Mind and World in Aristotle’s De Anima

IF 2.8 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW Pub Date : 2023-07-01 DOI:10.1215/00318108-10469525
Emily Kress
{"title":"<i>Mind and World in Aristotle’s</i> De Anima","authors":"Emily Kress","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10469525","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Here is a fact about humans: we use our senses to pick up on things around us and our intellect to understand whatever is out there to be understood. In Mind and World in Aristotle’s De Anima, Kelsey argues that this fact is, in Aristotle’s view, in need of an explanation. He finds one in De Anima 3.8’s suggestion that “intelligence [is] form of forms, and sensibility form of sensibilia” (432a2–3; quoted on p. 2). Roughly, his proposal is that our sensibility and intelligence “enter into the very idea” of their objects; they know them because they help make them what they are (20).This is an admirably adventurous thesis, and Kelsey’s arguments for it are likewise so. A particular strength, in fact, is the way the book brings out what is at stake philosophically in familiar and seemingly obscure doctrines alike. Two highlights, which I discuss below, are its discussions of how Aristotle’s engagement with his predecessors shapes his questions (and then makes it hard to answer them) and of how his account of perceptible qualities helps him meet this challenge. This book is therefore a significant contribution to scholarship on the De Anima (DA), and it will be of great value to scholars working on Aristotle’s philosophy of mind. Part of what makes it valuable, moreover, is how it encourages us to ask better questions about core Aristotelian doctrines: while some of Kelsey’s proposals (especially his account of per se causation, which I discuss below) are provocative, they are always productively so.The introduction sets up Kelsey’s core question. It is: “What about” our sensibility and intelligence “makes” them “subject[s] of” some “attribute” (6)? What must they be they like—in their essence (8)—to know what they do? The next three chapters argue that the DA is concerned to answer this question, and, moreover, to do so in a particular way: to show why sensibility and intelligence know “real beings” as they really are—not as they appear.Kelsey’s argument for this claim is a highlight of the book. It takes off from the observation that DA 2.5 answers two foundational questions in a way that, according to DA 3.3, should be problematic. These are: (A) whether perceivers and perceptibles “are like or unlike,” and (B) “whether perceiving is a matter of ‘being affected’ or ‘altered’” (40). The difficulty is that 2.5 wants to answer that perception is (A∗) like-by-like and (B∗) a case of being altered—where 3.3 suggests that those very commitments got Aristotle’s predecessors into trouble. Those thinkers held that “both understanding and judging are held to be like a kind of perceiving” (427a17–b6), apparently because they thought these are (A∗) like-by-like and (B∗) being altered (43).This “diagnosis,” Kelsey argues, is interesting because it “connects” (A∗) and (B∗) to another question: whether “how things are” just is “how they appear” (43). (A∗), for instance, reflects the view that “our judgments are … the mere projecting of a random and fluctuating piece of ourselves,” so that that our “verdicts” are like us, not things as they are (45). And (B∗) expresses the view (roughly) that in acquiring the state in virtue of which we perceive and judge, we come to judge differently (because we get altered), but not better. This puts the resulting judgments—also alterations—all “on a par,” so that all appearances are true (47–49). The upshot is that what lies behind (A) and (B) is the