Democratic Law

IF 2.8 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW Pub Date : 2023-07-01 DOI:10.1215/00318108-10469616
Melissa Schwartzberg
{"title":"<i>Democratic Law</i>","authors":"Melissa Schwartzberg","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10469616","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"The question of how communities may author their own laws, thereby manifesting autonomy (“self-legislation”), arises throughout the history of political thought. In Democratic Law, her Berkeley Tanner Lectures, Seana Valentine Shiffrin offers a distinguished contribution to this long inquiry: she argues that law’s value within democratic societies rests on its communicative capacity, enabling citizens to express their recognition of each other’s equal status.Following an insightful introduction by editor Hannah Ginsborg, Shiffrin’s first lecture, “Democratic Law,” provides the philosophical groundwork for the rest of the volume. Shiffrin characterizes democracy as a system that treats its members with equal concern and respect, and one that enables its citizens to serve as the “equal and exclusive co-authors” of its legal norms and directives (20). Law plays a distinctive and crucial role on this account because it allows us to identify and to communicate our shared moral commitments. Foremost among these joint commitments is that members are due equal recognition of their status as citizens (51) and each of us must intend to convey respect for each other as equal comembers (31). We cannot do so severally, given the scope of the community, but neither can we satisfy our obligation merely by endorsing or complying with existing norms (31–32, 38). Rather, “each of us needs to perform (and receive) a form of communicative action that enacts and thereby expresses our commitment to the respectful treatment that each of us merits as a moral equal and a joint member of our social cooperative venture” (39). Shiffrin argues that law—quotidian or constitutional, common or statutory—is the central means of discharging this communicative duty.The second half of the volume features two lectures on legal applications, “Democratic Law and the Erosion of Common Law” and “Constitutional Balancing and State Interests.” The former focuses on what might seem to be a minor, technical Supreme Court decision concerning frequent-flier programs, yet Shiffrin persuasively argues that it raises far-reaching concerns about the nature of public commitments. The question in Northwest, Inc. v. Ginsberg is whether a federal statute, the Airline Deregulation Act, preempts a state rule of common law by which parties to a contract have an implied covenant of good faith and fair dealing. Shiffrin objects to Justice Alito’s opinion for a unanimous court in Ginsberg for two main reasons. First, it wrongly characterizes the duty of good faith and fair dealing as subject to preemption, as a form of state action around which the parties could not contract, rather than characterizing the duty as pertaining to the underlying meaning of voluntary agreements (74–75). By incorporating a duty of good faith into contract law, a democratic society expresses the value of keeping commitments to each other, and that respect for each other as citizens means not deliberately acting to undermine the purpose of the agreements we form. Second, Justice Alito’s opinion, which treats statutory and common law as effectively identical for the purposes of the preemption provision in the ADA, neglects the distinctive value of the common law as a form of “collective moral articulation” (84). As Shiffrin notes, the Supreme Court has recently expanded the scope of federal preemption, displacing the development and articulation of common law. Since such evolution primarily takes place in state courts (especially with respect to contract law), preemption of the common law undermines the development of the “local social-moral culture” (87).In the third lecture, Shiffrin turns to “constitutional balancing,” by which a court weighs constitutional interests against state interests. She raises the important question of what it means for the state to have an interest at all, not merely whether such interest is sufficiently compelling to be balanced against the constitutional interests at stake. Here she expresses particular concerns about the invocation of “discretionary interests,” those which a state actor may entertain or promote but is not required to advance, as opposed to “mandatory interests.” She considers whether the mere identification of a discretionary interest on the part of a state suffices to establish that a state does in fact have such an interest for the purpose of constitutional balancing, and answers in the negative: a state must demonstrate a commitment to this interest, developed in a purposive and coherent fashion over time, for it to merit weight on a balancing test. Evidence of the “strength and sincerity” of the state’s interest must be provided (122), potentially requiring a showing