The Fragmented Mind

IF 2.8 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI:10.1215/00318108-10317606
Sara Aronowitz
{"title":"<i>The Fragmented Mind</i>","authors":"Sara Aronowitz","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10317606","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"This excellent volume contains 14 chapters exploring the idea of fragmentation: the division of a belief state into parts (“fragments”) that can represent the world in distinct, jointly incoherent ways. For instance, I might know that sea cucumbers are a type of animal related to starfish when I am asked in a biological context, but when I am at a restaurant and see them on the menu, I think that sea cucumbers are a vegetable. I have two ways of thinking of sea cucumbers, two fragments that are both sets of beliefs about the world but are in some sense separate from each other. Most of the contributions concentrate on whether fragmentation is a good model of belief and how a fragmented state of mind can be rationally evaluated, though the final section contains a paper by Gertler (chap. 13) applying a case of fragmentation and subsequent belief change to a question about agency.While fragmentation theories share the commitment to multiple (potentially) incoherent belief states, this volume reveals a deep divide between two families of views. The first, dispositionalism, holds that what it is to have a fragment is just to be disposed to exhibit a pattern of actions1 that is best explained by more than one set of beliefs (given one’s background beliefs and desires). On this view, fragments are by definition coherent within themselves, and also by definition at odds with one another. For Elga and Rayo (chap. 1) and Greco (chap. 2), at odds means picking out a different set of possible worlds whereas for Yalcin (chap. 6), it means partitioning possible space differently. Representationalists, on the other hand, such as Bendaña and Mandelbaum (chap. 3) or Murez (chap. 7) hold that a fragment is a psychologically real entity. This means that in principle we can ask whether fragments are internally coherent without triviality.This distinction between representationalism and dispositionalism is not just important to broader questions about belief, but directly bears on fragmentation. This is most clear when we consider that many of the questions raised in one of the two frameworks in this volume are not even able to be formulated on the alternative framework. I’ll give two examples.Bendaña and Mandelbaum ask: when do new fragments arise? Their answer is the “Environmental Principle”: new environments open up new fragments, so that if in my Portuguese class, I saw a chart of types of pastry, I might encode these separately (and potentially incoherently) from my stored knowledge of pastries acquired in other contexts. But notice that on the dispositionalist view, fragments arise if and only if one’s behavior is at odds with other parts of behavior, given background beliefs and desires. We can of course ask when behavior comes to be at odds in this way, and perhaps the answer might appeal to contexts. But this is not the same question at all, since Bendaña and Mandelbaum treat the creation of a new fragment as a mental event happening at a particular time. The question of when this event occurs is one that has ordinary efficient causes, such as the prior mental awareness of a new environment. On the contrary, the dispositionalist can only ascribe fragments to swathes of behavior, so there may be no clear beginning to a fragment. Likewise, the question of new fragments leaves open the possibility that, at least in principle, beliefs might be incoherent without acquiring a new fragment and, conversely, that new fragments can arise even when nothing contradictory is represented. That is, it can be true that I have a new fragment relative to Portuguese class without anything being contradictory. But of course, for the dispositionalist, this is conceptually impossible. Thus the question raised (and answered) by Bendaña and Mandelbaum means something quite different to the dispositionalist. Or rather, the real question they are asking, what psychological process makes me break off my representations into new fragments, cannot be asked at all—instead, new fragments are born (and expire) as a matter of conceptual necessity.From the dispositionalist side, Egan asks: “What constraints shall we impose on the proliferation of belief states in order to avoid collapse into triviality and maintain the status of doxastic states as explanatory of behavior rather than as a mere summary or redescription of it?” (123). This question, on the other hand, is ill posed for the representationalist. For her, there is a matter of fact about how many fragments you have and one that is not decided from the point of view of the external modeler. And more importantly, there is no problem of triviality—a person has the number of fragments that she has, and whatever number that is cannot be too many since it reflects her representational capacity.These two questions are instances of a deeper issue dividing this volume. In a sense, all of the fragmentation debate is motivated by incoherence. But there are two very different projects around understanding how we are less than fully logically consistent. The first is the project of understanding how, when, and why we strive to be coherent. (By “striving” I do not necessarily mean first-personal effort but rather the deployment of psychological processing). On the other hand, we might also ask whether and how it is conceptually possible to be incoherent. These questions are not just different but, I would