question of whether knowledge and perception get at things as they really are (43).How, then, can 2.5 safely claim that perceiving is like-by-like and a case of being altered? Kelsey’s answer is that it revises (A∗) and (B∗) to avoid the difficulties 3.3 identifies. The improved version of (A∗) turns out to be an application of the view that “having been affected by something is a matter of having become what the affecting agent is in the business of making things be” (53). This principle then does important work: applied to perception, it entails that it belongs “to colors by nature to be seen.” This means that we are like the things we perceive because it is in their nature to make us be like them—and so we perceive them as they are, not as they appear (54–55). (B∗) gets likewise qualified: one way of being altered—which perceivers experience in perception—is “being busy upon [one’s] appointed work” (58).This is an ingenious argument with significant upshots. One is a richer sense of the importance 2.5 attaches to (A) and (B). Another is a clearer sense of the work that Aristotle’s theory of per se causation can do—and the questions that we need to ask about it. This emerges from Kelsey’s discussion of the principle that “having been affected by something is a matter of having become what the affecting agent is in the business of making things be,” which he glosses as the claim that “(accidents apart) the way things interact is in line with their respective natures” (54).Kelsey’s account of this principle is a welcome and important addition to the literature, and it will undoubtedly spark debate. In Kelsey’s formulation, the principle is quite strong—as, indeed, it needs to be in order to justify the claim that it is in the nature of colors to be seen by us. Kelsey’s idea appears to be that the principle lets us take the full specification of the effect of an agent’s exercising some power on a patient and read off it the correct specification of that power. In Kelsey’s example, “pavement does not just happen to afford automobiles a smooth ride, that is what it is for” (54). Pavement’s effect is a smooth ride—because it has in its nature a power for this. (Thus, the agent’s “business” is what it has “a power of making things be”—its “defining work” [53].)If this is right, there is pressure to ensure we specify the effect from which we read off the agent’s power in just the right way. At a minimum, we must find the per se effect. After all, while mudflats do afford cars a smooth ride, their per se effect on cars is something else—for they, unlike pavement, surely do not have a power for affording smooth rides. The lesson is that our specification of the effect should omit things it is not plausible to think the agent has a power for. This sharpening, however, may make us wonder about the idea that in being perceived, a perceptible object exercises a power for “revealing itself” to sentient creatures (55)—a claim that is an important piece of groundwork for Kelsey’s ultimate view that sensibility is part of the form of perceptible objects.Another question concerns how best to characterize the dialectic between Aristotle and his predecessors about (A∗). In Kelsey’s discussion of 3.3, the relata of the likeness are “the qualities of the persons passing judgment” and the “verdicts” they issue (“what judges ‘see’”) (45). In his discussion of 2.5, they are “sentient creatures” and the “objects they perceive”—which “appear as they do thanks in part to something of them” (54–55). These two formulations raise an interesting question about the extent to which Aristotle is maintaining his predecessors’ picture of the explanandum: if the objects’ “appear[ing]” this way is the “verdict” we issue, he will have kept his predecessors’ formulation