首页 > 最新文献

PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW最新文献

英文 中文
Dark Matters: Pessimism and the Problem of Suffering 《暗物质:悲观主义与苦难问题》
1区 哲学 Pub Date : 2023-07-01 DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10469577
James Foster
In Dark Matters, Mara Van Der Lugt attempts to rehabilitate pessimism as a moral stance. Critical to this task is the distinction between what she calls “future-oriented” and “value-oriented” pessimism (10). The former is what most people presently understand the word pessimism to mean: a gloomy view about the future, an attitude of premature defeat.Although this kind of fatalism can be found alongside value-oriented pessimism, Van Der Lugt is chiefly interested in the latter, which she portrays as a sympathetic appreciation of suffering that, although not without hope, does not attempt to explain—let alone explain away—the existence of evil.To make this case, Dark Matters proceeds in three sections. The first section, comprising the introduction and first two chapters of the book, sets up the contrast between future- and value-oriented pessimism by examining various approaches to the classic problem of evil, as summarized by Epicurus’s classic trilemma among God’s power, God’s goodness, and the existence of evil.Some of these are what she calls “negative” strategies, which deny the premise that there is evil—or, more generously, a problematic amount of evil—in the world (33). And some are “positive” strategies, which accept the premise of evil in the world but attempt to explain the origin of evil by, for example, casting it as the inevitable side effect of free will and/or sin (35). Whatever their views about the future, those who take up these strategies are, in Van Der Lugt’s terms, “optimists.” And they are so by virtue of believing the problem of evil can be satisfactorily answered.On the other hand, those who take the contrasting approach, believing that the problem of evil is so acute that it cannot be rationally resolved, are pessimists. And first among them, for Van Der Lugt’s purposes, is Pierre Bayle, who set the terms of the pessimist/optimist debate in the early modern era by making the problem of evil primarily a problem of suffering.For Bayle, the primary task of addressing Epicurus’s query is not to justify or undermine belief in the existence of a good God. It is, rather, to understand, or at least appreciate, the irrefutable experience of human suffering. This focus on suffering alone does not make Bayle a pessimist. Rather, what makes him a pessimist is his insistence that there is far more suffering than pleasure in life, that we have little power to choose whether we suffer or flourish in any given circumstance, and that most of our pains cannot be explained as just punishment.In opposing Bayle’s diagnosis, Van Der Lugt suggests that most optimists employ a rhetorical strategy that she calls “the optics of optimism.” This strategy first attempts to meet Bayle head-on by denying his first two assertions. That is, optimists hold that there is far more joy in life than suffering and that we have significant capacity to choose happiness over sorrow. In this dispute, disagreement centers around a thought experiment proposed by Ba
在《暗物质》一书中,玛拉·范德卢特试图恢复悲观主义的道德立场。这项任务的关键在于区分她所说的“面向未来”和“面向价值”的悲观主义(10)。前者是目前大多数人对悲观一词的理解:对未来的悲观看法,过早失败的态度。虽然这种宿命论可以与价值导向的悲观主义并存,但范德卢特主要对后者感兴趣,她将后者描绘为对苦难的同情欣赏,尽管并非没有希望,但并不试图解释——更不用说解释了——邪恶的存在。为了证明这一点,《暗物质》分为三个部分。第一部分,包括本书的引言和前两章,通过考察对恶的经典问题的各种方法,建立了以未来为导向和以价值为导向的悲观主义之间的对比,伊壁鸠鲁的经典三困境总结了上帝的力量,上帝的善良和邪恶的存在。其中一些是她所谓的“消极”策略,这些策略否认世界上存在邪恶——或者更慷慨地说,邪恶的数量有问题——的前提(33)。还有一些是“积极”策略,它们接受世界上存在邪恶的前提,但试图解释邪恶的起源,例如,将其视为自由意志和/或罪恶不可避免的副作用(35)。无论他们对未来的看法如何,那些采取这些策略的人,用范德卢格特的话来说,都是“乐观主义者”。他们相信邪恶的问题可以得到令人满意的回答。另一方面,那些持相反观点的人是悲观主义者,他们认为邪恶的问题是如此尖锐,以至于无法理性地解决。首先,根据范德卢格特的目的,是皮埃尔·贝利,他在现代早期设定了悲观主义者和乐观主义者的争论,他把邪恶的问题主要看作是苦难的问题。对于Bayle来说,解决伊壁鸠鲁问题的首要任务不是证明或破坏对善神存在的信仰。更确切地说,是理解,或者至少是欣赏,人类痛苦的无可辩驳的经验。仅仅关注苦难并不能使贝尔成为悲观主义者。相反,使他成为悲观主义者的是他坚持认为生活中的痛苦远比快乐要多,我们几乎没有能力选择在任何特定的情况下是受苦还是繁荣,我们的大多数痛苦不能被解释为仅仅是惩罚。在反对Bayle的诊断时,Van Der Lugt认为大多数乐观主义者采用了一种修辞策略,她称之为“乐观主义的光学”。这一策略首先试图通过否定贝尔的前两个主张来正面对抗他。也就是说,乐观主义者认为生活中的快乐远远多于痛苦,我们有很大的能力选择快乐而不是悲伤。在这场争论中,分歧集中在Bayle提出的一个思想实验上:如果你问那些上了年纪的人,他们是否愿意以同样的善恶比例再过一次他们的生活,大多数人会给出否定的答案。乐观主义者,如威廉·金和莱布尼茨,不同意。在他们看来,如果另一种选择是被遗忘,大多数人会欣然同意重新过他们的生活。对于乐观主义者来说,问题不在于他们的答案不可信。事实上,他们对人类的普遍看法似乎是正确的。更确切地说,这不足以达到他们的目的。因为,尽管贝勒认为大多数人会选择遗忘而不是生命中的第二次轮回的观点可能确实是错误的,但即使有一种生物会合理地选择遗忘,也足以让那些主张存在良好的普遍秩序的人感到不安。这就是乐观主义发挥作用的地方。因为,当面对一个可能存在的可怜虫时,乐观主义者将他们的论点从“受造物”转向“宇宙”的观点(71)。他们承认,这个世界并不是没有被悲惨的可怜虫玷污的,但他们的痛苦要么是整体良好秩序所必需的,要么是在来生得到足够的回报。在这一点上,根据Van Der Lugt,关于早期现代邪恶问题的辩论结构已经确定。悲观主义者追随Bayle,发现乐观主义者对理性神正论的尝试是对实际经历的痛苦的残酷蔑视。与此同时,乐观主义者认为悲观主义者夸大了他们的情况,从而通过宣扬一种悲观的存在观而造成不必要的痛苦。正如范德卢格特所指出的,这两种立场都具有深刻的伦理意义;他们都关心哲学和神学试图解决邪恶问题的实际效果。在《暗物质》的第二部分,她带我们进行了一次“大旅行”,穿越了这场辩论在18世纪和19世纪的演变过程。
{"title":"<i>Dark Matters: Pessimism and the Problem of Suffering</i>","authors":"James Foster","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10469577","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10469577","url":null,"abstract":"In Dark Matters, Mara Van Der Lugt attempts to rehabilitate pessimism as a moral stance. Critical to this task is the distinction between what she calls “future-oriented” and “value-oriented” pessimism (10). The former is what most people presently understand the word pessimism to mean: a gloomy view about the future, an attitude of premature defeat.Although this kind of fatalism can be found alongside value-oriented pessimism, Van Der Lugt is chiefly interested in the latter, which she portrays as a sympathetic appreciation of suffering that, although not without hope, does not attempt to explain—let alone explain away—the existence of evil.To make this case, Dark Matters proceeds in three sections. The first section, comprising the introduction and first two chapters of the book, sets up the contrast between future- and value-oriented pessimism by examining various approaches to the classic problem