suggest, require different standpoints: the former a view of incoherence between real representations, and the latter a view of incoherence as a function of a whole person. This divide is not a problem with the volume, but it does lend it a somewhat disjointed feeling as authors on either side use similar language and examples to speak at distinct levels.The middle section of the book is devoted to connecting work on fragmentation to the topic of mental files. A mental file is a way of understanding what is going on in Frege cases where, for instance, I inadvertently think of the very same person under two different descriptions (Havel the politician/Havel the playwright). There is obviously a connection between these and fragmentation cases—in fact, it is sometimes hard to distinguish between them, though a difference is that fragmentation emphasizes a difference in propositions that are represented between fragments, whereas mental files emphasize a difference in the mode of presentation of a referent. This connection, while intuitive, has not received much attention, and this kind of work, connecting similar topics across different literatures, is often neglected. Recananti (chap. 9) in particular puts forward an illuminating connection between the two.One doubt I began to have about fragmentation in general started with a point made by Egan. He describes a case where someone can answer the question “Was the youngest von Trapp child’s name ‘Gretl’?” but not “What was the name of the youngest von Trapp child?” (111). After this, he observes, “Here is a puzzling feature of this sort of case: the information required to answer the two questions is exactly the same” (112). This seems false. I need more information to answer the open question about the name. The information cannot be the same since I could much more easily guess the right answer to the yes/no question. Likewise, I could answer the yes/no question by lacking knowledge of the name and just knowing facts such as “the name started with an A.” The question that includes the name contains more information, and I need less information to answer it.Egan is wrong about this case in an interesting way: he, like many of the other authors, seeks to explain the phenomenon of seemingly incoherent patterns of action and behavior through ascribing a more complex mental state to the agent than standard, unified belief. But this excludes, or rather internalizes, the role of the environment. When someone asks you “was the child named Gretl?” she is giving you information that is withheld in the other way of asking the question. But what becomes of this difference on the fragmentation picture?Elga and Rayo get nearest to this question. On their view, belief states are not relations between persons and propositions, but among persons, elicitation conditions, and propositions. Thus, relative to the elicitation condition of being asked this or that question, you are related to different sets of propositions. This does acknowledge the role of the environment, insofar as the elicitation conditions are environmental, and it is not committed to the idea that your beliefs are independent of the environment. But at the same time, the role of the environment is minimized in two ways. First, by including possible environmental conditions in the belief state, Elga and Rayo treat the variability between contexts as a feature of you rather than one shared by anyone in your circumstances. Second, by compiling all the elicitation conditions in a list, they elide differences in information between them: a person who has an easier time answering more informative questions like the yes/no question and a person who has an easier time answering when she is spinning in a circle are modeled as sharing the same kind of relativity to circumstance, whereas intuitively, a question that conveys information has a different kind of influence on belief than a physical motion that merely disposes you to some frame of mind.More generally, I worry that the category of fragmentation cases is heterogeneous between informationally relevant conditions and mere nonrational shifts, and treating them alike would miss that we expect many agents to respond to the von Trapp questions differently and indeed find such a pattern to reflect a rational uptake of implicitly conveyed information. Our relationship to our environments is an important part of the story of how we come to be incoherent, when incoherence is maintained, and how it is even possible, and so a major missing piece from the important work in this book is a focus beyond the agent’s mind.Finally, a striking feature of this book is its contemporary framing. Fragmentation, as introduced in this volume, is an idea originating from Cherniak, Lewis, and Stalnaker. In fact, almost every chapter in this book discusses a case from Lewis revolving around a mental map of Nassau Street. This unity has upsides, in allowing the book to be tightly focused and well-integrated compared to similar volumes. But it did leave me with questions about the broader history of this debate.Among surely many other places, historical antecedents can be found in the many descriptions of internal conflict in the Confessions (Augustine, 2008). In book 7, Augustine begins by describing his state of mind as he in some sense comes to believe that God is immaterial, but at the same time is unable to shake a way of thinking of God as occupying space: My heart vehemently protested against all the physical images in my mind, and by this single blow I attempted to expel from my mind’s eye the swarm of unpurified notions flying about there. Hardly had they been dispersed when in the flash of an