of the relata and revised his explanation of their likeness—but if it is their effect on sentient creatures while they are perceiving, he will have modified their conception of the relata too.With this groundwork in place, the next two chapters introduce two ingredients in Kelsey’s answer to his original question. The first builds on his account of like-by-like causation; this, he argues, requires “likeness in form” (69). The second expands on those forms, appealing to the notion of a “measure.” Measures, Kelsey argues, are not just like but also “conceptually prior to the objects known by them” (85). Purple, for instance, lies on a spectrum characterized by a “mean” or “middle”; moreover, it is “in the nature of” purple to lie “on one side or the other” of that middle (92–95). But, the next chapter argues, this middle is itself defined with reference to sensibility—which is its measure (see also 434a9; quoted on p. 100). When DA 2.12 defines sensibility as “a kind of ratio” (424a27–28)—itself a middle (424a4–5)—its point is that sensibility is a form that is the measure of perceptible forms (103–17). The upshot is that sensibility knows purple, because sensibility “enter[s] into” purple’s nature (90–91; see also 112–17). Something similar holds in the case of intelligence. The last two chapters therefore argue, roughly, that intelligence is a measure of its objects, insofar as “the clarity and distinctness which characterize its activity are (as it were) the very form” of those objects—what makes them intelligible (154).This section again sheds helpful new light on familiar doctrines. In Kelsey’s hands, Aristotle’s view that sensibility is a “middle” is not just an arcane detail or a convenient explanation of our ability to discriminate a variety of qualities but a reflection of their very nature—one that is well equipped to explain why we perceive them as they are. Kelsey’s book is to be commended not only for sketching a promising new position but for compelling us to get clear on what it would be to answer the question it addresses.Kelsey’s reasoning here, of course, is not uncontroversial. Consider his claim that where qualities lie on a spectrum, “each particular quality” “will lie” either “in the middle” or “on one side of the spectrum,” “by its very nature” (95). Why “by its very nature”? Kelsey’s answer is that it is “composed of” contraries according to a particular “ratio” (94)—one that makes it lie in such a position “in its very own nature” (94). But if this is the evidence that perceptible qualities are defined with reference to the middle, it may be challenging to reject the alternative view that they are “defined by the ‘ratios’” of contraries (95n18).1 For the reason they are defined with reference to the middle is that their ratio gives them the features that situate them with respect to it—and it is hard to see how the ratio can do this if it is not in their nature.Kelsey’s position, as the book’s conclusion emphasizes, is a surprising one: it assigns “a kind of priority—the priority of measure to measured” to sensibility and intelligence to what they perceive and understand (159). This, I would emphasize, is a welcome surprise: by clearly identifying the considerations that might push Aristotle to such a position, Kelsey’s excellent book opens up new questions and makes sure we think hard about what they are asking.Many thanks to Reier Helle for helpful comments on a draft of this review.","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.8000,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10469525","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Here is a fact about humans: we use our senses to pick up on things around us and our intellect to understand whatever is out there to be understood. In