Unusual claims, normative process: on the use and stringency of the scientific method.

Q Medicine Forschende Komplementarmedizin Pub Date : 2007-06-01 Epub Date: 2007-06-22 DOI:10.1159/000103287
John A Ives, James Giordano
{"title":"Unusual claims, normative process: on the use and stringency of the scientific method.","authors":"John A Ives, James Giordano","doi":"10.1159/000103287","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Do unusual claims require extraordinary proof? A scientific claim is evaluated through application of the scientific method. This involves experimentation (most rigorously in comparison to some form of control) and/or observation. Analyses and descriptions can be quantitative or qualitative, but adherence to stringent criteria to ensure validity of method and outcomes is essential. Claims that have been evaluated by this method are then disseminated through publication and/or presentation so as to be independently tested by other scientists. If such tests support the original claim, then, following a sufficient but indeterminate number of successful replications, the claim and any accompanying hypotheses and theories may be added to the scientific lexicon. If such tests fail to support the original claim, it is questioned and rejected (usually following a lesser number of replication attempts than is required to accept or sustain such claims). These results are commonly considered as ‘proof’ among the non-scientific, lay public. However, this is a misnomer. The process of discarding and/or accepting scientific claims is one of convergence upon ‘a truth’ that is subject to change as a consequence of scientific knowledge itself. Therefore, scientific claims and the truths they seek are always tangential. Unlike a mathematical proof, scientific claims and accompanying hypotheses and theoretical bases are always subject to scrutiny, challenge and revision, based upon both ongoing evaluation of the claim, and intellectual understanding of science and nature, at large. This is true for unusual claims as well as the more mundane. To suggest that something further needs to be applied to scrutinize an unusual claim is to misunderstand the principles of the scientific process, and scientific philosophy. It is of course a truism that all important or groundbreaking claims are by definition ‘unusual’. The elegance of the scientific process is that it addresses and evaluates all claims and discoveries identically. The process itself is progressive as Joshua Roebke claims ‘... science is ... an unending courtship, flirting ever closer with the absolute truth it desires though may never attain’ [2]. The scientific method, though rigorous, is not perfect. But, as Roebke notes, may be ‘... the best tool humans have for discerning facts of the world ...’ and ‘its utility, despite its limitations, earns it our trust’. The process of peer review is only a first step toward solidifying such trust and participating in that courtship. In this issue, such attention may be directed to somewhat ‘unusual’ scientific claims regarding outcomes and mechanisms of homeopathic treatments in which it is claimed that medicinal value may be found in solutions that do not contain the active ingredient. This seems contrary to the established theoretical understanding of pharmacobiology. However, the scientific approach is not to reject a claim simply because it seems implausible or unorthodox. Rather, the scientific approach is to test the claim. Historically, there have been numerous examples of scientific claims that were considered implausible, unorthodox, if not impossible based upon the epistemology of the time and/or culture, but were subsequently validated (e.g. heliocentricism, germ theory, etc.). In hindsight, we recognize that it was our understanding of both the claim and the natural world that was flawed. In this issue of FORSCHENDE KOMPLEMENTARMEDIZIN, Pathak and colleagues seem to have made an implausible claim – that an oral solution with none of the putatively active molecule present can significantly impact the course of hepatic neoplastic disease in a mouse model [3]. They have tested this hypothesis in their laboratories and maintain that there is evidence to support their claim. They have described the conditions under which tests of this hypothesis were performed and have submitted their findings to peer review pursuant to publication in this journal. This is the scientific process.","PeriodicalId":54318,"journal":{"name":"Forschende Komplementarmedizin","volume":"14 3","pages":"138-9"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2007-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1159/000103287","citationCount":"4","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Forschende Komplementarmedizin","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1159/000103287","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"2007/6/22 0:00:00","PubModel":"Epub","JCR":"Q","JCRName":"Medicine","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4

Abstract

Do unusual claims require extraordinary proof? A scientific claim is evaluated through application of the scientific method. This involves experimentation (most rigorously in comparison to some form of control) and/or observation. Analyses and descriptions can be quantitative or qualitative, but adherence to stringent criteria to ensure validity of method and outcomes is essential. Claims that have been evaluated by this method are then disseminated through publication and/or presentation so as to be independently tested by other scientists. If such tests support the original claim, then, following a sufficient but indeterminate number of successful replications, the claim and any accompanying hypotheses and theories may be added to the scientific lexicon. If such tests fail to support the original claim, it is questioned and rejected (usually following a lesser number of replication attempts than is required to accept or sustain such claims). These results are commonly considered as ‘proof’ among the non-scientific, lay public. However, this is a misnomer. The process of discarding and/or accepting scientific claims is one of convergence upon ‘a truth’ that is subject to change as a consequence of scientific knowledge itself. Therefore, scientific claims and the truths they seek are always tangential. Unlike a mathematical proof, scientific claims and accompanying hypotheses and theoretical bases are always subject to scrutiny, challenge and revision, based upon both ongoing evaluation of the claim, and intellectual understanding of science and nature, at large. This is true for unusual claims as well as the more mundane. To suggest that something further needs to be applied to scrutinize an unusual claim is to misunderstand the principles of the scientific process, and scientific philosophy. It is of course a truism that all important or groundbreaking claims are by definition ‘unusual’. The elegance of the scientific process is that it addresses and evaluates all claims and discoveries identically. The process itself is progressive as Joshua Roebke claims ‘... science is ... an unending courtship, flirting ever closer with the absolute truth it desires though may never attain’ [2]. The scientific method, though rigorous, is not perfect. But, as Roebke notes, may be ‘... the best tool humans have for discerning facts of the world ...’ and ‘its utility, despite its limitations, earns it our trust’. The process of peer review is only a first step toward solidifying such trust and participating in that courtship. In this issue, such attention may be directed to somewhat ‘unusual’ scientific claims regarding outcomes and mechanisms of homeopathic treatments in which it is claimed that medicinal value may be found in solutions that do not contain the active ingredient. This seems contrary to the established theoretical understanding of pharmacobiology. However, the scientific approach is not to reject a claim simply because it seems implausible or unorthodox. Rather, the scientific approach is to test the claim. Historically, there have been numerous examples of scientific claims that were considered implausible, unorthodox, if not impossible based upon the epistemology of the time and/or culture, but were subsequently validated (e.g. heliocentricism, germ theory, etc.). In hindsight, we recognize that it was our understanding of both the claim and the natural world that was flawed. In this issue of FORSCHENDE KOMPLEMENTARMEDIZIN, Pathak and colleagues seem to have made an implausible claim – that an oral solution with none of the putatively active molecule present can significantly impact the course of hepatic neoplastic disease in a mouse model [3]. They have tested this hypothesis in their laboratories and maintain that there is evidence to support their claim. They have described the conditions under which tests of this hypothesis were performed and have submitted their findings to peer review pursuant to publication in this journal. This is the scientific process.
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
不寻常的主张,规范的过程:关于使用和严格的科学方法。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
0.40
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
期刊最新文献
Unusual claims, normative process: on the use and stringency of the scientific method. Prospective controlled cohort studies on long-term therapy of cervical cancer patients with a mistletoe preparation (Iscador). Supportive evidence for the anticancerous potential of alternative medicine against hepatocarcinogenesis in mice. [Repeated cold water stimulations (hydrotherapy according to Kneipp) in patients with COPD]. [Evaluation of use of complementary and alternative medicine by schizophrenic patients].
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1