eye (i Cor. 15:52) they had regrouped and were back again. They attacked my power of vision and clouded it. Although you were not in the shape of the human body, I nevertheless felt forced to imagine something physical occupying space diffused either in the world or even through infinite space outside the world. Admittedly I thought of this as incorruptible and inviolable and unchangeable, which I set above what is corruptible, violable, and changeable. (111)A few features of Augustine’s presentation of division might shed light on the issue of fragmentation. First, unlike the paradigm cases of fragmentation from this volume, Augustine’s divided state persists despite him noticing it. He may not have had the full understanding of the contradiction he notes in the light of hindsight, but the description implies an effort to dispel the material conception that must reflect some degree of awareness. This seems intuitively possible, though it might already strain some of the views discussed above on which we only reason from one fragment at a time (e.g., Yalcin’s). Second, the conflict is not merely between propositions, or even between fine- and coarse-grained propositions, but between visual and abstract modes of thinking. We could even imagine these differences explain the first feature, why the division can persist despite being noticed.Most interestingly, an affective element pervades Augustine’s description: the relationship between the two states of mind is described as a war. I wonder whether the volume might have benefitted from more engagement with history, especially when it comes to exploring the connection between incoherence and affect that Loeb (1998) traces through the Stoics, Hume, and Peirce. While in Augustine’s case, the feeling of strife and division might draw on awareness of the conflict, there are surely ways to think of the affective side of fragmentation even in cases of partial or minimal awareness. This dimension is significant because it relates to questions of how and when fragments are combined, to the particular recalcitrance of core beliefs as noted by Bendaña and Mandelbaum, and even to the ethically and politically charged issues raised in the section on implicit beliefs. Many of the contributors appeal to the idea that beliefs are a set of maps that we use to steer, but the link with affect suggests that divided states of mind have a motivational force of their own—in the sense that we’re bothered or made uneasy by the division, or even in the sense of each belief substate pushing us and pushing against the others.Overall, this book is a tightly connected collection of papers on a topic at the heart of the intersection between metaphysics of mind and epistemology (with many more compelling contributions than I have room to discuss here). It will be a core resource to anyone interested in diving into this debate.","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"3 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":2.8000,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10317606","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

This excellent volume contains 14 chapters exploring the idea of fragmentation: the division of a belief state into parts (“fragments”) that can represent the world in distinct, jointly incoherent ways. For instance, I might know that sea cucumbers are a type of animal related to starfish when I am asked in a biological context, but when I am at a restaurant and see them on the menu, I think that sea cucumbers are a vegetable. I have two ways of thinking of sea cucumbers, two fragments that are both sets of beliefs about the world but are in some sense separate from each other. Most of the contributions concentrate on whether fragmentation is a good model of belief and how a fragmented state of mind can be rationally evaluated, though the final section contains a paper by Gertler (chap. 13) applying a case of fragmentation and subsequent belief change to a question about agency.While fragmentation theories share the commitment to multiple (potentially) incoherent belief states, this volume reveals a deep divide between two families of views. The first, dispositionalism, holds that what it is to have a fragment is just to be disposed to exhibit a pattern of actions1 that is best explained by more than one set of beliefs (given one’s background beliefs and desires). On this view, fragments are by definition coherent within themselves, and also by definition at odds with one another. For Elga and Rayo (chap. 1) and Greco (chap. 2), at odds means picking out a different set of possible worlds whereas for Yalcin (chap. 6), it means partitioning possible space differently. Representationalists, on the other hand, such as Bendaña and Mandelbaum (chap. 3) or Murez (chap. 7) hold that a fragment is a psychologically real entity. This means that in principle we can ask whether fragments are internally coherent without triviality.This distinction between representationalism and dispositionalism is not just important to broader questions about belief, but directly bears on fragmentation. This is most clear when we consider that many of the questions raised in one of the two frameworks in this volume are not even able to be formulated on the alternative framework. I’ll give two examples.Bendaña and Mandelbaum ask: when do new fragments arise? Their answer is the “Environmental Principle”: new environments open up new fragments, so that if in my Portuguese class, I saw a chart of types of pastry, I might encode these separately (and potentially incoherently) from my stored knowledge of pastries acquired in other contexts. But notice that on the dispositionalist