of evil, as summarized by Epicurus’s classic trilemma among God’s power, God’s goodness, and the existence of evil.Some of these are what she calls “negative” strategies, which deny the premise that there is evil—or, more generously, a problematic amount of evil—in the world (33). And some are “positive” strategies, which accept the premise of evil in the world but attempt to explain the origin of evil by, for example, casting it as the inevitable side effect of free will and/or sin (35). Whatever their views about the future, those who take up these strategies are, in Van Der Lugt’s terms, “optimists.” And they are so by virtue of believing the problem of evil can be satisfactorily answered.On the other hand, those who take the contrasting approach, believing that the problem of evil is so acute that it cannot be rationally resolved, are pessimists. And first among them, for Van Der Lugt’s purposes, is Pierre Bayle, who set the terms of the pessimist/optimist debate in the early modern era by making the problem of evil primarily a problem of suffering.For Bayle, the primary task of addressing Epicurus’s query is not to justify or undermine belief in the existence of a good God. It is, rather, to understand, or at least appreciate, the irrefutable experience of human suffering. This focus on suffering alone does not make Bayle a pessimist. Rather, what makes him a pessimist is his insistence that there is far more suffering than pleasure in life, that we have little power to choose whether we suffer or flourish in any given circumstance, and that most of our pains cannot be explained as just punishment.In opposing Bayle’s diagnosis, Van Der Lugt suggests that most optimists employ a rhetorical strategy that she calls “the optics of optimism.” This strategy first attempts to meet Bayle head-on by denying his first two assertions. That is, optimists hold that there is far more joy in life than suffering and that we have significant capacity to choose happiness over sorrow. In this dispute, disagreement centers around a thought experiment proposed by Ba","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135857674","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Scope of Consent 同意范围
1区 哲学 Pub Date : 2023-07-01 DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10469590
Danielle Bromwich
Consent covers certain actions but not others. If I lend you my new car, you are now free to use it to run errands but not to compete in a demolition derby. This is obvious enough, but determining exactly what I have permitted is much harder. Since you cannot read my mind, you cannot know for sure which uses of the car fall within the contours of my consent. But if you get this wrong, you use my car without my permission, and that is a rights violation. There is a lot riding on determining which actions are permitted by my consent. Fortunately, Tom Dougherty offers us a novel way to determine this in their excellent book The Scope of Consent.It is natural to think that the scope of consent is fixed by what the consent-giver intended to permit. This captures the intuition that the scope of consent is controlled by the person giving consent. This used to be Dougherty’s view. However, this Permissive Intentions View is implausible. Suppose I had no intention of lending you my car—I only said you could borrow it because I falsely believed it would not start. Despite saying you could use it, this view implies that your use would not fall under the scope of my consent since I did not, in fact, intend you to use it. Cases like these lead Dougherty to reject the Permissive Intentions View in parts 1 and 2 of the book. And, since this view is implied by the Mental View of Consent—the view that we consent only if we have a certain mental attitude—they reject that too.Another plausible idea is that the scope of consent is fixed by what the consent-giver successfully communicates to the consent-receiver. This is intuitive in two respects. First, while most people agree that the consent-giver should determine what has been permitted, they also think that the consent-receiver should have epistemic access to whatever falls within the scope of consent. Second, this view implies that consent is a public phenomenon. Dougherty agrees with the second implication, and this provides them with another reason to reject the Mental View in favor of a Behavioral View of Consent. However, they are not persuaded by the Successful Communication Principle itself. Since successful communication requires uptake, the view implies that the consent-giver has not waived their rights until the consent-receiver finds out. So, even if I leave you a note saying that you can borrow my car, I have not succeeded in consenting until you have read the note. Dougherty finds this counterintuitive, and they therefore reject the view.Dougherty agrees that consent requires public behavior, and so the Successful Communication Account is the closest rival to the view they end up defending. And yet, despite engaging with arguments offered in favor of a view that makes consent and its scope a matter of private intention in part 1 of the book, there is no discussion of arguments offered in favor of a view that makes consent and its scope a matter of public performance in part 2. As a result, Dougherty