that a state has adopted a serious approach to securing the interest, including answering the charge that the state has taken measures apparently at odds with an asserted interest (in her example, a state claiming an unqualified interest in preserving life so as to prohibit assisted suicide could not simultaneously allow the death penalty [103]).Characteristically for Shiffrin, these lectures are all beautifully argued. Likely due to the lecture genre, though, Shiffrin does not really situate her concept of coauthorship within the existing literature on group agency, joint commitment, and shared intentions. There is considerable philosophical work on these topics, and scholars, notably including Philip Pettit (2012), have in recent years profitably developed its implications for democracy. Political theorists have turned to Michael Bratman (1999) and Margaret Gilbert (1996) to characterize dimensions of the democratic process as a joint intentional practice, including Anna Stilz (2009) on the value of the state, Josiah Ober (2017) on collective self-government, Emilee Booth Chapman (2022) on elections, and Eric Beerbohm (2012), who specifically invokes joint intentional authorship to explain individuals’ complicity in injustice. Shiffrin’s contribution is distinctive among these accounts in part due to its quite demanding characterization of coauthorship, made more plausible by the stipulation that she argues from the standpoint of ideal theory, asking “what role democracy and law would play in a state whose institutions otherwise manifest features of material and intellectual forms of justice and whose citizens largely endorse the principles of justice and their instantiation” (20).One natural worry is that because Shiffrin’s account of joint authorship presupposes a shared endorsement of the principles of justice, it might mean that the joint commitment in fact occurs at this earlier stage rather than through the activity of legislation, or that the communicative act of lawmaking merely redescribes that endorsement. So the second and third lectures—in nonideal theory—should respond to this concern by demonstrating how contemporary democracies such as the United States, who fall short of such conditions, could still enable coauthorship, if imperfectly. Here some difficulties arise.To begin, in the first lecture, Shiffrin argues that for law to be democratic, the “terms of that participation must themselves be equal, under some salient description, or else the message will not be each of ours and the participatory structure will belie at least part of the message of our mutual equality” (39). Yet in lectures 2 and 3, Shiffrin shifts to treating participation on equal terms as inessential, raising some challenges for the coherence of the argument overall.Shiffrin’s interlocutors note this problem. Like other Tanner Lecture volumes, the book features commentaries: in this case, excellent contributions from philosopher Niko Kolodny, legal scholar Richard R. W. Brooks, and political theorist Anna Stilz. Kolodny and Stilz both raise the objection—inter alia—that although Shiffrin insists that participation in the creation of democratic law requires that each of us have an opportunity to participate for the communication to be ours and publicly so (or else the message will not be each of ours), she does not require us to have an equal say. As Kolodny points out, we are asked to communicate equal standing, and doing so seems to matter very greatly for the moral lives of our members, as their self-respect depends on it. If we do not need to do so through an equal say, then the process would seem to compromise the content—as, per Kolodny’s piquant example, in the manufacture of a MAGA hat abroad (139). Stilz presses Shiffrin on how apparently inegalitarian institutions such as judge-made common law can satisfy the egalitarian communicative duty (174–76). Like Kolodny, she takes up the issue of whether egalitarian participation rights are fundamental to democratic communication and asks what connection the common law has to such rights, in part given its origins in the nondemocratic domain of twelfth-century England.Evading these worries places Shiffrin in the difficult position of defending the common law as a more effective means than statutes for each of us to communicate equal status. In her second lecture, Shiffrin contrasts the common law favorably with “many manifestations of the legislative process” (84); she argues that whereas the legislature may be subject to capture by interest groups and disproportionately responsive to larger and better organized groups, the “common law process embodies a judicial manifestation of the equal importance of each citizen, a process less sensitive to affiliation and social power than many manifestations of the legislative process” (84). This is a surprising assertion, one far more consistent with Ronald Dworkin’s (1986: 238–39) vision of Hercules—an “author in the chain of common law” —than a robust defense of democratic