view, fragments arise if and only if one’s behavior is at odds with other parts of behavior, given background beliefs and desires. We can of course ask when behavior comes to be at odds in this way, and perhaps the answer might appeal to contexts. But this is not the same question at all, since Bendaña and Mandelbaum treat the creation of a new fragment as a mental event happening at a particular time. The question of when this event occurs is one that has ordinary efficient causes, such as the prior mental awareness of a new environment. On the contrary, the dispositionalist can only ascribe fragments to swathes of behavior, so there may be no clear beginning to a fragment. Likewise, the question of new fragments leaves open the possibility that, at least in principle, beliefs might be incoherent without acquiring a new fragment and, conversely, that new fragments can arise even when nothing contradictory is represented. That is, it can be true that I have a new fragment relative to Portuguese class without anything being contradictory. But of course, for the dispositionalist, this is conceptually impossible. Thus the question raised (and answered) by Bendaña and Mandelbaum means something quite different to the dispositionalist. Or rather, the real question they are asking, what psychological process makes me break off my representations into new fragments, cannot be asked at all—instead, new fragments are born (and expire) as a matter of conceptual necessity.From the dispositionalist side, Egan asks: “What constraints shall we impose on the proliferation of belief states in order to avoid collapse into triviality and maintain the status of doxastic states as explanatory of behavior rather than as a mere summary or redescription of it?” (123). This question, on the other hand, is ill posed for the representationalist. For her, there is a matter of fact about how many fragments you have and one that is not decided from the point of view of the external modeler. And more importantly, there is no problem of triviality—a person has the number of fragments that she has, and whatever number that is cannot be too many since it reflects her representational capacity.These two questions are instances of a deeper issue dividing this volume. In a sense, all of the fragmentation debate is motivated by incoherence. But there are two very different projects around understanding how we are less than fully logically consistent. The first is the project of understanding how, when, and why we strive to be coherent. (By “striving” I do not necessarily mean first-personal effort but rather the deployment of psychological processing). On the other hand, we might also ask whether and how it is conceptually possible to be incoherent. These questions are not just different but, I would suggest, require different standpoints: the former a view of incoherence between real representations, and the latter a view of incoherence as a function of a whole person. This divide is not a problem with the volume, but it does lend it a somewhat disjointed feeling as authors on either side use similar language and examples to speak at distinct levels.The middle section of the book is devoted to connecting work on fragmentation to the topic of mental files. A mental file is a way of understanding what is going on in Frege cases where, for instance, I inadvertently think of the very same person under two different descriptions (Havel the politician/Havel the playwright). There is obviously a connection between these and fragmentation cases—in fact, it is sometimes hard to distinguish between them, though a difference is that fragmentation emphasizes a difference in propositions that are represented between fragments, whereas mental files emphasize a difference in the mode of presentation of a referent. This connection, while intuitive, has not received much attention, and this kind of work, connecting similar topics across different literatures, is often neglected. Recananti (chap. 9) in particular puts forward an illuminating connection between the two.One doubt I began to have about fragmentation in general started with a point made by Egan. He describes a case where someone can answer the question “Was the youngest von Trapp child’s name ‘Gretl’?” but not “What was the name of the youngest von Trapp child?” (111). After this, he observes, “Here is a puzzling feature of this sort of case: the information required to answer the two questions is exactly the same” (112). This seems false. I need more information to answer the open question about the name. The information cannot be the same since I could much more easily guess the right answer to the yes/no question. Likewise, I could answer the yes/no question by lacking knowledge of the name and just knowing facts such as “the name started with an A.” The question that includes the name contains more information, and I need less information to answer it.Egan is wrong about this case in an interesting way: he, like many of the other authors, seeks to explain the phenomenon of seemingly incoherent patterns of action and behavior through ascribing a more complex mental state to the agent than standard, unified belief. But this excludes, or rather internalizes, the role of the environment. When someone asks you “was the child named Gretl?” she is giving you information that is withheld in the other way of asking the question. But what becomes of this difference on the fragmentation picture?Elga and Rayo get nearest to this question. On their view, belief states are not relations between persons and propositions, but among persons, elicitation conditions, and propositions. Thus, relative to the elicitation