同意涵盖某些行为,但不包括其他行为。如果我把我的新车借给你,你现在可以自由地用它跑腿,但不能参加拆迁比赛。这是显而易见的,但要确定我究竟允许了什么就困难得多了。既然你不能读懂我的心思,你就不能确切地知道这辆车的哪些用途在我同意的范围内。但如果你弄错了,你未经我允许就用了我的车,这是侵犯人权。在我的同意下,哪些行动是允许的,这是很重要的。幸运的是,汤姆·多尔蒂在他的优秀著作《同意的范围》中为我们提供了一种新颖的方法来确定这一点。人们很自然地认为,同意的范围是由同意的人打算允许什么来确定的。这抓住了一种直觉,即同意的范围由给予同意的人控制。这曾经是多尔蒂的观点。然而,这种宽容的意图观点是不可信的。假设我无意把我的车借给你——我只是说你可以借,因为我错误地认为它发动不了。尽管说你可以使用它,但这种观点意味着你的使用不属于我同意的范围,因为事实上我并没有打算让你使用它。像这样的案例导致多尔蒂在书的第1部分和第2部分中拒绝了宽容意图观点。而且,由于这一观点隐含在同意的心理观点中,即只有当我们有某种心理态度时,我们才会同意,他们也拒绝了这一观点。另一个似是而非的观点是,同意的范围是由同意者与同意接受者成功沟通的内容决定的。这在两个方面是直观的。首先,虽然大多数人同意同意的人应该决定什么是允许的,但他们也认为同意的接受者应该对同意范围内的任何东西都有认知上的访问权。其次,这种观点暗示同意是一种公共现象。Dougherty同意第二种暗示,这为他们提供了另一个理由来拒绝心理观点而支持行为观点。然而,他们并没有被成功沟通原则本身所说服。由于成功的沟通需要理解,这种观点意味着,在同意的接受者发现之前,同意的给予者并没有放弃他们的权利。所以,即使我给你留了一张纸条,说你可以借我的车,在你看了纸条之前,我还没有成功地同意。多尔蒂发现这是违反直觉的,因此他们拒绝接受这种观点。多尔蒂同意同意需要公众行为,因此成功沟通账户是他们最终捍卫的观点最接近的对手。然而,尽管在书的第一部分中讨论了支持同意及其范围是私人意图问题的观点,但在第二部分中没有讨论支持同意及其范围是公共行为问题的观点。因此,Dougherty没有考虑到为什么对于任何试图公正对待双方同意本质的观点来说,“接受”可能是一个特征——而不是一个缺陷。要了解“接受”的吸引力,可以考虑“同意”在人际道德中所起的作用。如果你读了我的笔记,你可以用它来证明你使用我的车是合理的。然而,如果你还没来得及看,纸条就掉在书架后面了,或者我的伴侣抓住它,打算给你,但很快就忘了,你就没有理由认为你现在可以借我的车了。要证明没有我的同意就不被允许的行为是正当的,别人有充分的理由相信你得到了我的允许是不够的;你需要有充分的理由相信你拥有它,这需要吸收。考虑到这种观点的优点和多尔蒂自己的局限性(值得赞扬的是,他们在书的最后详细讨论了这一点),这里缺乏对成功沟通理论的实际辩护的参与有点不幸。为了调和把我们拉向每一个被拒绝的观点的直觉——也就是说,同意的给予者应该决定同意的范围,而同意的接受者必须在认知上获得允许的范围——多尔蒂在书的第三部分为我们提供了他们的证据说明。该解释包括(1)关于什么构成同意的观点(意志表达观点),(2)确定同意范围的原则(尽职调查原则),以及(3)支持两者的论点(人际辩护论点)。意志表达观点保留了同意给予者在决定同意范围中起作用的直觉,因为同意只是一种有意的意志表达。 即使她不认为自己放弃了反对性侵犯的权利(因为她认为这种权利已经被放弃了),通过提出这种联合行动,她成功地给了丈夫一个很好的理由,让他认为他现在被允许和她发生性关系。这其中的含义令人惊讶:一个同意的人可能会在不明白自己在做什么的情况下表示同意。《同意的范围》中充满了同样新颖的论点、刺激的案例和创造性的建议。而且,在很多方面,多尔蒂在这本书中取得了一些了不起的成就:他们设想了一种确定同意范围的方法,这种方法完美地平衡了我们认为同意给予者应该对他们所同意的内容拥有的控制权,而不否认同意接受者对该同意范围内的内容的认知访问。虽然账户存在问题,但没有什么是无法克服的,一个承诺平衡这些因素的账户具有很高的价值。那些在这一领域工作的人,以及那些想要对这一领域的主要争论有一个清晰见解的局外人,都将从阅读这本文笔优美、想象力丰富、雄心勃勃的书中获益。
{"title":"<i>The Scope of Consent</i>","authors":"Danielle Bromwich","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10469590","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10469590","url":null,"abstract":"Consent covers certain actions but not others. If I lend you my new car, you are now free to use it to run errands but not to compete in a demolition derby. This is obvious enough, but determining exactly what I have permitted is much harder. Since you cannot read my mind, you cannot know for sure which uses of the car fall within the contours of my consent. But if you get this wrong, you use my car without my permission, and that is a rights violation. There is a lot riding on determining which actions are permitted by my consent. Fortunately, Tom Dougherty offers us a novel way to determine this in their excellent book The Scope of Consent.It is natural to think that the scope of consent is fixed by what the consent-giver intended to permit. This captures the intuition that the scope of consent is controlled by the person giving consent. This used to be Dougherty’s view. However, this Permissive Intentions View is implausible. Suppose I had no intention of lending you my car—I only said you could borrow it because I falsely believed it would not start. Despite saying you could use it, this view implies that your use would not fall under the scope of my consent since I did not, in fact, intend you to use it. Cases like these lead Dougherty to reject the Permissive Intentions View in parts 1 and 2 of the book. And, since this view is implied by the Mental View of Consent—the view that we consent only if we have a certain mental attitude—they reject that too.Another plausible idea is that the scope of consent is fixed by what the consent-giver successfully communicates to the consent-receiver. This is intuitive in two respects. First, while most people agree that the consent-giver should determine what has been permitted, they also think that the consent-receiver should have epistemic access to whatever falls within the scope of consent. Second, this view implies that consent is a public phenomenon. Dougherty agrees with the second implication, and this provides them with another reason to reject the Mental View in favor of a Behavioral View of Consent. However, they are not persuaded by the Successful Communication Principle itself. Since successful communication requires uptake, the view implies that the consent-giver has not waived their rights until the consent-receiver finds out. So, even if I leave you a note saying that you can borrow my car, I have not succeeded in consenting until you have read the note. Dougherty finds this counterintuitive, and they therefore reject the view.Dougherty agrees that consent requires public behavior, and so the Successful Communication Account is the closest rival to the view they end up defending. And yet, despite engaging with arguments offered in favor of a view that makes consent and its scope a matter of private intention in part 1 of the book, there is no discussion of arguments offered in favor of a view that makes consent and its scope a matter of public performance in part 2. As a result, Dougherty","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135857678","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Rational Polarization 理性的极化
1区 哲学 Pub Date : 2023-07-01 DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10469499
Kevin Dorst
Predictable polarization is everywhere: we can often predict how people’s opinions, including our own, will shift over time. Extant theories either neglect the fact that we can predict our own polarization, or explain it through irrational mechanisms. They needn’t. Empirical studies suggest that polarization is predictable when evidence is ambiguous, that is, when the rational response is not obvious. I show how Bayesians should model such ambiguity and then prove that—assuming rational updates are those which obey the value of evidence—ambiguity is necessary and sufficient for the rationality of predictable polarization. The main theoretical result is that there can be a series of such updates, each of which is individually expected to make you more accurate, but which together will predictably polarize you. Polarization results from asymmetric increases in accuracy. This mechanism is not only theoretically possible, but empirically plausible. I argue that cognitive search—searching a cognitively accessible space for a particular item—often yields asymmetrically ambiguous evidence, I present an experiment supporting its polarizing effects, and I use simulations to show how it can explain two of the core causes of polarization: confirmation bias and the group polarization effect.