Mind and World in Aristotle’s De Anima, Kelsey argues that this fact is, in Aristotle’s view, in need of an explanation. He finds one in De Anima 3.8’s suggestion that “intelligence [is] form of forms, and sensibility form of sensibilia” (432a2–3; quoted on p. 2). Roughly, his proposal is that our sensibility and intelligence “enter into the very idea” of their objects; they know them because they help make them what they are (20).This is an admirably adventurous thesis, and Kelsey’s arguments for it are likewise so. A particular strength, in fact, is the way the book brings out what is at stake philosophically in familiar and seemingly obscure doctrines alike. Two highlights, which I discuss below, are its discussions of how Aristotle’s engagement with his predecessors shapes his questions (and then makes it hard to answer them) and of how his account of perceptible qualities helps him meet this challenge. This book is therefore a significant contribution to scholarship on the De Anima (DA), and it will be of great value to scholars working on Aristotle’s philosophy of mind. Part of what makes it valuable, moreover, is how it encourages us to ask better questions about core Aristotelian doctrines: while some of Kelsey’s proposals (especially his account of per se causation, which I discuss below) are provocative, they are always productively so.The introduction sets up Kelsey’s core question. It is: “What about” our sensibility and intelligence “makes” them “subject[s] of” some “attribute” (6)? What must they be they like—in their essence (8)—to know what they do? The next three chapters argue that the DA is concerned to answer this question, and, moreover, to do so in a particular way: to show why sensibility and intelligence know “real beings” as they really are—not as they appear.Kelsey’s argument for this claim is a highlight of the book. It takes off from the observation that DA 2.5 answers two foundational questions in a way that, according to DA 3.3, should be problematic. These are: (A) whether perceivers and perceptibles “are like or unlike,” and (B) “whether perceiving is a matter of ‘being affected’ or ‘altered’” (40). The difficulty is that 2.5 wants to answer that perception is (A∗) like-by-like and (B∗) a case of being altered—where 3.3 suggests that those very commitments got Aristotle’s predecessors into trouble. Those thinkers held that “both understanding and judging are held to be like a kind of perceiving” (427a17–b6), apparently because they thought these are (A∗) like-by-like and (B∗) being altered (43).This “diagnosis,” Kelsey argues, is interesting because it “connects” (A∗) and (B∗) to another question: whether “how things are” just is “how they appear” (43). (A∗), for instance, reflects the view that “our judgments are … the mere projecting of a random and fluctuating piece of ourselves,” so that that our “verdicts” are like us, not things as they are (45). And (B∗) expresses the view (roughly) that in acquiring the state in virtue of which we perceive and judge, we come to judge differently (because we get altered), but not better. This puts the resulting judgments—also alterations—all “on a par,” so that all appearances are true (47–49). The upshot is that what lies behind (A) and (B) is the question of whether knowledge and perception get at things as they really are (43).How, then, can 2.5 safely claim that perceiving is like-by-like and a case of being altered? Kelsey’s answer is that it revises (A∗) and (B∗) to avoid the difficulties 3.3 identifies. The improved version of (A∗) turns out to be an application of the view that “having been affected by something is a matter of having become what the affecting agent is in the business of making things be” (53). This principle then does important