condition of being asked this or that question, you are related to different sets of propositions. This does acknowledge the role of the environment, insofar as the elicitation conditions are environmental, and it is not committed to the idea that your beliefs are independent of the environment. But at the same time, the role of the environment is minimized in two ways. First, by including possible environmental conditions in the belief state, Elga and Rayo treat the variability between contexts as a feature of you rather than one shared by anyone in your circumstances. Second, by compiling all the elicitation conditions in a list, they elide differences in information between them: a person who has an easier time answering more informative questions like the yes/no question and a person who has an easier time answering when she is spinning in a circle are modeled as sharing the same kind of relativity to circumstance, whereas intuitively, a question that conveys information has a different kind of influence on belief than a physical motion that merely disposes you to some frame of mind.More generally, I worry that the category of fragmentation cases is heterogeneous between informationally relevant conditions and mere nonrational shifts, and treating them alike would miss that we expect many agents to respond to the von Trapp questions differently and indeed find such a pattern to reflect a rational uptake of implicitly conveyed information. Our relationship to our environments is an important part of the story of how we come to be incoherent, when incoherence is maintained, and how it is even possible, and so a major missing piece from the important work in this book is a focus beyond the agent’s mind.Finally, a striking feature of this book is its contemporary framing. Fragmentation, as introduced in this volume, is an idea originating from Cherniak, Lewis, and Stalnaker. In fact, almost every chapter in this book discusses a case from Lewis revolving around a mental map of Nassau Street. This unity has upsides, in allowing the book to be tightly focused and well-integrated compared to similar volumes. But it did leave me with questions about the broader history of this debate.Among surely many other places, historical antecedents can be found in the many descriptions of internal conflict in the Confessions (Augustine, 2008). In book 7, Augustine begins by describing his state of mind as he in some sense comes to believe that God is immaterial, but at the same time is unable to shake a way of thinking of God as occupying space: My heart vehemently protested against all the physical images in my mind, and by this single blow I attempted to expel from my mind’s eye the swarm of unpurified notions flying about there. Hardly had they been dispersed when in the flash of an eye (i Cor. 15:52) they had regrouped and were back again. They attacked my power of vision and clouded it. Although you were not in the shape of the human body, I nevertheless felt forced to imagine something physical occupying space diffused either in the world or even through infinite space outside the world. Admittedly I thought of this as incorruptible and inviolable and unchangeable, which I set above what is corruptible, violable, and changeable. (111)A few features of Augustine’s presentation of division might shed light on the issue of fragmentation. First, unlike the paradigm cases of fragmentation from this volume, Augustine’s divided state persists despite him noticing it. He may not have had the full understanding of the contradiction he notes in the light of hindsight, but the description implies an effort to dispel the material conception that must reflect some degree of awareness. This seems intuitively possible, though it might already strain some of the views discussed above on which we only reason from one fragment at a time (e.g., Yalcin’s). Second, the conflict is not merely between propositions, or even between fine- and coarse-grained propositions, but between visual and abstract modes of thinking. We could even imagine these differences explain the first feature, why the division can persist despite being noticed.Most interestingly, an affective element pervades Augustine’s description: the relationship between the two states of mind is described as a war. I wonder whether the volume might have benefitted from more engagement with history, especially when it comes to exploring the connection between incoherence and affect that Loeb (1998) traces through the Stoics, Hume, and Peirce. While in Augustine’s case, the feeling of strife and division might draw on awareness of the conflict, there are surely ways to think of the affective side of fragmentation even in cases of partial or minimal awareness. This dimension is significant because it relates to questions of how and when fragments are combined, to the particular recalcitrance of core beliefs as noted by Bendaña and Mandelbaum, and even to the ethically and politically charged issues raised in the section on implicit beliefs. Many of the contributors appeal to the idea that beliefs are a set of maps that we use to steer, but the link with affect suggests that divided states of mind have a motivational force of their own—in the sense that we’re bothered or made uneasy by the division, or even in the sense of each belief substate pushing us and pushing against the others.Overall, this book is a tightly connected collection of papers on a topic at the heart of the intersection between metaphysics of mind and epistemology (with many more compelling contributions than I have room to discuss here). It will be a core resource to anyone interested in diving into this debate.