coauthorship. The claim that social power plays a lesser role in contract litigation than in legislation is contestable: litigation is costly, litigants with greater resources are often advantaged in an adversarial context, and surely the development of the common law in state courts of appeal depends on litigants who can bear those material and transaction costs and who may be able to delay settlement. Moreover, judges themselves tend to possess significant social power, certainly relative to many state legislators.More seriously, taking Stilz’s argument a step further, if forced to locate myself as a coauthor either of the common law of contracts or of a statute, it is hard to imagine choosing the former. (Shifflin would maintain that one need not actually choose, and that I should equally see myself in both.) A state court of appeals judge (elected or appointed) resolves a breach of contract dispute between private parties unknown to me and issues a judgment on, say, “lack of privity,” an unfamiliar concept; the case receives no media attention. By contrast, statutes emerge from a public legislative process; even if certain bills are little noticed, representatives facing competitive, partisan elections can anticipate that they will be held accountable for their votes. Now, one might argue—reasonably, in my view—that neither plausibly meets the standards of coauthorship, but it is hard to argue that the displacement of the common law of states through federal preemption poses a worse affront to citizens as coauthors than having their state legislation struck down by the Supreme Court. Indeed, Shiffrin expressly argues in the second lecture that “local and state governments may have a special significance for communicative approaches” through the creation of law by a community “powerful enough to generate a distinctive identity and camaraderie between citizens” (67). If preemption through federal legislation may threaten these communicative aims, so too might a sweeping role for federal courts in scrutinizing the depth of citizens’ commitments, as Shiffrin defends in the third lecture.Given that state legislatures would seem to be main forums for the articulation of local norms—a domain in which one could most plausibly ascribe coauthorship to citizens—it is surprising how little deference Shiffrin is willing to afford them. Brooks characterizes Shiffrin’s objection as a worry about cheap talk, in which a state can evince commitment to a discretionary interest without incurring costs in so doing (162); the aim is to raise the price of such communication by insisting that it must be backed up by prior investments. Brooks proposes that one might reasonably presume that state actors could speak authentically when representing interests, and he intimates that such a presumption might be necessary for state action to preserve the communicative value that Shiffrin seeks to ascribe to it (163). Alternatively, he suggests that bringing the interests of speaker and addressee into alignment can help to make cheap talk credible, and so here he recommends “focusing on the democratically representative institutions that promote the interests of agents” (164). Both of these proposals seem warranted insofar as we want to secure conditions of authorship.Yet Shiffrin insists that we cannot take legislators’ word for it: whatever the support for these norms within their community, if these laws merely manifest new discretionary interests (departing from the status quo), and if state actors cannot demonstrate the consistency of such interests throughout the fabric of their law to the satisfaction of courts, they ought to enjoy little weight on balance. Put differently, if a state seeks to act as a laboratory for legislative experimentation, citizens must insure that Bunsen burners are lit beneath all laws that might reflect related interests, lest such an interest be dismissed as fleeting or pretextual.And citizens can have no complaint when their commitments are dismissed as shallow. In the first lecture, Shiffrin is willing to defend the value of voting in elections as a means of how “I, as a co-author, should contribute to the joint deliberation about and determination of the particular form that commitment should take (whether directly, as with a referendum, or indirectly, when we elect agents who themselves offer a concrete vision of how to make our joint commitment more determinate)” (53–54). But by the end of the volume, in her reply to commentators, Shiffrin characterizes elections and referenda as in fact failing to satisfy the communicative requirements because of the absence of reason-giving: “judicial institutions … permit participation by citizens that is dramatically more articulate and … produce results that are dramatically more articulate than elections” (213–14).It would seem, then, that most of us will remain silent coauthors. Because Shiffrin briefly draws an analogy to joint academic writing (22), please forgive a final observation that, if this can count as coauthorship, my h-index really should be much higher.","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"83 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":2.8000,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10469616","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