work: applied to perception, it entails that it belongs “to colors by nature to be seen.” This means that we are like the things we perceive because it is in their nature to make us be like them—and so we perceive them as they are, not as they appear (54–55). (B∗) gets likewise qualified: one way of being altered—which perceivers experience in perception—is “being busy upon [one’s] appointed work” (58).This is an ingenious argument with significant upshots. One is a richer sense of the importance 2.5 attaches to (A) and (B). Another is a clearer sense of the work that Aristotle’s theory of per se causation can do—and the questions that we need to ask about it. This emerges from Kelsey’s discussion of the principle that “having been affected by something is a matter of having become what the affecting agent is in the business of making things be,” which he glosses as the claim that “(accidents apart) the way things interact is in line with their respective natures” (54).Kelsey’s account of this principle is a welcome and important addition to the literature, and it will undoubtedly spark debate. In Kelsey’s formulation, the principle is quite strong—as, indeed, it needs to be in order to justify the claim that it is in the nature of colors to be seen by us. Kelsey’s idea appears to be that the principle lets us take the full specification of the effect of an agent’s exercising some power on a patient and read off it the correct specification of that power. In Kelsey’s example, “pavement does not just happen to afford automobiles a smooth ride, that is what it is for” (54). Pavement’s effect is a smooth ride—because it has in its nature a power for this. (Thus, the agent’s “business” is what it has “a power of making things be”—its “defining work” [53].)If this is right, there is pressure to ensure we specify the effect from which we read off the agent’s power in just the right way. At a minimum, we must find the per se effect. After all, while mudflats do afford cars a smooth ride, their per se effect on cars is something else—for they, unlike pavement, surely do not have a power for affording smooth rides. The lesson is that our specification of the effect should omit things it is not plausible to think the agent has a power for. This sharpening, however, may make us wonder about the idea that in being perceived, a perceptible object exercises a power for “revealing itself” to sentient creatures (55)—a claim that is an important piece of groundwork for Kelsey’s ultimate view that sensibility is part of the form of perceptible objects.Another question concerns how best to characterize the dialectic between Aristotle and his predecessors about (A∗). In Kelsey’s discussion of 3.3, the relata of the likeness are “the qualities of the persons passing judgment” and the “verdicts” they issue (“what judges ‘see’”) (45). In his discussion of 2.5, they are “sentient creatures” and the “objects they perceive”—which “appear as they do thanks in part to something of them” (54–55). These two formulations raise an interesting question about the extent to which Aristotle is maintaining his predecessors’ picture of the explanandum: if the objects’ “appear[ing]” this way is the “verdict” we issue, he will have kept his predecessors’ formulation of the relata and revised his explanation of their likeness—but if it is their effect on sentient creatures while they are perceiving, he will have modified their conception of the relata too.With this groundwork in place, the next two chapters introduce two ingredients in Kelsey’s answer to his original question. The first builds on his account of like-by-like causation; this, he argues, requires “likeness in form” (69). The second expands on those forms, appealing to the notion of a “measure.” Measures, Kelsey