的倾向一定有心理学上的解释。解释是什么?自我毁灭的欲望?害怕自由?这种探索本身就是一种力量。适应性遗忘假设贝娅塔患有饮食失调症,在她还是个孩子的时候被她自己的父亲猥亵过。后来,她的父亲开枪自杀了,现在她对性骚扰没有任何记忆。然而,贝娅塔的饮食失调很大程度上是这些经历的结果。很有可能,如果贝娅塔回忆起自己被猥亵过,那将弊大于利。在这方面,我们可以和雷默一起问:“理解第一的方法是否有可能破坏对不适应特征根源的适应性‘遗忘’?”回答:在这里,理解历史,而不是忘记它,可能会让Beata深入了解和同情可能导致肥胖的动机。例如,她可能会幻想,如果她肥胖且没有吸引力,她就可以阻止性骚扰——因此,她现在变成那样是为了防止性骚扰再次发生,更希望能逆转它。(在无意识的进行中,时间被认为存在于“未经检验的现在”中)(brake 2009, p. 63;2015,第131页;2022,第4页;2023,第404页。)这样做的一个好处是,在获得这种类型的认可后,Beata可能会发现改变自己的行为更容易,否则她不会这样做;防止自己被骚扰从来都不是她的责任,她现在也没有理由让自己对已故的父亲失去吸引力,也没有理由为了阻止现在的男人而保持肥胖。克莱尔是一名钢琴演奏家和酒鬼。重要的是,克莱尔并不认为自己对酒精的渴望是破坏性的,相反,这是她自己身份的组成部分。她说:“没有酒精,我就不是我自己。”雷默问道,我们的方法是否“适用于行为人将适应不良特征视为其身份组成部分的情况?”回答:虽然没有一种方法可以保证成功,但我们的观点是,我们的方法比被称为修剪视图的主要替代方法有更好的机会。既然根据规定,克莱尔不倾向于把自己的酗酒视为一个问题,那么…
{"title":"Could Understanding Harm?","authors":"Iskra Fileva, Linda A.W. Brakel","doi":"10.1353/ppp.2023.a908270","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2023.a908270","url":null,"abstract":"Could Understanding Harm? Iskra Fileva, PhD (bio) and Linda A.W. Brakel, MD (bio) We would like to thank the editors for organizing this symposium and our commentators—Marga Reimer and James Phillips—for the thought-provoking feedback. Although we had thought about the ideas we discuss from many different angles, our commentators raised several interesting issues we had not considered. We are grateful for the opportunity to continue the conversation. Reply to Reimer As Professor Reimer notes, we advocate an approach to self-constitution that we dub “understanding first.” On this approach, non-moral and non-normative understanding of the origin of maladaptive traits must precede moral evaluation and attempts to free oneself—or as we say “prune”—undesirable traits. Professor Reimer presents several interesting cases meant both to extend and test the limits of our proposal. We appreciate this approach and respond to each case in turn. Genes and Alcoholism Suppose Alejandro, an adult raised by adoptive parents, struggles with alcohol addiction. He learns that his biological parents died of alcoholic liver disease and comes to believe that his alcohol problem is caused by a genetic propensity toward alcohol abuse. One can ask: “Does an understanding first approach have the potential to undermine the sense of agency that is necessary for the effective treatment of maladaptive traits?” Answer: It can be explained to Alejandro that genetic proclivities are just that—proclivities—that can be overridden. In fact, behavior can alter our very genes—although not at the sequence level— changes known as “epigenetic.” And the liver disease of the biological parents can serve as a cautionary tale. If even in light of these considerations, Alejandro’s tendency to see genetic propensities as deterministic persists, it is worth asking why. There is no evidence that “genes are destiny,” so the disposition to see them that way must have a psychological explanation. What is the explanation? A self-destructive desire? Fear of freedom? This exploration can itself be empowering. [End Page 211] Adaptive Forgetting Suppose Beata, who has an eating disorder, was molested by her own father when she was a child. Subsequently, her father shot himself and now she has no recollection of the molestation. However, Beata’s eating disorder is largely a result of those experiences. It is quite possible that if Beata were to recall being molested, that would do more harm than good. In this connection, one can ask together with Reimer: “Does an understanding first approach have the potential to undermine an adaptive ‘forgetting’ of root causes of maladaptive traits?” Answer: Here, understanding the history, instead of forgetting it, might allow Beata to gain insight into and empathize with possible motives that may have led to becoming obese. For example, she might have the phantasy that if she had been obese and unattractive, she could have prevented the molestation—hence, become that ","PeriodicalId":45397,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","volume":"13 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135588272","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Diagnostic Criteria, Psychological Tests, and Ratings Scales: Extending the History 诊断标准、心理测试和评定量表:延长病史