The question of how communities may author their own laws, thereby manifesting autonomy (“self-legislation”), arises throughout the history of political thought. In Democratic Law, her Berkeley Tanner Lectures, Seana Valentine Shiffrin offers a distinguished contribution to this long inquiry: she argues that law’s value within democratic societies rests on its communicative capacity, enabling citizens to express their recognition of each other’s equal status.Following an insightful introduction by editor Hannah Ginsborg, Shiffrin’s first lecture, “Democratic Law,” provides the philosophical groundwork for the rest of the volume. Shiffrin characterizes democracy as a system that treats its members with equal concern and respect, and one that enables its citizens to serve as the “equal and exclusive co-authors” of its legal norms and directives (20). Law plays a distinctive and crucial role on this account because it allows us to identify and to communicate our shared moral commitments. Foremost among these joint commitments is that members are due equal recognition of their status as citizens (51) and each of us must intend to convey respect for each other as equal comembers (31). We cannot do so severally, given the scope of the community, but neither can we satisfy our obligation merely by endorsing or complying with existing norms (31–32, 38). Rather, “each of us needs to perform (and receive) a form of communicative action that enacts and thereby expresses our commitment to the respectful treatment that each of us merits as a moral equal and a joint member of our social cooperative venture” (39). Shiffrin argues that law—quotidian or constitutional, common or statutory—is the central means of discharging this communicative duty.The second half of the volume features two lectures on legal applications, “Democratic Law and the Erosion of Common Law” and “Constitutional Balancing and State Interests.” The former focuses on what might seem to be a minor, technical Supreme Court decision concerning frequent-flier programs, yet Shiffrin persuasively argues that it raises far-reaching concerns about the nature of public commitments. The question in Northwest, Inc. v. Ginsberg is whether a federal statute, the Airline Deregulation Act, preempts a state rule of common law by which parties to a contract have an implied covenant of good faith and fair dealing. Shiffrin objects to Justice Alito’s opinion for a unanimous court in Ginsberg for two main reasons. First, it wrongly characterizes the duty of good faith and fair dealing as subject to preemption, as a form of state action around which the parties could not contract, rather than characterizing the duty as pertaining to the underlying meaning of voluntary agreements (74–75). By incorporating a duty of good faith into contract law, a democratic society expresses the value of keeping commitments to each other, and that respect for each other as citizens means not deliberately acting to undermine the purpose of the agreements we form. Second, Justice Alito’s opinion, which treats statutory and common law as effectively identical for the purposes of the preemption provision in the ADA, neglects the distinctive value of the common law as a form of “collective moral articulation” (84). As Shiffrin notes, the Supreme Court has recently expanded the scope of federal preemption, displacing the development and articulation of common law. Since such evolution primarily takes place in state courts (especially with respect to contract law), preemption of the common law undermines the development of the “local social-moral culture” (87).In the third lecture, Shiffrin turns to “constitutional balancing,” by which a court weighs constitutional interests against state interests. She raises the important question of what it means for the state to have an interest at all, not merely whether such interest is sufficiently compelling to be balanced against the constitutional interests at stake. Here she expresses particular concerns about the invocation of “discretionary interests,” those which a state actor may entertain or promote but is not required to advance, as opposed to “mandatory interests.” She considers whether the mere identification of a discretionary interest on the part of a state suffices to establish that a state does in fact have such an interest for the purpose of constitutional balancing, and answers in the negative: a state must demonstrate a commitment to this interest, developed in a purposive and coherent fashion over time, for it to merit weight on a balancing test. Evidence of the “strength and sincerity” of the state’s interest must be provided (122), potentially requiring a showing that a state has adopted a serious approach