argues, are not just like but also “conceptually prior to the objects known by them” (85). Purple, for instance, lies on a spectrum characterized by a “mean” or “middle”; moreover, it is “in the nature of” purple to lie “on one side or the other” of that middle (92–95). But, the next chapter argues, this middle is itself defined with reference to sensibility—which is its measure (see also 434a9; quoted on p. 100). When DA 2.12 defines sensibility as “a kind of ratio” (424a27–28)—itself a middle (424a4–5)—its point is that sensibility is a form that is the measure of perceptible forms (103–17). The upshot is that sensibility knows purple, because sensibility “enter[s] into” purple’s nature (90–91; see also 112–17). Something similar holds in the case of intelligence. The last two chapters therefore argue, roughly, that intelligence is a measure of its objects, insofar as “the clarity and distinctness which characterize its activity are (as it were) the very form” of those objects—what makes them intelligible (154).This section again sheds helpful new light on familiar doctrines. In Kelsey’s hands, Aristotle’s view that sensibility is a “middle” is not just an arcane detail or a convenient explanation of our ability to discriminate a variety of qualities but a reflection of their very nature—one that is well equipped to explain why we perceive them as they are. Kelsey’s book is to be commended not only for sketching a promising new position but for compelling us to get clear on what it would be to answer the question it addresses.Kelsey’s reasoning here, of course, is not uncontroversial. Consider his claim that where qualities lie on a spectrum, “each particular quality” “will lie” either “in the middle” or “on one side of the spectrum,” “by its very nature” (95). Why “by its very nature”? Kelsey’s answer is that it is “composed of” contraries according to a particular “ratio” (94)—one that makes it lie in such a position “in its very own nature” (94). But if this is the evidence that perceptible qualities are defined with reference to the middle, it may be challenging to reject the alternative view that they are “defined by the ‘ratios’” of contraries (95n18).1 For the reason they are defined with reference to the middle is that their ratio gives them the features that situate them with respect to it—and it is hard to see how the ratio can do this if it is not in their nature.Kelsey’s position, as the book’s conclusion emphasizes, is a surprising one: it assigns “a kind of priority—the priority of measure to measured” to sensibility and intelligence to what they perceive and understand (159). This, I would emphasize, is a welcome surprise: by clearly identifying the considerations that might push Aristotle to such a position, Kelsey’s excellent book opens up new questions and makes sure we think hard about what they are asking.Many thanks to Reier Helle for helpful comments on a draft of this review.
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
亚里士多德《论动物》中的精神与世界
这是一个关于人类的事实:我们用我们的感官来感知我们周围的事物,用我们的智力来理解任何需要理解的东西。在亚里士多德的《论阿尼玛》中的《心灵与世界》中,凯尔西认为,在亚里士多德看来,这个事实需要一个解释。他在《论阿尼玛》3.8中找到了一个,即“智力是形式的形式,感性是感性的形式”(432a2-3;粗略地说,他的建议是,我们的感性和智慧“进入到它们的对象的理念之中”;他们了解他们,因为他们帮助他们成为现在的样子。这是一个令人钦佩的冒险命题,凯尔西对此的论证也同样如此。事实上,这本书的一个特别之处在于,它揭示了在熟悉的和看似模糊的教义中,哲学上的利害关系。我将在下面讨论两个重点,一是讨论亚里士多德与前人的接触如何塑造了他的问题(然后使这些问题难以回答),二是他对可感知品质的描述如何帮助他应对这一挑战。因此,这本书是对《阿尼马论》(DA)学术研究的重要贡献,对研究亚里士多德心灵哲学的学者具有重要价值。此外,本书之所以有价值,部分原因在于它鼓励我们对亚里士多德的核心学说提出更好的问题:虽然凯尔西的一些建议(尤其是他对自身因果关系的解释,我将在下面讨论)具有挑衅性,但它们总是富有成效的。引言部分提出了凯尔西的核心问题。它是:“为什么”我们的“感性和智慧”使“他们”成为“某些属性”的主体?他们必须是什么样的人——他们的本质(8)——才能知道他们在做什么?接下来的三章认为,DA关注的是回答这个问题,而且,以一种特殊的方式来回答这个问题:说明为什么感性和智力知道“真实的存在”是什么样子,而不是它们看起来的样子。凯尔西对这一观点的论证是本书的一大亮点。它源于这样一种观察,即DA 2.5以一种根据DA 3.3应该存在问题的方式回答了两个基本问题。它们是:(A)感知者和被感知者是否“相似或不同”,以及(B)“感知是‘被影响’还是‘被改变’的问题”(40)。