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
支离破碎的心灵
但是有两个非常不同的项目是关于理解为什么我们不是完全逻辑一致的。第一个是了解我们如何、何时以及为什么努力保持连贯的项目。(我所说的“努力”不一定是指第一人称的努力,而是指心理过程的运用)。另一方面,我们也可能会问,不连贯在概念上是否可能以及如何可能。这些问题不仅不同,而且我认为,需要不同的立场:前者是对真实表象之间不连贯的看法,后者是对作为整个人的功能的不连贯的看法。这种分歧对全书来说不是问题,但它确实给人一种有点脱节的感觉,因为双方的作者都使用类似的语言和例子来表达不同的层次。本书的中间部分致力于将碎片化的研究与心理档案的主题联系起来。心理档案是一种理解弗雷格案例中发生的事情的方式,例如,我无意中以两种不同的描述(哈维尔是政治家/哈维尔是剧作家)想到同一个人。很明显,这些和碎片案例之间有联系——事实上,有时很难区分它们,尽管区别在于碎片强调的是在碎片之间表征的命题的差异,而心理档案强调的是指称的呈现模式的差异。这种联系虽然直观,但并没有受到太多关注,而这种将不同文献中的类似主题联系起来的工作往往被忽视。Recananti(第9章)特别提出了两者之间具有启发性的联系。我对碎片化的一个疑问始于伊根的一个观点。他描述了一个案例,在这个案例中,有人可以回答这个问题:“冯·特拉普最小的孩子的名字是‘格雷特’吗?”而不是“冯·特拉普家最小的孩子叫什么名字?””(111)。在此之后,他观察到,“这类案例有一个令人困惑的特点:回答这两个问题所需的信息完全相同”(112)。这似乎是错误的。我需要更多的信息来回答关于名字的悬而未决的问题。信息不可能是相同的,因为我可以更容易地猜出是/否问题的正确答案。同样,我也可以在不知道名字的情况下回答“是/否”问题,只知道“名字以a开头”这样的事实。包含名字的问题包含了更多的信息,我需要更少的信息来回答它。在这个案例中,伊根以一种有趣的方式错了:他和其他许多作者一样,试图通过将一种比标准的、统一的信念更复杂的心理状态归因于行为人,来解释看似不连贯的行动和行为模式。但这排除了环境的作用,或者说内化了环境的作用。当有人问你“这个孩子叫格里托吗?”“她是在向你提供其他提问方式所隐瞒的信息。但在碎片化的图景中,这种差异会变成什么呢?埃尔加和雷奥最接近这个问题。在他们看来,信念状态不是人与命题之间的关系,而是人、引出条件和命题之间的关系。因此,相对于被问这个或那个问题的引出条件,你与不同的命题集有关。这确实承认了环境的作用,只要启发条件是环境的,它不致力于你的信念独立于环境的观点。但与此同时,环境的作用在两个方面被最小化了。首先,通过在信念状态中包含可能的环境条件,Elga和Rayo将环境之间的可变性视为你的特征,而不是你所处环境中的任何人所共有的特征。第二,通过将所有的激发条件汇编成一个列表,从而忽略了它们之间的信息差异:一个人更容易回答像“是/否”这样的信息量更大的问题,一个人更容易回答当她在一个圆圈里旋转时,被建模为与环境有相同的相对性,然而,从直觉上讲,一个传达信息的问题对信念的影响不同于一个仅仅让你进入某种心境的物理运动。更一般地说,我担心碎片案例的类别在信息相关条件和仅仅非理性转移之间是异质的,并且将它们视为相同会错过我们期望许多代理以不同的方式回应冯特拉普问题,并确实找到这样一种模式来反映对隐含传达信息的理性吸收。 我们与环境的关系是我们如何变得不连贯,何时保持不连贯,以及这种不连贯是如何可能的故事的重要组成部分,因此,这本书中重要的工作中缺少的一个重要部分是超越主体思想的关注。最后,这本书的一个显著特点是它的当代框架。本卷中介绍的碎片化是一种源自切尔尼亚克、刘易斯和斯托纳克的思想。事实上,这本书的几乎每一章都在讨论刘易斯关于拿骚街地图的一个案例。与同类书籍相比,这种统一性有其优点,可以使本书紧密地集中在一起,并且集成良好。但这确实让我对这场辩论的更广泛的历史产生了疑问。当然,在许多其他地方,可以在《忏悔录》中对内部冲突的许多描述中找到历史先例(奥古斯丁,2008)。在第7卷中,奥古斯丁开始描述他的精神状态,因为他在某种意义上开始相信上帝是非物质的,但同时又无法摆脱上帝占据空间的思维方式:我的心强烈地抗议我脑海中所有的物质形象,通过这一次打击,我试图从我的脑海中驱逐那些飞来的未经净化的观念。