to securing the interest, including answering the charge that the state has taken measures apparently at odds with an asserted interest (in her example, a state claiming an unqualified interest in preserving life so as to prohibit assisted suicide could not simultaneously allow the death penalty [103]).Characteristically for Shiffrin, these lectures are all beautifully argued. Likely due to the lecture genre, though, Shiffrin does not really situate her concept of coauthorship within the existing literature on group agency, joint commitment, and shared intentions. There is considerable philosophical work on these topics, and scholars, notably including Philip Pettit (2012), have in recent years profitably developed its implications for democracy. Political theorists have turned to Michael Bratman (1999) and Margaret Gilbert (1996) to characterize dimensions of the democratic process as a joint intentional practice, including Anna Stilz (2009) on the value of the state, Josiah Ober (2017) on collective self-government, Emilee Booth Chapman (2022) on elections, and Eric Beerbohm (2012), who specifically invokes joint intentional authorship to explain individuals’ complicity in injustice. Shiffrin’s contribution is distinctive among these accounts in part due to its quite demanding characterization of coauthorship, made more plausible by the stipulation that she argues from the standpoint of ideal theory, asking “what role democracy and law would play in a state whose institutions otherwise manifest features of material and intellectual forms of justice and whose citizens largely endorse the principles of justice and their instantiation” (20).One natural worry is that because Shiffrin’s account of joint authorship presupposes a shared endorsement of the principles of justice, it might mean that the joint commitment in fact occurs at this earlier stage rather than through the activity of legislation, or that the communicative act of lawmaking merely redescribes that endorsement. So the second and third lectures—in nonideal theory—should respond to this concern by demonstrating how contemporary democracies such as the United States, who fall short of such conditions, could still enable coauthorship, if imperfectly. Here some difficulties arise.To begin, in the first lecture, Shiffrin argues that for law to be democratic, the “terms of that participation must themselves be equal, under some salient description, or else the message will not be each of ours and the participatory structure will belie at least part of the message of our mutual equality” (39). Yet in lectures 2 and 3, Shiffrin shifts to treating participation on equal terms as inessential, raising some challenges for the coherence of the argument overall.Shiffrin’s interlocutors note this problem. Like other Tanner Lecture volumes, the book features commentaries: in this case, excellent contributions from philosopher Niko Kolodny, legal scholar Richard R. W. Brooks, and political theorist Anna Stilz. Kolodny and Stilz both raise the objection—inter alia—that although Shiffrin insists that participation in the creation of democratic law requires that each of us have an opportunity to participate for the communication to be ours and publicly so (or else the message will not be each of ours), she does not require us to have an equal say. As Kolodny points out, we are asked to communicate equal standing, and doing so seems to matter very greatly for the moral lives of our members, as their self-respect depends on it. If we do not need to do so through an equal say, then the process would seem to compromise the content—as, per Kolodny’s piquant example, in the manufacture of a MAGA hat abroad (139). Stilz presses Shiffrin on how apparently inegalitarian institutions such as judge-made common law can satisfy the egalitarian communicative duty (174–76). Like Kolodny, she takes up the issue of whether egalitarian participation rights are fundamental to democratic communication and asks what connection the common law has to such rights, in part given its origins in the nondemocratic domain of twelfth-century England.Evading these worries places Shiffrin in the difficult position of defending the common law as a more effective means than statutes for each of us to communicate equal status. In her second lecture, Shiffrin contrasts the common law favorably with “many manifestations of the legislative process” (84); she argues that whereas the legislature may be subject to capture by interest groups and disproportionately responsive to larger and better organized groups, the “common law process embodies a judicial manifestation of the equal importance of each citizen, a process less sensitive to affiliation and social power than many manifestations of the legislative process” (84). This is a surprising assertion, one far more consistent with Ronald Dworkin’s (1986: 238–39) vision of Hercules—an “author in the chain of common law” —than a robust defense of democratic coauthorship. The claim that social power plays a lesser