可预测的两极分化无处不在:我们经常可以预测人们的观点,包括我们自己的观点,将如何随着时间的推移而转变。现存的理论要么忽视了我们可以预测自身极化的事实,要么通过不合理的机制来解释它。他们不需要。实证研究表明,当证据不明确时,即理性反应不明显时,两极分化是可以预测的。我展示了贝叶斯学派应该如何为这种模糊性建模,然后证明——假设理性更新是那些服从证据价值的更新——对于可预测的两极分化的合理性来说,模糊性是必要和充分的。主要的理论结果是,可能会有一系列这样的更新,每个更新都被期望使你更准确,但可以预见的是,它们加在一起会使你两极分化。偏振是由于精度的不对称增加造成的。这种机制不仅在理论上是可行的,而且在经验上也是可信的。我认为,认知搜索——为一个特定的物品搜索一个认知可达的空间——经常产生不对称的模糊证据,我提出了一个支持其极化效应的实验,我用模拟来说明它如何解释极化的两个核心原因:确认偏差和群体极化效应。
{"title":"Rational Polarization","authors":"Kevin Dorst","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10469499","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10469499","url":null,"abstract":"Predictable polarization is everywhere: we can often predict how people’s opinions, including our own, will shift over time. Extant theories either neglect the fact that we can predict our own polarization, or explain it through irrational mechanisms. They needn’t. Empirical studies suggest that polarization is predictable when evidence is ambiguous, that is, when the rational response is not obvious. I show how Bayesians should model such ambiguity and then prove that—assuming rational updates are those which obey the value of evidence—ambiguity is necessary and sufficient for the rationality of predictable polarization. The main theoretical result is that there can be a series of such updates, each of which is individually expected to make you more accurate, but which together will predictably polarize you. Polarization results from asymmetric increases in accuracy. This mechanism is not only theoretically possible, but empirically plausible. I argue that cognitive search—searching a cognitively accessible space for a particular item—often yields asymmetrically ambiguous evidence, I present an experiment supporting its polarizing effects, and I use simulations to show how it can explain two of the core causes of polarization: confirmation bias and the group polarization effect.","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135857709","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Shifty Speech and Independent Thought: Epistemic Normativity in Context 诡谲言语与独立思维:语境中的认知规范性
1区 哲学 Pub Date : 2023-07-01 DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10469564
Dorit Ganson
Crafted within a knowledge-first epistemological framework, Mona Simion’s engaging and wide-ranging work ensures that both the Knowledge Norm of Assertion (KNA) and Classical Invariantism (CI) can be part of a viable and productive research program.Dissatisfied with current strategies on offer in the literature, she successfully counters objections to the pair sourced in “shiftiness intuitions”—intuitions that seem to indicate that mere changes in practical context can impact the propriety of assertions and knowledge attributions. For example, in Keith DeRose’s famous pair of low stakes versus high stakes bank cases, the consequences of Keith’s acting on The bank is open on Saturday if it were false change from trivial in low stakes to catastrophic in high stakes. We are to suppose that the proposition is true, and that Keith has access to the same quantity and quality of evidence for it in both cases. In low stakes, but not in high stakes, we are inclined to think that Keith can appropriately assert to his inquiring wife “The bank is open on Saturday.” In low stakes, Keith’s knowledge ascription “I know that the bank is open on Saturday” strikes us as aptly asserted and true. In high stakes only a knowledge denial on Keith’s part strikes us as aptly asserted and true.If we want to hang on to KNA, it looks like we will have to abandon CI and concede that ‘knows’ or knowledge is sensitive to changes in practical considerations. If we want to retain CI, we can try to say that, while Keith does still know that the bank is open on Saturday in high stakes, he does not have sufficient warrant to properly assert that it is. But such a move seems to run counter to KNA. We appear to be stuck in the Shiftiness Dilemma.Keen to get us out of the dilemma and to preserve the idea that epistemically good thinking and asserting are independent of practical concerns, Simion suggests a strategy that can also be used to protect other epistemic speech-act norms and notions from similar threats of practical shiftiness. She notes that having an impact on the degree of epistemic warrant required is not enough to make a norm an epistemic one. Fair enough. If I am given strong practical reason (a million dollars, or a gun to the head) not to adopt full belief until I have gathered more evidence, there is potentially some nonepistemic norm at work in the demand for further evidence. So it is a live possibility (indeed, a plausible one, as Simion would say) that our intuitions in the Shiftiness Dilemma are being misdescribed: they are tracking all-things-considered propriety of assertion, not epistemic propriety. In high stakes, practical norms override the epistemic norm KNA. Keith’s asserting “The bank is open on Saturday” would be epistemically proper but all-things-considered improper.Simion backs up her account with an etiological-function origin story and typology for the norms of assertion. Here is her characterization of etiological function for traits, artifacts,
