Porphyry’s Commentary on Ptolemy’s Harmonics: A Greek Text and Annotated Translation, edited and translated by Barker, A.

Q1 Arts and Humanities Greek and Roman Musical Studies Pub Date : 2019-03-21 DOI:10.1163/22129758-12341339
L. Taub
{"title":"Porphyry’s Commentary on Ptolemy’s Harmonics: A Greek Text and Annotated Translation, edited and translated by Barker, A.","authors":"L. Taub","doi":"10.1163/22129758-12341339","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"pertinent writings of particular Neoplatonists further to refine and argue for its thesis. In both parts, moreover, H. pays careful attention to previous scholarship pertinent to his topic and thesis. Conspicuously absent from his narrative, though, is analysis or even indication of where Porphyry’s mentor Plotinus fits into the book’s topic – for example, as may be gleaned from his Sixth Ennead and its treatises on being and number. This quibble aside, H.’s narrative and analyses highlight the diversity and plurality among the particular Neoplatonists not only with respect to how much, or to what degree, they discerned doctrinal harmony in Plato’s and Aristotle’s philosophies but also in their methodologies for discerning this. Thus, for example, we find Porphyry carefully critiquing (and criticising) Aristotelian doctrines regarding the soul to discern where Aristotle was correct (and so potentially in agreement with Plato) regarding the soul (pp. 56–8) whereas we find Stephanus of Alexandria purposively reading Aristotle in a manner which would agree with Platonic doctrine, proclaiming that ‘if he [Aristotle] spoke of an unwritten tablet . . . it is because it contains letters that are minuscule and invisible’ (p. 70). Another important corollary toH.’s harmonisation thesis is the fact that, howevermuch a particular Neoplatonist may discern Plato and Aristotle to ‘agree’, also a ‘recurrent feature in late Neoplatonism is the affirmation of the superiority of Plato over Aristotle in everything having to do with questions of metaphysics and theology’ (p. 52). Thus, for example, in reading Syranius we find ‘the distinction between an Aristotle who is more a philosopher of nature, and a Plato who is more of a theologian’ (p. 124). Or, in more general terms, among the Neoplatonists ‘the philosophy of Plato is considered to be higher, more theological, and more inspired as compared to that of Aristotle’ (p. 134) so that even ‘Aristotle’s Metaphysics can only be an intermediary stage between the study of principles and natural causes and the true theology developed byPlato’ (p. 134). Even here, though, there is no singlemonolithicNeoplatonist viewpoint, as Simplicius, for example, maintained that in most cases of seeming differences between Plato and Aristotle ‘the difference between the philosophers is not over a reality, but over a name’ (p. 167); and David (Elias) counsels the exegete not to approach the philosophers’ textsas either aPeripatetic or aPlatonist but to approach themasequals andnot take sides (p. 141). The book’s concluding bibliography of previous scholarship and textual resources is also (again aside from Plotinus) quite thorough and useful.","PeriodicalId":36585,"journal":{"name":"Greek and Roman Musical Studies","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2019-03-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1163/22129758-12341339","citationCount":"3","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Greek and Roman Musical Studies","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1163/22129758-12341339","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"Arts and Humanities","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3