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-01 DOI: 10.1353/ppp.2023.a908276
Peter Zachar
Diagnostic Criteria, Psychological Tests, and Ratings Scales: Extending the History Peter Zachar, PhD (bio) Le moigne narrates a history of the development of psychiatric ratings scales as hybrids between psychological tests and diagnostic categories. In his telling, psychological tests seek to quantify population-based traits on which every person has a position and which tend to be conceptualized as being stable. Personality traits are often conceptualized as dispositions. Diagnostic categories represent not trait-like properties of populations but episodic states consisting of clusters of symptoms experienced by individuals with disorders. Ratings, scales, he notes, are hybrids between the two. They are used to quantify psychiatric symptom clusters so that change over time can be measured. Le Moigne argues that these distinctions were initially suggested during the development of measures that could assess outcomes in psychopharmacological treatment studies. With respect to depression, Le Moigne writes that in the 1970s and 1980s something akin to depressive personality was reconceptualized as a temperament. A key move, somewhat reflective of Kraepelin’s notion of a depressive temperament, was to view a dysthymic temperament as both a predisposing factor and an attenuated form of depression. Thus, an episodic state commandeered the predisposing–dispositional role that was assigned to stable personality traits. This conceptual shift allowed test-like ratings scales to be seen as useful for quantifying not just stable traits, but salient features of episodic states that are potentially subject to change in response to interventions. To put it another way, in the development of a psychological test, one goal is to have high test-retest reliability (i.e., stability of measurement). With rating scales used to measure change, one wants the scores to not be as stable; ideally the scores on the later assessments will be lower. According to Le Moigne, when dysthymia was subsequently placed on axis I of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM)-III (as a syndrome) and segregated from personality disorders which were placed on axis II, personality traits were evicted from the conceptualization of depressive disorders. One perennial feature of psychiatry and psychology is that even if an older idea is superseded [End Page 253] in the view of some thinkers, it can still attract adherents. Indeed, interest in understanding a relationship between personality and attenuated states did not fully disappear. For example, based on research in genetics, the schizophrenia spectrum concept included not only schizophrenia, but also milder conditions such that were conceptualized as personality disorders; that is, schizotypal personality disorder and paranoid personality disorder (Kety, Rosenthal, Wender, & Schulsinger, 1971). During the development of the DSM-IV, some people wanted to add depressive personality disorder to the manual (Phillips,