在知识优先的认识论框架下,Mona Simion引人入胜且涉猎广泛的工作确保了断言的知识规范(KNA)和经典不变量(CI)都可以成为一个可行且富有成效的研究项目的一部分。她对文献中提供的当前策略不满意,成功地反驳了来自“变化直觉”的反对意见,这种直觉似乎表明,在实际环境中,仅仅是变化就会影响断言和知识归因的适当性。例如,在Keith DeRose著名的低风险与高风险银行案例中,如果是错误的,Keith对银行周六营业的行为的后果从低风险的微不足道变成了高风险的灾难性。我们假设命题为真,并且基思在两种情况下都能获得相同数量和质量的证据。在低风险情况下,而不是高风险情况下,我们倾向于认为基思可以恰当地对询问他的妻子说:“银行星期六开门。”在低风险的情况下,Keith的知识归属“我知道银行周六开门”给我们的印象是恰当的断言和真实的。在高风险的情况下,只有基思方面的知识否认给我们的印象是恰当的断言和真实的。如果我们想要坚持KNA,看起来我们将不得不放弃CI并承认“知道”或知识对实际考虑的变化是敏感的。如果我们想保留CI,我们可以试着说,虽然Keith仍然知道银行在周六以高赌注开放,但他没有足够的保证来正确断言它是开放的。但这样的举动似乎与朝鲜人民军背道而驰。我们似乎陷入了诡谲的困境。为了让我们摆脱困境,并保持认识论上的良好思考和断言独立于实践问题的观点,Simion提出了一种策略,该策略也可用于保护其他认识论上的言语行为规范和概念免受类似的实践变化的威胁。她指出,对所要求的认识论保证的程度产生影响并不足以使规范成为认识论规范。很好。如果有人给我强有力的实际理由(比如一百万美元,或者拿枪顶着我的头),让我在收集到更多证据之前不要完全相信,那么在需要进一步证据的过程中,可能会有一些非认知规范在起作用。因此,这是一个活生生的可能性(事实上,一个似是而非的可能性,正如西米恩会说的那样),我们在诡谲困境中的直觉被错误地描述了:它们追踪的是所有被认为是主张的适当性,而不是认知的适当性。在高风险情况下,实践规范凌驾于认知规范KNA之上。基思断言“银行周六开门”在认识论上是正确的,但在所有方面都被认为是不恰当的。Simion用病因功能起源故事和断言规范的类型学来支持她的叙述。以下是她对特征、人工制品和行为的病因功能的描述。E-function。令牌类型T的e-function B型生产效果E系统中的S敌我识别(1)令牌产生的T E过去,(2)生产E导致B型S / S的祖先,和(3)生产E B-benefited S的祖先有助于解释为什么T中存在着这种模式,一个行动准则函数或类型的操作的目的,进而类型的行动提供了好处。断言的认识论规范将是一个特征和可靠地使断言实践的参与者确保其主要认识论善的规范,Simion将其定义为知识(在正常条件下由知识渊博的说话者的断言产生的听者的证言性知识)。练习中的动作直接或间接地以实现练习的目标为目的。断言是探究实践中的一种行动,它以产生知识为目的。因此,西米恩得出结论,断言的目的是产生知识。这种说法有助于解释,为什么在高风险的情况下,考虑一切的基思不应该断言“银行周六开门”,即使他知道这是真的。审慎的断言规范凌驾于认识论的KNA之上,因为当多种功能发生冲突时,那些对生物体生存更重要的功能将产生更重的规范约束。然后,Simion将她的解释应用于一般的构成句——例如,表达说话者的信念和听者形成或继续持有类似信念的意图的言语行为。运用巴赫和哈尼什的分类学,她认为,作为信念的表达,因此是断言的变种,构成句也受制于知识规范。巴赫和哈尼什确定了15种不同的构成句子类别,每一种都以它们所表达的信念和意图的类型为特征。 管理一个物种的规范必须至少和管理相应类型的规范一样强。因此,作为类型断言的种类,每个子范畴至少服从于KNA的必要方向。最终,我们为列表上的每一个言语行为都得出了一个知识规范,比如推测的知识规范(KNC):一个人的推测是,只有当一个人知道有理由,但没有足够的理由,相信p时,p在认识论上是允许的。大多数对各种构成词的建议解释总体上是足够合理的,尽管j·l·奥斯汀肯定不高兴看到这么多不同的言语行为被塑造成各种断言。西米恩以对猜测、讲述和道德主张的反思作为结语。当KNA和CI与直觉相关数据的兼容性得到保证时,Simion就可以从移位困境的角度来解释移位直觉的挑战,从而宣告成功。确保解释框架的经验充分性是重要的一步,但通过对最佳解释的推断来宣告胜利还为时过早。其他候选人也被证明与KNA熟悉的解释成功相匹配(包括彩票命题,摩尔语句等)。与KNA不同的是,只需要认识论上的证明或理性的信仰或信任的替代方案可以允许一个主体在认识论上正确地主张他们所相信的东西,当他们的信仰是认识论上的理性的时候,即使在他们没有意识到的失败理由的情况下。此外,这些规范似乎更适合于哲学或激烈的道德讨论,因为在这些讨论中几乎没有共识,个人通常不知道他们所断言的是真的。Simion发出警告说,诡辩困境威胁到“作为一个整体的认知规范性”(xii - xii),但关于理性信任的规范似乎特别免疫。正如Simion所指出的,她提出的规范的病因-功能模型可以用一个不同的核心认知目标来重建。事实上,密立根启发下的这些模型在哲学的其他领域也很受欢迎,在这些领域中,信息的概念占据了中心位置——这个概念可能更适合于严格的定义,并在与科学的对话中使用,而不是知识。我们也想知道,当模型以这种方式具有延展性时,病因功能模型对知识优先的认知规范性观点具有什么样的特殊权重。当我们试图将Simion的策略应用于Keith的信念或判断时,即他所断言的知识归属/否认是正确的,那么Simion保护知识上好的思考和断言免受实践变化的策略的有效性就变得不那么明显了。目前还不清楚,我们是否应该假设,在高风险的情况下,基思在认识论上应该相信/判断他所宣称的知识否认是错误的,但考虑到所有的事情,他应该相信/判断这是正确的。当然,我们不必接受,知识优先的,对断言规范性的病因功能解释,也适用于信念,但是,我们在解释基思判断的变化方面取得了什么进展他知道银行周六开的是低风险的,而不是高风险的?此外,还有其他方法可以在低赌注对和高赌注对的情况下为易错古典不变量论者生成问题。下面是一个简化版的关于实用主义侵占的辩论难题。考虑一些较低的情况,即您满足知道p的不变标准,但您的合理置信度低于确定性。在这些情况中,一定有一些情况您也满足不变标准,即知道如果p为真,那么在您的行动选择中,<s:2> -ing会产生最佳的总体结果。比如说,你有一个带有ϕ按钮的机器,你知道这个机器非常可靠,它会告诉你如果你按下按钮,p为真和p为假的成本或收益是多少。如果你的ϕ(按下ϕ按钮)是真的,你赢得100美元;如果φ和p为假,你损失100美元。你面临的选择是:φ还是不φ。既然你知道p,并且你知道如果p为真,那么在你的行动选择中,你可以合理地推断出,在你的行动选择中,<s:2> -ing会产生最佳的结果,因此你应该φ。如果你知道哪一种行动会带来最好的结果,那就是你应该做的。现在考虑高值,p的证据的数量和质量是相同的,你仍然知道你的机器是非常可靠的。然而,这一次,机器告诉你,如果你推φ,
{"title":"<i>Shifty Speech and Independent Thought: Epistemic Normativity in Context</i>","authors":"Dorit Ganson","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10469564","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10469564","url":null,"abstract":"Crafted within a knowledge-first epistemological framework, Mona Simion’s engaging and wide-ranging work ensures that both the Knowledge Norm of Assertion (KNA) and Classical Invariantism (CI) can be part of a viable and productive research program.Dissatisfied with current strategies on offer in the literature, she successfully counters objections to the pair sourced in “shiftiness intuitions”—intuitions that seem to indicate that mere changes in practical context can impact the propriety of assertions and knowledge attributions. For example, in Keith DeRose’s famous pair of low stakes versus high stakes bank cases, the consequences of Keith’s acting on The bank is open on Saturday if it were false change from trivial in low stakes to catastrophic in high stakes. We are to suppose that the proposition is true, and that Keith has access to the same quantity and quality of evidence for it in both cases. In low stakes, but not in high stakes, we are inclined to think that Keith can appropriately assert to his inquiring wife “The bank is open on Saturday.” In low stakes, Keith’s knowledge ascription “I know that the bank is open on Saturday” strikes us as aptly asserted and true. In high stakes only a knowledge denial on Keith’s part strikes us as aptly asserted and true.If we want to hang on to KNA, it looks like we will have to abandon CI and concede that ‘knows’ or knowledge is sensitive to changes in practical considerations. If we want to retain CI, we can try to say that, while Keith does still know that the bank is open on Saturday in high stakes, he does not have sufficient warrant to properly assert that it is. But such a move seems to run counter to KNA. We appear to be stuck in the Shiftiness Dilemma.Keen to get us out of the dilemma and to preserve the idea that epistemically good thinking and asserting are independent of practical concerns, Simion suggests a strategy that can also be used to protect other epistemic speech-act norms and notions from similar threats of practical shiftiness. She notes that having an impact on the degree of epistemic warrant required is not enough to make a norm an epistemic one. Fair enough. If I am given strong practical reason (a million dollars, or a gun to the head) not to adopt full belief until I have gathered more evidence, there is potentially some nonepistemic norm at work in the demand for further evidence. So it is a live possibility (indeed, a plausible one, as Simion would say) that our intuitions in the Shiftiness Dilemma are being misdescribed: they are tracking all-things-considered propriety of assertion, not epistemic propriety. In high stakes, practical norms override the epistemic norm KNA. Keith’s asserting “The bank is open on Saturday” would be epistemically proper but all-things-considered improper.Simion backs up her account with an etiological-function origin story and typology for the norms of assertion. Here is her characterization of etiological function for traits, artifacts, ","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135857681","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Sustaining Democracy: What We Owe to the Other Side 维持民主:我们对对方的亏欠