他们刚被分散,一眨眼(林前十五:52)就又聚集回来了。他们攻击了我的视力,使它变得模糊不清。虽然你不是人体的形状,但我还是觉得有一种物质占据了世界中扩散的空间,甚至穿越了世界之外的无限空间。诚然,我认为这是不可腐蚀的,不可侵犯的,不可改变的,我把它放在可腐蚀的,不可侵犯的,可改变的东西之上。(111)奥古斯丁关于分裂的陈述的几个特点可能会对分裂的问题有所启发。首先,与本书中分裂的范例不同,奥古斯丁的分裂状态持续存在,尽管他注意到了这一点。他可能没有完全理解他在事后指出的矛盾,但这种描述暗示了一种消除物质概念的努力,这种物质概念必须反映某种程度的意识。这似乎在直觉上是可能的,尽管它可能已经影响了上面讨论的一些观点,即我们一次只能从一个片段进行推理(例如,Yalcin的)。其次,冲突不仅存在于命题之间,甚至不存在于细粒度命题与粗粒度命题之间,还存在于视觉思维模式与抽象思维模式之间。我们甚至可以想象这些差异解释了第一个特征,为什么尽管被注意到,分裂仍然存在。最有趣的是,奥古斯丁的描述中弥漫着一种情感因素:两种精神状态之间的关系被描述为一场战争。我想知道这本书是否可以从更多的历史接触中受益,特别是当它涉及到探索不连贯和影响之间的联系时,Loeb(1998)追溯了斯多葛学派、休谟和皮尔斯。虽然在奥古斯丁的例子中,冲突和分裂的感觉可能会引起对冲突的意识,但肯定有办法思考分裂的情感方面,即使是在部分或最小意识的情况下。这个维度很重要,因为它涉及到如何以及何时将碎片组合在一起的问题,涉及到Bendaña和曼德尔鲍姆所指出的核心信仰的特殊顽固性,甚至涉及到隐含信仰部分提出的道德和政治问题。许多作者认为信念是一组我们用来引导的地图,但与情感的联系表明,分裂的精神状态有其自身的动力——从某种意义上说,我们被这种分裂所困扰或不安,甚至从某种意义上说,每个信念的子状态都在推动我们,并推动其他信念。总的来说,这本书是一本紧密相连的论文合集,其主题是心灵形而上学和认识论之间交叉的核心(其中有许多令人信服的贡献,超出了我在这里讨论的空间)。对于任何有兴趣深入这场辩论的人来说,这将是一个核心资源。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW PHILOSOPHY-
CiteScore
7.40
自引率
0.00%
发文量
17
期刊介绍: In continuous publication since 1892, the Philosophical Review has a long-standing reputation for excellence and has published many papers now considered classics in the field, such as W. V. O. Quine"s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” Thomas Nagel"s “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” and the early work of John Rawls. The journal aims to publish original scholarly work in all areas of analytic philosophy, with an emphasis on material of general interest to academic philosophers, and is one of the few journals in the discipline to publish book reviews.
期刊最新文献
Reasons First Dark Matters: Pessimism and the Problem of Suffering Democratic Law Sustaining Democracy: What We Owe to the Other Side Mind and World in Aristotle’s De Anima
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1