诊断标准、心理测试和评定量表:扩展历史Peter Zachar博士(生物)Le moigne叙述了精神病学评定量表作为心理测试和诊断类别的混合体的发展历史。在他的叙述中,心理测试试图量化基于人群的特征,每个人都有自己的位置,这些特征往往被概念化为稳定的。人格特质通常被定义为性格。诊断类别代表的不是群体的特征,而是由疾病个体所经历的症状群组成的偶发状态。他指出,评级和量表是两者的混合体。它们被用来量化精神症状群,以便可以测量随时间的变化。Le Moigne认为,这些区别最初是在评估精神药理学治疗研究结果的措施发展过程中提出的。关于抑郁症,Le Moigne写道,在20世纪70年代和80年代,类似于抑郁人格的东西被重新定义为一种气质。一个关键的举动,多少反映了Kraepelin的抑郁气质的概念,是将心境恶劣的气质视为一种诱发因素和抑郁症的减弱形式。因此,一种偶发状态占据了被分配给稳定人格特质的倾向-性格角色。这种概念上的转变使得类似测试的评分量表不仅可以用来量化稳定的特征,还可以用来量化在干预措施下可能发生变化的情景状态的显著特征。换句话说,在开发心理测试时,一个目标是具有高的重测信度(即测量的稳定性)。对于用来衡量变化的评分量表,人们希望分数不那么稳定;理想情况下,后期评估的分数会低一些。根据Le Moigne的说法,当心境恶劣随后被置于精神疾病诊断与统计手册(DSM)-III(作为一种综合征)的轴I上,并与置于轴II上的人格障碍分开时,人格特征被从抑郁症的概念化中驱逐出去。精神病学和心理学的一个长期特征是,即使在一些思想家看来,一个旧的想法被取代了,它仍然可以吸引追随者。事实上,人们对理解人格与弱化状态之间关系的兴趣并没有完全消失。例如,基于遗传学的研究,精神分裂症谱系概念不仅包括精神分裂症,还包括被定义为人格障碍的较轻微的疾病;即分裂型人格障碍和偏执型人格障碍(Kety, Rosenthal, Wender, & Schulsinger, 1971)。在DSM-IV的开发过程中,一些人想在手册中增加抑郁症人格障碍(Phillips, Hirschfeld, Shea, & Gunderson, 1995)。这似乎已经成为了情绪障碍专家和人格障碍专家之间的领土之争。情绪障碍专家向人格障碍专家提出挑战,要求他们将抑郁型人格障碍与早发性慢性心境恶劣区分开来。他们能够通过使用诸如批评、责备和贬低自我等标准来做到这一点。在情绪障碍工作组提议将其中一些标准纳入心境恶劣的修订标准集之后,这两套标准重叠了。结果是旧的心境恶劣的标准被印在DSM-IV中,而抑郁型人格障碍的标准和修订后的心境恶劣的标准都被放在附录中。在DSM-5中,消除了轴II,将人格障碍与所有症候症状群放在同一水平。即便如此,人们仍然对与个性有关的弱化演讲感兴趣。在DSM-5的开发过程中,有人认为使用诊断谱作为组织手册的元结构(Andrews et al., 2009)。一种想法是将一些人格障碍转移到最合适的范围内,类似于减弱的形式。这确实发生在分裂型人格障碍中这在DSM-5关于精神分裂症的章节和关于人格障碍的章节中都有。在精神分裂症一章中,它被定位为谱系中最早出现的疾病。也有人对将回避型人格障碍与焦虑症分类感兴趣,但没有证据支持这种变化。这些问题可能……
{"title":"Diagnostic Criteria, Psychological Tests, and Ratings Scales: Extending the History","authors":"Peter Zachar","doi":"10.1353/ppp.2023.a908276","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2023.a908276","url":null,"abstract":"Diagnostic Criteria, Psychological Tests, and Ratings Scales: Extending the History Peter Zachar, PhD (bio) Le moigne narrates a history of the development of psychiatric ratings scales as hybrids between psychological tests and diagnostic categories. In his telling, psychological tests seek to quantify population-based traits on which every person has a position and which tend to be conceptualized as being stable. Personality traits are often conceptualized as dispositions. Diagnostic categories represent not trait-like properties of populations but episodic states consisting of clusters of symptoms experienced by individuals with disorders. Ratings, scales, he notes, are hybrids between the two. They are used to quantify psychiatric symptom clusters so that change over time can be measured. Le Moigne argues that these distinctions were initially suggested during the development of measures that could assess outcomes in psychopharmacological treatment studies. With respect to depression, Le Moigne writes that in the 1970s and 1980s something akin to depressive personality was reconceptualized as a temperament. A key move, somewhat reflective of Kraepelin’s notion of a depressive temperament, was to view a dysthymic temperament as both a predisposing factor and an attenuated form of depression. Thus, an episodic state commandeered the predisposing–dispositional role that was assigned to stable personality traits. This conceptual shift allowed test-like ratings scales to be seen as useful for quantifying not just stable traits, but salient features of episodic states that are potentially subject to change in response to interventions. To put it another way, in the development of a psychological test, one goal is to have high test-retest reliability (i.e., stability of measurement). With rating scales used to measure change, one wants the scores to not be as stable; ideally the scores on the later assessments will be lower. According to Le Moigne, when dysthymia was subsequently placed on axis I of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM)-III (as a syndrome) and segregated from personality disorders which were placed on axis II, personality traits were evicted from the conceptualization of depressive disorders. One perennial feature of psychiatry and psychology is that even if an older idea is superseded [End Page 253] in the view of some thinkers, it can still attract adherents. Indeed, interest in understanding a relationship between personality and attenuated states did not fully disappear. For