1区 哲学 Pub Date : 2023-07-01 DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10469629
Kevin Vallier
Sustaining Democracy is Robert Talisse’s well-argued follow-up to his previous book, Overdoing Democracy. Talisse has argued that American political polarization endangers democracy. The problem occurs when Americans allow their politics to become their identity and, in doing so, lose crosscutting identities, religious, familial, and civic. We not only lose the intrinsic value of those identities; we overdo democracy, and make it worse.In Sustaining Democracy, Talisse explores the political mindset that can sustain a democratic society. How must a citizen regard her opponents? The requisite attitude requires facing up to what Talisse calls the democrat’s dilemma. This is “the tension between the moral requirement to recognize the equality of political opponents and the moral directive to pursue and promote political justice” (4). This state of mind means allowing injustice to win for a time. If citizens do not allow injustice to rule, they must reject the political equality of their opponents. Our opponents see justice differently than we do. They sometimes win elections. If we insist on our own vision of justice, we will want to restrict the political equality of others. So, democratic citizens either allow injustice or violate political equality. What do we do?Talisse argues that sustaining democracy involves honoring political equality. The good citizen must recognize political equality and his biases about justice. Bearing both in mind, the good citizen can allow injustice to prevail for a time. And in doing so, he honors his opponents and sustains democracy with them.Many people fear that we must sometimes suspend democracy to promote justice, but if people are political equals, we cannot do this. Not always.Chapter 1 stresses that democracy involves political equality: politics is how equal persons govern themselves together. So democracy is a moral proposal, not merely a practical one. Citizens have to see others as part of a collective project, which means everyone gets an equal say. Indeed, they are entitled to one. That does not mean one must give in to their opponents’ views, only honor them in the democratic process. There is no complicity in injustice here. Citizens acknowledge a moral burden to discharge their civic duties to promote justice. Nonetheless, chapter 2 explains why democracy requires letting the opposition govern.Chapter 3 shows how belief polarization can exacerbate the democrat’s dilemma. Talisse suggests ways to overcome belief polarization. If Reba resists belief polarization, she can see the values and views she shared with others. Reba’s reflections may reduce her temptation to view political losses as disastrous. So she must scrutinize her own political thinking to locate her biases and correct them where she can (especially biases that lead her to delegitimize electoral victories). The belief that others misunderstand justice does not undermine the legitimacy of an election.Chapter 4 explores strategies to engag
《维持民主》是罗伯特·塔利斯继其上一本书《过度民主》之后的又一部颇有争议的著作。塔利斯认为,美国的政治两极分化危及民主。当美国人允许他们的政治成为他们的身份时,问题就出现了,在这样做的过程中,他们失去了跨领域的身份,宗教的,家庭的和公民的。我们不仅失去了这些身份的内在价值;我们过度民主,使它变得更糟。在《维持民主》一书中,塔利斯探讨了能够维持民主社会的政治心态。一个公民该如何看待她的对手?这种必要的态度要求直面塔利斯所说的民主党的困境。这就是“承认政治对手平等的道德要求与追求和促进政治正义的道德指示之间的紧张关系”(4)。这种心态意味着允许不公正在一段时间内获胜。如果公民不允许不公正统治,他们就必须拒绝对手的政治平等。我们的对手对正义的看法与我们不同。他们有时会赢得选举。如果我们坚持自己的正义观,我们就会想要限制他人的政治平等。因此,民主公民要么允许不公正,要么违反政治平等。我们该怎么办?塔利斯认为,维持民主需要尊重政治平等。好公民必须认识到政治平等和他对正义的偏见。考虑到这两点,好公民可以允许不公正盛行一段时间。在这样做的过程中,他尊重他的对手,并与他们一起维持民主。许多人担心我们有时必须暂停民主以促进正义,但如果人们在政治上是平等的,我们就不能这样做。不总是正确的。第一章强调民主涉及政治平等:政治是平等的人如何共同管理自己。因此,民主是一种道德建议,而不仅仅是一种实践建议。公民必须将他人视为集体项目的一部分,这意味着每个人都有平等的发言权。事实上,他们有资格这样做。这并不意味着一个人必须屈服于对手的观点,只是在民主进程中尊重他们。这里不存在不公正的共犯。公民认识到履行公民义务促进正义的道德责任。尽管如此,第二章解释了为什么民主需要让反对派执政。第三章阐述了信仰极化如何加剧了民主党人的困境。塔利斯提出了克服信念两极分化的方法。如果热巴能抵制信仰两极分化,她就能看到自己与他人共有的价值观和观点。热巴的反思可能会减少她将政治失败视为灾难性的诱惑。因此,她必须仔细审视自己的政治思维,找出自己的偏见,并在可能的地方纠正它们(尤其是那些导致她使选举胜利失去合法性的偏见)。认为别人误解了正义,并不会破坏选举的合法性。第4章探讨了吸引那些具有竞争党派忠诚的人的策略。这些形式的接触是有益的,但不足以维持民主政治。事实上,某些形式的政治参与会降低政体。塔利斯邀请读者认识到他们有信仰两极分化,应该对他们的政治观点进行合理的批评。第二个解决信念两极分化的方法是在我们自己和其他公民之间拉开“政治距离”。公民有时应该退出政治参与,甚至在政治问题上退居社会“孤独”。在结语中,塔利斯强调了公民对另一方的责任:成为一个更有道德、更有效的政治对手。塔利斯的书是一部公共哲学著作。读者不应期望塔利斯对专业民主理论家可能提出的每一个反对意见都予以反驳。但人们仍然可以提出担忧。我觉得塔利斯对民主党困境的阐述很有启发性。民主公民身份确实需要平衡两种道德考虑:我们对正义的看法是正确的,其他人在政治上与我们平等。只有当公民允许那些对正义有错误看法的人占上风时,紧张局势才会得到解决。至少在选举周期内是这样。诚然,严重的不公正可能会限制民主。如果一个民主总统通过承诺种族灭绝赢得选举,应该有人阻止公众选举他。但在民主政治中,这种情况比通常想象的要少。塔利斯认为,人们常常会误解别人为什么会相信自己,而且在很多情况下,他们根本不知道自己相信什么。我们可以把错误的论点和动机归咎于他们,使我们的对手看起来很可怕。民主党的困境造成了真正的认知失调。但为了尊重我们的对手,我们必须学会以那种心态生活。否则,我们将破坏而不是维持民主制度。 民主党人的困境也适用于开放社会的其他特征。自由社会面临着一个相关的言论自由困境。有些人发表冒犯性和不道德的言论,但公民为了其他社会利益而允许这样做。市场也提出了类似的挑战。人们可以买卖一些不喜欢的商品。