role in contract litigation than in legislation is contestable: litigation is costly, litigants with greater resources are often advantaged in an adversarial context, and surely the development of the common law in state courts of appeal depends on litigants who can bear those material and transaction costs and who may be able to delay settlement. Moreover, judges themselves tend to possess significant social power, certainly relative to many state legislators.More seriously, taking Stilz’s argument a step further, if forced to locate myself as a coauthor either of the common law of contracts or of a statute, it is hard to imagine choosing the former. (Shifflin would maintain that one need not actually choose, and that I should equally see myself in both.) A state court of appeals judge (elected or appointed) resolves a breach of contract dispute between private parties unknown to me and issues a judgment on, say, “lack of privity,” an unfamiliar concept; the case receives no media attention. By contrast, statutes emerge from a public legislative process; even if certain bills are little noticed, representatives facing competitive, partisan elections can anticipate that they will be held accountable for their votes. Now, one might argue—reasonably, in my view—that neither plausibly meets the standards of coauthorship, but it is hard to argue that the displacement of the common law of states through federal preemption poses a worse affront to citizens as coauthors than having their state legislation struck down by the Supreme Court. Indeed, Shiffrin expressly argues in the second lecture that “local and state governments may have a special significance for communicative approaches” through the creation of law by a community “powerful enough to generate a distinctive identity and camaraderie between citizens” (67). If preemption through federal legislation may threaten these communicative aims, so too might a sweeping role for federal courts in scrutinizing the depth of citizens’ commitments, as Shiffrin defends in the third lecture.Given that state legislatures would seem to be main forums for the articulation of local norms—a domain in which one could most plausibly ascribe coauthorship to citizens—it is surprising how little deference Shiffrin is willing to afford them. Brooks characterizes Shiffrin’s objection as a worry about cheap talk, in which a state can evince commitment to a discretionary interest without incurring costs in so doing (162); the aim is to raise the price of such communication by insisting that it must be backed up by prior investments. Brooks proposes that one might reasonably presume that state actors could speak authentically when representing interests, and he intimates that such a presumption might be necessary for state action to preserve the communicative value that Shiffrin seeks to ascribe to it (163). Alternatively, he suggests that bringing the interests of speaker and addressee into alignment can help to make cheap talk credible, and so here he recommends “focusing on the democratically representative institutions that promote the interests of agents” (164). Both of these proposals seem warranted insofar as we want to secure conditions of authorship.Yet Shiffrin insists that we cannot take legislators’ word for it: whatever the support for these norms within their community, if these laws merely manifest new discretionary interests (departing from the status quo), and if state actors cannot demonstrate the consistency of such interests throughout the fabric of their law to the satisfaction of courts, they ought to enjoy little weight on balance. Put differently, if a state seeks to act as a laboratory for legislative experimentation, citizens must insure that Bunsen burners are lit beneath all laws that might reflect related interests, lest such an interest be dismissed as fleeting or pretextual.And citizens can have no complaint when their commitments are dismissed as shallow. In the first lecture, Shiffrin is willing to defend the value of voting in elections as a means of how “I, as a co-author, should contribute to the joint deliberation about and determination of the particular form that commitment should take (whether directly, as with a referendum, or indirectly, when we elect agents who themselves offer a concrete vision of how to make our joint commitment more determinate)” (53–54). But by the end of the volume, in her reply to commentators, Shiffrin characterizes elections and referenda as in fact failing to satisfy the communicative requirements because of the absence of reason-giving: “judicial institutions … permit participation by citizens that is dramatically more articulate and … produce results that are dramatically more articulate than elections” (213–14).It would seem, then, that most of us will remain silent coauthors. Because Shiffrin briefly draws an analogy to joint academic writing (22), please forgive a final observation that, if this can count as coauthorship, my h-index really should be much higher.