example, based on research in genetics, the schizophrenia spectrum concept included not only schizophrenia, but also milder conditions such that were conceptualized as personality disorders; that is, schizotypal personality disorder and paranoid personality disorder (Kety, Rosenthal, Wender, & Schulsinger, 1971). During the development of the DSM-IV, some people wanted to add depressive personality disorder to the manual (Phillips, ","PeriodicalId":45397,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","volume":"14 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135588417","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Understanding First: A Psychoanalytic Take on Self-Constitution 理解第一:对自我构成的精神分析
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-01 DOI: 10.1353/ppp.2023.a908267
Iskra Fileva, Linda A.W. Brakel
Abstract: In this paper, we criticize what we dub the “pruning view” of self-constitution, championed widely by philosophers, mainly though not exclusively in the Kantian tradition, and instead defend an alternative view inspired by psychoanalysis. We argue that normative assessment comes much too early on the pruning view, so early that it interferes with achieving deeper self-understanding that can produce lasting change. On the proposal we advocate, self-constitution must begin with a non-moralizing attempt to truly understand why one has undesirable and unwanted propensities. We call this the “understanding first” principle. Only after deeper self-understanding has been achieved are attempts to liberate oneself from unwanted elements likely to succeed.
摘要:在本文中,我们批判了哲学家们广泛倡导的自我构成的“修剪观”,并为精神分析启发的另一种观点辩护。我们认为,在修剪观点中,规范性评估来得太早了,太早了,以至于它干扰了实现更深层次的自我理解,从而产生持久的变化。根据我们提倡的建议,自我建构必须从一种非道德化的尝试开始,以真正理解为什么一个人有不受欢迎和不受欢迎的倾向。我们称之为“理解第一”原则。只有在对自我有了更深入的了解之后,把自己从不想要的因素中解放出来的努力才有可能成功。
{"title":"Understanding First: A Psychoanalytic Take on Self-Constitution","authors":"Iskra Fileva, Linda A.W. Brakel","doi":"10.1353/ppp.2023.a908267","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2023.a908267","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract: In this paper, we criticize what we dub the “pruning view” of self-constitution, championed widely by philosophers, mainly though not exclusively in the Kantian tradition, and instead defend an alternative view inspired by psychoanalysis. We argue that normative assessment comes much too early on the pruning view, so early that it interferes with achieving deeper self-understanding that can produce lasting change. On the proposal we advocate, self-constitution must begin with a non-moralizing attempt to truly understand why one has undesirable and unwanted propensities. We call this the “understanding first” principle. Only after deeper self-understanding has been achieved are attempts to liberate oneself from unwanted elements likely to succeed.","PeriodicalId":45397,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","volume":"29 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135588827","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
“What Is Actually Being Measured?”: Causality and Underlying Scientific Thinking Process in the Assessment of Depression “实际被衡量的是什么?”:抑郁症评估中的因果关系和潜在的科学思维过程
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-01 DOI: 10.1353/ppp.2023.a908277
Greta Kaluzeviciute-Moreton