但如果公民想要尊重彼此的财产权,即使是在混合经济中,他们也必须表现出宽容。所以,在某种程度上,塔利斯所指出的困境出现在许多情境中,塔利斯可能已经承认了。如果这种困境是一种熟悉的认知紧张,他的论点就会得到加强。我不会把民主党人的困境描述为主要涉及对正义的分歧。其他分歧也带来了这种困境。一些公民可能不会在司法框架内思考政治。一些基督徒认为福音意味着政治应该超越正义:公共政策应该关注关怀、怜悯和恩典。但这些基督教徒将遇到类似的民主困境。在塔利斯的辩护中,正义的主张可能具有独特的属性。不公正会激发情绪反应和行动,而其他分歧不会。正义必须得到伸张。当有人犯下不公正的罪行时,公民必须立即行动起来。许多社会哲学家已经认识到这一点,因此,如果我们想为塔利斯辩护,人们可以辩称,不公正使这种困境变得尖锐。读者还需要考虑对民主党困境的更广泛的回应,而不是塔利斯所提供的。想象一下你发现罗伊诉韦德案只是。但你也知道,当法官决定有争议的问题时,他们扭曲了我们的政治。人们只会根据司法候选人投票给那些令人讨厌的政客,从而忽视了其他重要问题。公民们在短期内面临着民主党的困境:有时反堕胎或支持堕胎的总统会获胜,他们的法官会获胜。但有人可能会说,如果公众将堕胎政策下放,民主党的困境在联邦层面就会消失。公民可以在全国选举中把堕胎问题搁置一边,双方都不能说服自己容忍不公正的堕胎制度。他们将争端转移到各国,这些国家在这个问题上有更多的内部共识。这并不奇怪。民主社会经常分散政治决策来解决冲突。人们可能会对另一件事产生异议——即塔利斯对个人道德的关注。是的,公民必须面对真正的正义与尊重政治平等之间的紧张关系。是的,他们必须学会与之共存。但大多数人的普通态度不会因为反思民主党的困境而改变。塔利斯知道社会因素决定了我们的政治态度。有鉴于此,我发现塔利斯的建议如此注重个人,这有点奇怪。如果读者相信塔利斯的观点,她可能仍然会觉得抵抗部落势力太有挑战性。她的环境必须改变,以确保她能养成必要的心态。在这里,塔利斯再次建议我们开发横切身份。然后,如果我们加入另一个群体,我们就能从部落主义中解脱出来。这是个好建议。但我仍然担心,单边行动缺乏适当的现实主义。理论家和政策制定者还必须研究改善民主的制度改革,例如采用产生两个以上政党的选举程序。有了三个或更多的选择,人们可能会形成更微妙的政治态度。这一点和其他建议可以加起来。言下之意是,这些制度改革可能比个人行动更能维持民主。只有伴随着制度改革,塔利斯的明智建议才有可能成为现实。是的,也许一个人必须从改变态度开始。但我不确定。即使在当前的政治环境下,一些减少两极分化和提高信任的改革也可能奏效。一些人认为,改革竞选资金可以减少两极化。立法机构的议程设定者参与消极的议程设定:阻止投票,通常是为了让捐赠者和朋友受益。通过消极议程设置,立法机关可以通过审议和投票来解决争议。他们不能对解决紧迫社会问题的立法投票。但消极的议程设置(还)不是一个两极分化的问题。事实上,很少有人知道它。但这里的改革可以极大地改善民主进程。我同意塔利斯的解决方案。但塔利斯过分强调了对正义的分歧,他的解决方案过分强调了个人道德。尽管如此,《维持民主》是一位经验丰富的民主理论家写的一部深刻而清晰的作品,可以给善于反思的民主公众带来很多启示。
{"title":"<i>Sustaining Democracy: What We Owe to the Other Side</i>","authors":"Kevin Vallier","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10469629","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10469629","url":null,"abstract":"Sustaining Democracy is Robert Talisse’s well-argued follow-up to his previous book, Overdoing Democracy. Talisse has argued that American political polarization endangers democracy. The problem occurs when Americans allow their politics to become their identity and, in doing so, lose crosscutting identities, religious, familial, and civic. We not only lose the intrinsic value of those identities; we overdo democracy, and make it worse.In Sustaining Democracy, Talisse explores the political mindset that can sustain a democratic society. How must a citizen regard her opponents? The requisite attitude requires facing up to what Talisse calls the democrat’s dilemma. This is “the tension between the moral requirement to recognize the equality of political opponents and the moral directive to pursue and promote political justice” (4). This state of mind means allowing injustice to win for a time. If citizens do not allow injustice to rule, they must reject the political equality of their opponents. Our opponents see justice differently than we do. They sometimes win elections. If we insist on our own vision of justice, we will want to restrict the political equality of others. So, democratic citizens either allow injustice or violate political equality. What do we do?Talisse argues that sustaining democracy involves honoring political equality. The good citizen must recognize political equality and his biases about justice. Bearing both in mind, the good citizen can allow injustice to prevail for a time. And in doing so, he honors his opponents and sustains democracy with them.Many people fear that we must sometimes suspend democracy to promote justice, but if people are political equals, we cannot do this. Not always.Chapter 1 stresses that democracy involves political equality: politics is how equal persons govern themselves together. So democracy is a moral proposal, not merely a practical one. Citizens have to see others as part of a collective project, which means everyone gets an equal say. Indeed, they are entitled to one. That does not mean one must give in to their opponents’ views, only honor them in the democratic process. There is no complicity in injustice here. Citizens acknowledge a moral burden to discharge their civic duties to promote justice. Nonetheless, chapter 2 explains why democracy requires letting the opposition govern.Chapter 3 shows how belief polarization can exacerbate the democrat’s dilemma. Talisse suggests ways to overcome belief polarization. If Reba resists belief polarization, she can see the values and views she shared with others. Reba’s reflections may reduce her temptation to view political losses as disastrous. So she must scrutinize her own political thinking to locate her biases and correct them where she can (especially biases that lead her to delegitimize electoral victories). The belief that others misunderstand justice does not undermine the legitimacy of an election.Chapter 4 explores strategies to engag","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135857676","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Leibniz on Time, Space, and Relativity 莱布尼茨论时间、空间和相对论
1区 哲学 Pub Date : 2023-07-01 DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10469538
Jeffrey K. McDonough