Abstract

pertinent writings of particular Neoplatonists further to refine and argue for its thesis. In both parts, moreover, H. pays careful attention to previous scholarship pertinent to his topic and thesis. Conspicuously absent from his narrative, though, is analysis or even indication of where Porphyry’s mentor Plotinus fits into the book’s topic – for example, as may be gleaned from his Sixth Ennead and its treatises on being and number. This quibble aside, H.’s narrative and analyses highlight the diversity and plurality among the particular Neoplatonists not only with respect to how much, or to what degree, they discerned doctrinal harmony in Plato’s and Aristotle’s philosophies but also in their methodologies for discerning this. Thus, for example, we find Porphyry carefully critiquing (and criticising) Aristotelian doctrines regarding the soul to discern where Aristotle was correct (and so potentially in agreement with Plato) regarding the soul (pp. 56–8) whereas we find Stephanus of Alexandria purposively reading Aristotle in a manner which would agree with Platonic doctrine, proclaiming that ‘if he [Aristotle] spoke of an unwritten tablet . . . it is because it contains letters that are minuscule and invisible’ (p. 70). Another important corollary toH.’s harmonisation thesis is the fact that, howevermuch a particular Neoplatonist may discern Plato and Aristotle to ‘agree’, also a ‘recurrent feature in late Neoplatonism is the affirmation of the superiority of Plato over Aristotle in everything having to do with questions of metaphysics and theology’ (p. 52). Thus, for example, in reading Syranius we find ‘the distinction between an Aristotle who is more a philosopher of nature, and a Plato who is more of a theologian’ (p. 124). Or, in more general terms, among the Neoplatonists ‘the philosophy of Plato is considered to be higher, more theological, and more inspired as compared to that of Aristotle’ (p. 134) so that even ‘Aristotle’s Metaphysics can only be an intermediary stage between the study of principles and natural causes and the true theology developed byPlato’ (p. 134). Even here, though, there is no singlemonolithicNeoplatonist viewpoint, as Simplicius, for example, maintained that in most cases of seeming differences between Plato and Aristotle ‘the difference between the philosophers is not over a reality, but over a name’ (p. 167); and David (Elias) counsels the exegete not to approach the philosophers’ textsas either aPeripatetic or aPlatonist but to approach themasequals andnot take sides (p. 141). The book’s concluding bibliography of previous scholarship and textual resources is also (again aside from Plotinus) quite thorough and useful.
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
波菲利对托勒密和声的评论:希腊文本和注释翻译,巴克主编。
特定新柏拉图主义者的相关著作进一步完善和论证了其论点。此外,在这两部分中,H.都仔细地注意到了以往与他的主题和论文相关的学术研究。然而,在他的叙述中,显然没有分析甚至表明波菲利的导师普罗提努斯在书中的主题中的位置——例如,可以从他的《第六Ennead》及其关于存在和数字的论文中找到。撇开这些狡辩不谈,H.的叙述和分析突出了特定新柏拉图主义者之间的多样性和多样性,不仅是关于他们在柏拉图和亚里士多德的哲学中察觉到了多少或在多大程度上察觉到了教义上的和谐,还包括他们察觉到这一点的方法。因此,例如,我们发现Porphyry仔细地批评(和批评)亚里士多德关于灵魂的学说,以辨别亚里士多德在灵魂方面的正确之处(因此可能与柏拉图一致)(第56-8页),而我们发现亚历山大的Stephanus有目的地以与柏拉图学说一致的方式阅读亚里士多德,宣称“如果他(亚里士多德)谈到一块未成文的石碑。这是因为它包含了微小而不可见的字母(第70页)。H的另一个重要推论他的调和论是这样一个事实,即无论一个特定的新柏拉图主义者如何能辨别出柏拉图和亚里士多德“同意”,“新柏拉图主义晚期的一个反复出现的特征是,在与形而上学和神学问题有关的一切方面,柏拉图都比亚里士多德优越”(第52页)。因此,例如,在阅读《叙拉尼乌斯》时,我们发现“亚里士多德更像是一位自然哲学家,而柏拉图更像是神学家”(第124页)。或者,更一般地说,在新柏拉图主义者中,“与亚里士多德相比,柏拉图的哲学被认为更高、更神学、更受启发”(第134页),因此即使是“亚里士多德的形而上学也只能是原理和自然原因研究与柏拉图发展的真正神学之间的中间阶段”(第34页)。然而,即使在这里,也没有单一的新柏拉图主义观点,例如,Simplicius坚持认为,在柏拉图和亚里士多德之间大多数看似不同的情况下,“哲学家之间的差异不是因为现实,而是因为名字”(第167页);大卫(Elias)建议训诫者不要将哲学家的文本视为泛泛主义者或柏拉图主义者,而是要处理逻辑,不要偏袒任何一方(第141页)。这本书对以往学术和文本资源的总结性参考书目也相当全面和有用(同样除了普罗提诺)。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
Greek and Roman Musical Studies
Greek and Roman Musical Studies Arts and Humanities-Classics
CiteScore
1.70
自引率
0.00%
发文量
23
期刊最新文献
Greek and Latin Texts on the Harp and Similar Instruments in Byzantine Times Echoing the Eleusinian World: Eleusinian Topoi and Sounds in Pindaric Epinician Poetry Pompē, Peplos, Poikilia: Picturing the Panathenaia on an Athenian Amphora Aspects of Roman Dance Culture. Religious Cults, Theatrical Entertainments, Metaphorical Appropriations, edited by Schlapbach, K. Texts, Bodies, Images, Movement
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1