“What Is Actually Being Measured?”: Causality and Underlying Scientific Thinking Process in the Assessment of Depression Greta Kaluzeviciute-Moreton, PhD (bio) Depression is a complex mental health phenomenon due to its multifaceted nature. For one, depression is thought to have a significant genetic component, with studies suggesting that heritability is a significant factor in the development of the disorder (Sullivan, Neale, Kendler, 2000). In clinical psychology, environmental factors such as childhood trauma, chronic stress, social isolation and negative life events (e.g., the loss of a loved one) have been documented as significant risk factors for the development of depression or as trigger events for depressive episodes (Fu & Parahoo, 2009; Kendler, Kuhn, & Prescott, 2004; Neitzke, 2016). Despite this, causal theories of mental health conditions are often tricky and/or scarcely reflected in both diagnostic and rating scales. For instance, the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders classifies mental health disorders primarily based on observable symptoms and behaviors, rather than on the underlying psychological and neurobiological processes that may contribute to these symptoms (Kendler, 2006). Similarly, rating scales for depression are typically designed to assess the severity of symptoms, rather than their underlying causes, that is, most rating scales are used as screening tools to identify individuals who may require further evaluation and treatment. Some rating scales may include items related to causal factors, such as the Beck Depression Inventory-II (BDI-II) includes an item that asks about “loss of interest in sex,” which could be related to either biological or psychological factors. Several rating scales include items assessing risk factors for depression, such as family history of depression or personal history of trauma. This may be indicative of both genetic and environmental risk factors, such as the Patient Health [End Page 255] Questionnaire-9, includes an item that asks about family history of depression. However, while risk and causal factors are related, they are distinct in the assessment of depression. Risk factors refer to factors that increase the likelihood of developing depression, while causal factors refer to factors that directly contribute to the development of the condition. The presence of a risk factor does not necessarily mean that an individual will develop depression (Peterson & Seligman, 1984). However, the two are frequently blurred and equated in psychotherapy research (Westen & Bradley, 2005). As such, the historical issues of rating and diagnostic scales, aptly depicted by the Le Moigne (2023) as full of “composite, if not contradictory, heritage, weaving together the classificatory and discontinuous tradition of psychiatry, on the one hand, and the psychometric and continuous tradition of psychology, on the other” (p. XX<EQ>), suffer from an epistemological oversight when it comes
“实际被衡量的是什么?”:抑郁症的因果关系和潜在的科学思维过程Greta Kaluzeviciute-Moreton博士(生物)抑郁症是一种复杂的心理健康现象,由于其多方面的性质。首先,抑郁症被认为具有重要的遗传成分,研究表明,遗传性是该疾病发展的重要因素(Sullivan, Neale, Kendler, 2000)。在临床心理学中,环境因素,如童年创伤、慢性压力、社会孤立和负面生活事件(如失去亲人)已被记录为抑郁症发展的重要风险因素或抑郁症发作的触发事件(Fu & Parahoo, 2009;肯德勒,库恩和普雷斯科特,2004;Neitzke, 2016)。尽管如此,心理健康状况的因果理论往往是棘手的和/或几乎没有反映在诊断和评级量表。例如,《精神障碍诊断和统计手册》主要根据可观察到的症状和行为对精神健康障碍进行分类,而不是根据可能导致这些症状的潜在心理和神经生物学过程(Kendler, 2006年)。同样,抑郁症的评定量表通常用于评估症状的严重程度,而不是其潜在原因,也就是说,大多数评定量表被用作筛选工具,以确定可能需要进一步评估和治疗的个体。一些评定量表可能包括与因果因素相关的项目,如贝克抑郁量表ii (BDI-II)包括一个关于“对性失去兴趣”的项目,这可能与生物或心理因素有关。一些评定量表包括评估抑郁症风险因素的项目,如抑郁症家族史或个人创伤史。这可能是遗传和环境风险因素的指示,如患者健康问卷-9,包括一个关于抑郁症家族史的问题。然而,虽然风险因素和因果因素是相关的,但它们在抑郁症的评估中是不同的。风险因素是指增加患抑郁症可能性的因素,而因果因素是指直接导致病情发展的因素。风险因素的存在并不一定意味着个体会患上抑郁症(Peterson & Seligman, 1984)。然而,在心理治疗研究中,这两者经常被模糊和等同起来(Westen & Bradley, 2005)。因此,评定和诊断量表的历史问题,被Le Moigne(2023)恰当地描述为“一方面是精神病学的分类和不连续的传统,另一方面是心理学的心理测量学和连续的传统,交织在一起,即使不是矛盾的,遗产是复合的”(第XX页),在评估复杂心理健康状况(如抑郁症)的因果因素时,受到认识论的忽视。反过来,这又引出了一个更广泛的心理测量问题:到底测量的是什么?Le Moigne的详细概述主要集中在抑郁症的“表面”症状学(这促成了两种截然不同的评估形式:异质评估和自我评估),以及它在整个历史上对抑郁症分类和分类的后续影响。然而,抑郁症的总体概念(包括对因果因素及其评估的更详细的考虑)和评定量表在应用研究(如心理治疗)中的有用性仍然是背景。“实际测量的是什么”这个问题显然在心理测量学中并不新鲜。然而,考虑到评定量表(如BDI)被认为是普遍适用的“循证”工具(Rogers, Adler, Bungay, & Wilson, 2005),以及心理治疗研究中常见且被广泛接受的科学思维形式(Kaluzeviciute & Willemsen, 2020),不断重新审视这个问题是很重要的。从认识论的角度来看,科学思维方式不仅需要方法论共同的认知操作,还需要生成、共享、吸收和转化知识的实践(Hacking, 2012)。因此,重要的是要承认,任何科学工具,包括评分量表,不仅包括研究人员发现他们所研究的现象的内容,还包括研究人员如何发现他们所研究的现象(即,科学的思维方式传达了一种行为品质)(Kaluzeviciute & Willemsen, 2020)。正如Le Moigne(2023)所指出的那样,分类学导致了一种基于类别的逻辑,因为它认为所检查的现象仅由一个…