困难在于,第2.5节要回答的是,知觉是(A *)同类的知觉,(B *)被改变的知觉——而第3.3节指出,正是这些行为使亚里士多德的前人陷入麻烦。那些思想家认为“理解和判断都被认为是类似于一种感知”(427a17-b6),显然是因为他们认为这两者是(a *)相似的,(B *)被改变的(43)。Kelsey认为,这个“诊断”很有趣,因为它将(A∗)和(B∗)与另一个问题“联系起来”:“事物是怎样的”是否只是“它们是怎样出现的”(43)。例如,(A *)反映了这样一种观点,即“我们的判断……仅仅是我们自身随机和波动部分的投射”,因此,我们的“判断”就像我们一样,而不是事物的本来面貌(45)。并且(B *)(粗略地)表达了这样一种观点,即在获得我们赖以感知和判断的状态时,我们的判断会变得不同(因为我们被改变了),而不是更好。这就把由此产生的判断——也包括变化——都“平起平坐”,因此所有的表象都是真实的(47-49)。结论是,(A)和(B)的背后是一个问题,即知识和知觉是否了解事物的本来面目。那么,2.5怎么能有把握地宣称感知是相似的,是被改变的呢?Kelsey的回答是,它修正了(A∗)和(B∗)以避免3.3指出的困难。(A *)的改进版本被证明是一种观点的应用,即“受到某物的影响是指已经成为影响因素在使事物成为那样的事情”(53)。这一原则随后发挥了重要作用:将其应用于感知,它意味着它属于“自然可见的颜色”。这意味着我们与我们所感知的事物相似,因为它们的本性使我们与它们相似——因此我们感知它们的是它们的本来面目,而不是它们的表象(54-55)。(B *)也得到了同样的限定:一种被改变的方式——感知者在感知中体验到的——是“忙于[某人]指定的工作”。这是一个具有重要意义的巧妙论点。一个是对2.5对(a)和(B)的重要性有了更丰富的认识。另一个是对亚里士多德因果关系本身理论所能做的工作有了更清晰的认识,以及我们需要提出的问题。这是从Kelsey关于“被某物影响就是成为影响者在创造事物中所扮演的角色”这一原则的讨论中出现的,他将这一原则解释为“(除了意外)事物相互作用的方式符合它们各自的性质”(54)。 凯尔西对这一原则的描述是对文献的一个受欢迎和重要的补充,它无疑会引发辩论。在凯尔西的表述中,这个原则是相当有力的——事实上,为了证明我们能看到颜色的本质这一主张是正确的,它需要是强有力的。凯尔西的观点似乎是,这个原则让我们能够充分说明代理人对病人行使某种权力所产生的影响,并从中读出这种权力的正确说明。在Kelsey的例子中,“人行道并不是碰巧为汽车提供了一个平稳的行驶,这就是它的作用”(54)。路面的作用是让你平稳地行驶,因为它本身就有这种能力。(因此,代理的“业务”是它拥有的“使事物成为现实的能力”——它的“定义工作”[53])。如果这是正确的,那么我们就有压力确保我们以正确的方式读出代理人的权力所产生的影响。至少,我们必须找到其本身的影响。毕竟,虽然泥滩确实能让汽车平稳行驶,但它们本身对汽车的影响是另一回事——因为与人行道不同,泥滩肯定没有让汽车平稳行驶的能力。我们从中得到的教训是,我们对效果的描述应该忽略那些认为行为人有能力做不到的事情。然而,这种锐化可能会让我们怀疑这样一种观点,即在被感知的过程中,一个可感知的物体行使了一种向有知觉的生物“揭示自身”的力量(55)——这一主张是凯尔西最终观点的重要基础,即感性是可感知物体形式的一部分。另一个问题是关于如何最好地描述亚里士多德和他的前辈关于(A *)的辩证法。在Kelsey第3.3节的讨论中,相似性的关联词是“做出判决的人的品质”和他们做出的“判决”(“法官‘看到’的东西”)(45)。在他对第2.5节的讨论中,它们是“有知觉的生物”和“它们感知的对象”——“它们之所以出现,部分是由于它们自身的某些东西”(54-55)。这两种表述提出了一个有趣的问题,即亚里士多德在多大程度上维持了他的前辈对解释的描述:如果客体以这种方式“出现”是我们的“结论”,他将保留了他的前辈对关系的表述,并修改了他对它们相似性的解释——但如果这是它们在感知时对有知觉的生物的影响,他也将修改他们对关系的概念。有了这些基础,接下来的两章将介绍凯尔西对他最初问题的回答中的两个成分。第一个是建立在他的同类因果关系的基础上;他认为,这需要“形式上的相似”(69)。第二种是在这些形式的基础上进行扩展,诉诸于“度量”的概念。Kelsey认为,度量不仅与已知的对象相似,而且“在概念上先于已知的对象”(85)。例如,紫色位于以“平均”或“中间”为特征的光谱上;此外,紫色的“本质”是躺在中间的“一边或另一边”(92-95)。但是,下一章认为,这种中间本身是根据感性来规定的,感性是它的尺度(参见434a9;引自第100页)。当DA 2.12将感性定义为“一种比率”(424a27-28)——它本身是一个中间(424a4-5)——它的要点是感性是一种形式,是可感知形式的尺度(103-17)。结果是感性认识紫色,因为感性“进入”了紫色的本性(90-91;参见112-17)。类似的情况也适用于智力。因此,最后两章大致认为,智力是对其对象的一种衡量,因为“表征其活动的清晰性和独特性(就其本身而言)正是”这些对象的“形式”——使它们具有可理解性的东西(154)。本节再次对我们熟悉的教义提供了有益的新阐释。在凯尔西的笔下,亚里士多德关于感性是“中间”的观点不仅仅是一个神秘的细节,也不仅仅是对我们区分各种品质的能力的一种方便的解释,而是对它们本质的反映——它很好地解释了我们为什么会这样看待它们。凯尔西的书值得称赞,不仅因为它描绘了一个有希望的新立场,而且因为它迫使我们弄清楚,要回答它所提出的问题,它将是什么。当然,凯尔西的推理并非毫无争议。考虑到他的主张,当品质位于光谱上时,“每个特定的品质”“将位于”“中间”或“光谱的一边”,“就其本质而言”(95)。为什么是“本性使然”?凯尔西的回答是,它是按照特定的“比例”“由”对立面“组成”的(94)——这使得它处于这样一个“按其自身性质”的位置(94)。 但是,如果这是可感知品质是参照中间来定义的证据,那么拒绝另一种观点,即它们是“由对立面的‘比例’来定义的”,可能是具有挑战性的(95n18)它们之所以被定义为中间,是因为它们的比例赋予了它们相对于中间的特征——如果不是它们的本性,很难看出比例如何能做到这一点。凯尔西的立场,正如书的结论所强调的,是一个令人惊讶的立场:它赋予了感性和智慧“一种优先权——一种尺度对尺度的优先权”,赋予它们感知和理解的东西(159)。我要强调的是,这是一个受欢迎的惊喜:通过清楚地识别可能将亚里士多德推向这种境地的考虑因素,凯尔西这本优秀的书开辟了新的问题,并确保我们认真思考他们所问的问题。非常感谢Reier Helle对本文草稿的有益评论。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW PHILOSOPHY-
CiteScore
7.40
自引率
0.00%
发文量
17
期刊介绍: In continuous publication since 1892, the Philosophical Review has a long-standing reputation for excellence and has published many papers now considered classics in the field, such as W. V. O. Quine"s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” Thomas Nagel"s “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” and the early work of John Rawls. The journal aims to publish original scholarly work in all areas of analytic philosophy, with an emphasis on material of general interest to academic philosophers, and is one of the few journals in the discipline to publish book reviews.
期刊最新文献
Reasons First Dark Matters: Pessimism and the Problem of Suffering Democratic Law Sustaining Democracy: What We Owe to the Other Side Mind and World in Aristotle’s De Anima
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1