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
民主法
社区如何制定自己的法律,从而体现自治(“自我立法”)的问题贯穿于整个政治思想史。Seana Valentine Shiffrin在伯克利坦纳讲座(Berkeley Tanner Lectures)的《民主法》(Democratic Law)中,对这一漫长的探究做出了杰出的贡献:她认为,在民主社会中,法律的价值取决于它的沟通能力,使公民能够表达对彼此平等地位的认可。在编辑汉娜·金斯伯格(Hannah Ginsborg)富有洞察力的介绍之后,西弗林的第一讲“民主法”为本书的其余部分提供了哲学基础。Shiffrin将民主描述为一种以平等的关心和尊重对待其成员的制度,并使其公民能够成为其法律规范和指令的“平等和唯一的共同作者”(20)。在这方面,法律发挥着独特而关键的作用,因为它使我们能够识别和交流我们共同的道德承诺。在这些共同承诺中,最重要的是各成员作为公民的地位应得到平等承认(51),我们每一个成员都必须打算表达对彼此作为平等成员的尊重(31)。鉴于社区的范围,我们不能单独这样做,但我们也不能仅仅通过赞同或遵守现有规范来履行我们的义务(31 - 32,38)。相反,“我们每个人都需要执行(并接受)一种形式的交流行为,这种行为制定并因此表达了我们对尊重对待的承诺,我们每个人都应该作为道德平等者和我们社会合作事业的共同成员得到尊重对待”(39)。Shiffrin认为,日常法或宪法法,普通法或成文法是履行这种沟通义务的主要手段。下半部分有两个关于法律应用的讲座,“民主法与普通法的侵蚀”和“宪法平衡与国家利益”。前者关注的是最高法院关于常旅客计划的一项看似微不足道的技术性裁决,但Shiffrin令人信服地辩称,它引发了对公共承诺性质的深远关注。Northwest, Inc.诉Ginsberg案的问题在于,联邦法规《航空公司放松管制法》(Airline Deregulation Act)是否优先于州普通法规定,即合同各方有诚信和公平交易的默示契约。希夫林反对阿利托大法官关于金斯伯格案一致判决的意见,主要有两个原因。首先,它错误地将诚实信用和公平交易的义务定性为优先原则,将其定性为一种各方不能围绕其订立合同的国家行为形式,而不是将其定性为与自愿协议的基本含义有关(74-75)。通过将诚信义务纳入合同法,民主社会表达了对彼此信守承诺的价值,以及作为公民相互尊重意味着不故意采取行动破坏我们达成的协议的目的。其次,阿利托大法官的意见认为,就《美国残疾人法》的优先条款而言,成文法和普通法实际上是相同的,忽视了普通法作为一种“集体道德表达”形式的独特价值(84)。正如Shiffrin所指出的,最高法院最近扩大了联邦优先购买权的范围,取代了普通法的发展和衔接。由于这种演变主要发生在州法院(特别是在合同法方面),对普通法的优先适用破坏了“地方社会道德文化”的发展(87)。在第三讲中,Shiffrin转向了“宪法平衡”,即法院权衡宪法利益与国家利益。她提出了一个重要的问题,即国家拥有利益到底意味着什么,而不仅仅是这种利益是否足够引人注目,足以与岌岌可危的宪法利益相平衡。在这里,她表达了对“自由裁量利益”的特别关注,即国家行为者可以接受或促进但不需要推进的利益,而不是“强制性利益”。她考虑了仅仅认定一个国家的自由裁量性利益是否足以确定一个国家实际上为了宪法平衡的目的而拥有这样的利益,并给出了否定的答案:一个国家必须表现出对这种利益的承诺,随着时间的推移,以一种有目的和连贯的方式发展,因为它在平衡测试中值得重视。 必须提供国家利益的“力量和诚意”的证据(122),这可能需要证明一个国家已经采取了认真的方法来确保利益,包括回答有关国家采取了明显与所主张的利益不一致的措施的指控(在她的例子中,一个声称保护生命的无条件利益以禁止协助自杀的国家不能同时允许死刑[103])。希夫林的特点是,这些演讲都有精彩的论述。然而,可能是由于讲课类型的原因,Shiffrin并没有真正将她的合著概念置于现有的关于群体代理、共同承诺和共同意图的文献中。关于这些主题有相当多的哲学研究,学者们,尤其是菲利普·佩蒂特(Philip Pettit, 2012),近年来对其对民主的影响进行了有益的研究。政治理论家已经转向迈克尔·布拉特曼(1999)和玛格丽特·吉尔伯特(1996),将民主进程的维度描述为一种共同的有意实践,包括安娜·斯蒂尔兹(2009)关于国家价值的研究,乔西亚·奥伯(2017)关于集体自治的研究,艾米丽·布斯·查普曼(2022)关于选举的研究,以及埃里克·比尔博姆(2012),他特别引用了共同有意作者来解释个人在不公正中的共谋行为。在这些论述中,Shiffrin的贡献是与众不同的,部分原因是她对合著者的描述非常苛刻,她从理想理论的立场出发,提出了“民主和法律在一个国家中扮演什么角色,这个国家的制度在其他方面表现出物质和精神形式的正义,其公民在很大程度上支持正义原则及其实例”(20)。