{"title":"“What Is Actually Being Measured?”: Causality and Underlying Scientific Thinking Process in the Assessment of Depression","authors":"Greta Kaluzeviciute-Moreton","doi":"10.1353/ppp.2023.a908277","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2023.a908277","url":null,"abstract":"“What Is Actually Being Measured?”: Causality and Underlying Scientific Thinking Process in the Assessment of Depression Greta Kaluzeviciute-Moreton, PhD (bio) Depression is a complex mental health phenomenon due to its multifaceted nature. For one, depression is thought to have a significant genetic component, with studies suggesting that heritability is a significant factor in the development of the disorder (Sullivan, Neale, Kendler, 2000). In clinical psychology, environmental factors such as childhood trauma, chronic stress, social isolation and negative life events (e.g., the loss of a loved one) have been documented as significant risk factors for the development of depression or as trigger events for depressive episodes (Fu & Parahoo, 2009; Kendler, Kuhn, & Prescott, 2004; Neitzke, 2016). Despite this, causal theories of mental health conditions are often tricky and/or scarcely reflected in both diagnostic and rating scales. For instance, the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders classifies mental health disorders primarily based on observable symptoms and behaviors, rather than on the underlying psychological and neurobiological processes that may contribute to these symptoms (Kendler, 2006). Similarly, rating scales for depression are typically designed to assess the severity of symptoms, rather than their underlying causes, that is, most rating scales are used as screening tools to identify individuals who may require further evaluation and treatment. Some rating scales may include items related to causal factors, such as the Beck Depression Inventory-II (BDI-II) includes an item that asks about “loss of interest in sex,” which could be related to either biological or psychological factors. Several rating scales include items assessing risk factors for depression, such as family history of depression or personal history of trauma. This may be indicative of both genetic and environmental risk factors, such as the Patient Health [End Page 255] Questionnaire-9, includes an item that asks about family history of depression. However, while risk and causal factors are related, they are distinct in the assessment of depression. Risk factors refer to factors that increase the likelihood of developing depression, while causal factors refer to factors that directly contribute to the development of the condition. The presence of a risk factor does not necessarily mean that an individual will develop depression (Peterson & Seligman, 1984). However, the two are frequently blurred and equated in psychotherapy research (Westen & Bradley, 2005). As such, the historical issues of rating and diagnostic scales, aptly depicted by the Le Moigne (2023) as full of “composite, if not contradictory, heritage, weaving together the classificatory and discontinuous tradition of psychiatry, on the one hand, and the psychometric and continuous tradition of psychology, on the other” (p. XX&lt;EQ&gt;), suffer from an epistemological oversight when it comes ","PeriodicalId":45397,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology","volume":"2013 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135588419","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Philosophy Psychiatry & Psychology
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1