一个自然的担忧是,因为Shiffrin对共同作者的描述以对正义原则的共同认可为前提,这可能意味着共同承诺实际上发生在这个早期阶段,而不是通过立法活动,或者立法的交流行为只是重新描述了这种认可。因此,第二节和第三节课——在非理想理论中——应该通过展示当代民主国家,如美国,虽然不具备这样的条件,但仍然可以实现合作,如果不完美的话——来回应这种担忧。这里出现了一些困难。首先,在第一讲中,Shiffrin认为,要使法律成为民主的,“参与的条件本身必须是平等的,在一些显著的描述下,否则信息将不是我们每个人的,参与结构将至少部分地相信我们相互平等的信息”(39)。然而在第二和第三讲中,Shiffrin转而认为平等参与是不必要的,这对整个论证的连贯性提出了一些挑战。Shiffrin的对话者注意到了这个问题。像其他坦纳讲座卷一样,这本书也有评论:在这种情况下,哲学家尼科·科洛德尼、法律学者理查德·r·w·布鲁克斯和政治理论家安娜·斯蒂茨的杰出贡献。Kolodny和Stilz都提出了反对意见,除了其他之外,尽管Shiffrin坚持认为参与民主法律的创造需要我们每个人都有机会参与到交流中来,并且是公开的(否则信息就不是我们每个人的),但她并没有要求我们有平等的发言权。正如科洛德尼所指出的,我们被要求以平等的身份交流,这样做似乎对我们成员的道德生活非常重要,因为他们的自尊依赖于此。如果我们不需要通过平等的发言权来做到这一点,那么这个过程似乎就会损害内容——就像Kolodny在国外制造MAGA帽子的有趣例子一样(139)。Stilz向Shiffrin施压,探讨诸如法官制定的普通法等明显不平等的制度如何能够满足平等主义的沟通义务(174-76)。和科洛德尼一样,她探讨了平等参与权是否是民主交流的基础,并询问普通法与这些权利有什么联系,部分原因是普通法起源于12世纪英国的非民主领域。回避这些担忧使Shiffrin陷入了一个艰难的境地,即捍卫普通法是一种比成文法更有效的手段,使我们每个人都能沟通平等地位。在她的第二次演讲中,Shiffrin将普通法与“立法过程的许多表现形式”进行了有利的对比(84);她认为,虽然立法机关可能受到利益集团的控制,并不成比例地对更大、更有组织的集团作出反应,但“普通法程序体现了每个公民同等重要性的司法表现,与立法程序的许多表现形式相比,这一程序对从属关系和社会权力不那么敏感”(84)。 但在卷的最后,在她对评论家的回复中,Shiffrin将选举和全民公决定性为事实上未能满足沟通要求,因为缺乏给出理由:“司法机构……允许公民参与,这明显更清晰,并且……产生的结果明显比选举更清晰”(213-14)。这样看来,我们大多数人都将保持沉默。由于Shiffrin简单地将其比作共同学术写作(22),请原谅最后的观察,如果这可以算作共同作者,我的h指数应该更高。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW PHILOSOPHY-
CiteScore
7.40
自引率
0.00%
发文量
17
期刊介绍: In continuous publication since 1892, the Philosophical Review has a long-standing reputation for excellence and has published many papers now considered classics in the field, such as W. V. O. Quine"s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” Thomas Nagel"s “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” and the early work of John Rawls. The journal aims to publish original scholarly work in all areas of analytic philosophy, with an emphasis on material of general interest to academic philosophers, and is one of the few journals in the discipline to publish book reviews.
期刊最新文献
Reasons First Dark Matters: Pessimism and the Problem of Suffering Democratic Law Sustaining Democracy: What We Owe to the Other Side Mind and World in Aristotle’s De Anima
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1