In his impressive Leibniz on Time, Space, and Relativity, Ric Arthur manages to juggle a daunting array of tasks: tracking the chronological development of Leibniz’s views over more than half a century; explicating Leibniz’s groundbreaking mathematics; assembling texts—primary and secondary—in at least five languages; and, as if in passing, offering original translations and assessments of countless source materials. All this erudition is put to the service of offering detailed interpretations of Leibniz’s challenging theories of time, space, and motion. Arthur’s performance is a lifetime in the making, and his Leibniz on Time, Space, and Relativity is certain to be essential reading for those interested in the topics it covers for many years to come.Leibniz’s subtle theory of time defies easy summary. According to Arthur, Leibniz’s theory of time is ultimately grounded in relations among states of substances. States of substances are representations of a world from a perspective. States that do not contradict one another occur at the same time. States that do contradict one another are successive. Among successive states, some provide reasons for others. A state that provides a reason for another state is temporally prior to that state. One thing exists before, after, or at the same time as another thing not because of the way both things are related to some special, independent third thing—namely, time—but rather because of the relations they bear to one another (and other similar things). A occurs before, after, or at the same time as B because of the relations between A and B. For Arthur’s Leibniz, time itself is an abstract ordering relation that structures not only all actual temporal relations but also all possible temporal relations. It guarantees not only that my fifth birthday must precede my fiftieth but also that my fiftieth must precede my merely possible five hundredth.Is Leibniz eliminating time? Many commentators have thought so. Leibniz was a nominalist, and nominalists typically deny that abstract objects exist. In holding that time is abstract, mustn’t Leibniz also hold that time doesn’t really exist? “No,” says Arthur. Abstract objects, for Leibniz, have a home in the “divine mind” (61). Thus, while the abstract structure that orders all possible existing things can’t itself exist in the concrete world, that doesn’t mean that it doesn’t exist at all. Furthermore, and perhaps even more importantly, the temporal relations holding between things in the world are not abstract. Even if time itself were not real, Arthur’s Leibniz would still insist that my fifth birthday occurred before my fiftieth birthday and at roughly the same time as my older brother’s seventh birthday. Even if time is abstract, temporal relations are not.But wait, doesn’t Leibniz also hold that relations are ideal? And in holding that temporal relations are ideal, isn’t Leibniz suggesting that temporal relations themselves are not real? Again, Arthur thinks no
在《莱布尼茨论时间、空间和相对论》这本令人印象深刻的书中,里克·阿瑟设法处理了一系列令人望而生畏的任务:追踪半个多世纪以来莱布尼茨观点的时间顺序发展;解释莱布尼茨开创性的数学;汇编至少五种语言的小学和中学文本;而且,似乎是顺带提供了对无数原始材料的原始翻译和评估。所有这些博学都是为了对莱布尼茨具有挑战性的时间、空间和运动理论提供详细的解释。亚瑟的表演是一生的成就,他的《莱布尼茨论时间、空间和相对论》肯定是那些对它所涵盖的主题感兴趣的人在未来许多年里必不可少的读物。莱布尼茨精妙的时间理论难以简单概括。根据亚瑟的说法,莱布尼茨的时间理论最终建立在物质状态之间的关系上。物质状态是从一个角度来表征一个世界。不相互矛盾的状态同时出现。相互矛盾的状态是连续的。在历届州中,有些州为其他州提供了理由。一种状态为另一种状态提供了理由,这种状态在时间上先于另一种状态。一个事物在另一个事物之前、之后或同时存在,不是因为这两个事物与某个特殊的、独立的第三个事物——即时间——的关系,而是因为它们彼此之间(以及其他类似事物)的关系。由于A和B之间的关系,A在B之前、之后或同时发生。对于阿瑟的莱布尼茨来说,时间本身是一种抽象的有序关系,它不仅构建了所有实际的时间关系,也构建了所有可能的时间关系。它不仅保证我的五岁生日必须在我五十岁之前,而且保证我的五十岁生日必须在我可能的五百岁之前。莱布尼茨消除了时间吗?许多评论人士都这么认为。莱布尼茨是一位唯名论者,而唯名论者通常否认抽象对象的存在。在认为时间是抽象的同时,莱布尼茨难道不能也认为时间是不存在的吗?“不,”阿瑟说。对莱布尼茨来说,抽象的物体在“神圣的心灵”中有一个家(61)。因此,虽然对所有可能存在的事物进行排序的抽象结构本身不能存在于具体世界中,但这并不意味着它根本不存在。此外,也许更重要的是,世界上事物之间的时间关系并不是抽象的。即使时间本身不是真实的,阿瑟的莱布尼茨仍然坚持认为,我的五岁生日发生在我五十岁生日之前,与我哥哥的七岁生日大致相同。即使时间是抽象的,时间关系也不是。等等,莱布尼茨不也认为关系是理想的吗?莱布尼茨认为时间关系是理想的,这不是在暗示时间关系本身不是真实的吗?阿瑟还是不这么认为。他认为,虽然“莱布尼茨否认关系作为自身实体的现实性,但他并没有因此否认关系事实的现实性,例如物质的两种状态一个接一个地发生的事实”(61)。假设柏拉图比亚里士多德更老。由于种种原因,莱布尼茨认为,柏拉图和亚里士多德之间的任何关系既不能单独存在于柏拉图身上,也不能单独存在于亚里士多德身上,也不能同时存在于两者身上。因此,柏拉图和亚里士多德之间的任何关系,都必须至少部分地建立在对他们两人都加以考虑的思想基础之上。在莱布尼茨看来,关系正是这种意义上的理想。但“柏拉图比亚里士多德老”仍然是正确的,即使没有人考虑柏拉图和亚里士多德。柏拉图比亚里士多德更老,这是基于柏拉图的内在本质和亚里士多德的内在本质。旧比关系在形而上学上是理想的,但关系的“事实”却不是。亚瑟的莱布尼茨对时间的基础有一种复杂的看法,但亚瑟认为——我同意——说莱布尼茨意味着消除时间是不准确的。亚瑟认为莱布尼茨也有类似的空间观。莱布尼茨在与塞缪尔·克拉克的著名书信往来中,将他成熟的空间(和时间)观与牛顿的观点进行了对比。笼统地说,克拉克和牛顿认为空间是一个固定不变的背景。物体通过与空间区域的搭配而存在于空间中。物体通过在不同时间与空间的不同区域搭配而在空间中移动。莱布尼茨与这种观点相反,并与他自己对时间的理解保持一致,他认为存在的事物彼此之间存在着直接的空间关系。与时间一样,一件事物与另一件事物具有空间性,不是因为两者都与某些特殊的、独立的第三件事物(即空间)相关,而是因为它们彼此之间(以及其他类似事物)的关系。 人们很容易认为,要么莱布尼茨的等量假设是对罗马权力的虚伪奉承,要么莱布尼茨对哥白尼主义的承诺是心虚的——例如,莱布尼茨只是将哥白尼主义视为众多可能体系中的一种。在亚瑟的阅读中,莱布尼茨对几何运动和因果运动的区分提出了一条更令人满意的中间道路。莱布尼茨确实认为,从几何学的观点来看,哥白尼学说应该仅仅是众多可能体系中的一种。他确实相信,从几何学的角度来看,即使是天使也不能说,行星或太阳是在运动的。从几何的角度来看,这样的问题根本没有意义。但从因果关系的角度来看,它们确实是有道理的,从因果关系的角度来看,我们可以对哪些物体真正在运动做出更好或更坏的假设。因此,莱布尼茨可以连贯地坚持,从几何的观点来看,哥白尼学说只是众多可能体系中的一种,而从因果的观点来看,哥白尼学说是我们最好的假设,行星确实在运动,太阳确实是静止的。在亚瑟的阅读中,即使莱布尼茨的语言是和解的,他对哥白尼主义的承诺也没有怯懦。莱布尼茨的《论时间、空间和相对论》是学术上的杰作。它在历史上、哲学上和技术上都很丰富。(我有没有提到,它包括一系列附录,其中包括正式的论述,亚瑟王背景观点的详细说明,以及原始翻译?甚至还有一个专业术语表!)应该承认,这不是一本轻松的书。虽然写得很清楚,组织也很好,但篇幅很长,内容很详细。它的封面之间有足够的材料至少三本重要的书,每个主要主题一本。的确,书中充满了论点、文本注释和学术细节,以至于人们可能会忍不住认为,在数学家的意义上,它是密集的,在任何两个哲学论点、笔记或学术细节之间,人们总能找到另一个论点、笔记或学术细节。对于那些对学术鉴赏家和对莱布尼茨、早期现代哲学或时空哲学感兴趣的人来说,亚瑟的杰作保证了一个密集但无穷无尽的乐趣系列。对待自己。
{"title":"<i>Leibniz on Time, Space, and Relativity</i>","authors":"Jeffrey K. McDonough","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10469538","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10469538","url":null,"abstract":"In his impressive Leibniz on Time, Space, and Relativity, Ric Arthur manages to juggle a daunting array of tasks: tracking the chronological development of Leibniz’s views over more than half a century; explicating Leibniz’s groundbreaking mathematics; assembling texts—primary and secondary—in at least five languages; and, as if in passing, offering original translations and assessments of countless source materials. All this erudition is put to the service of offering detailed interpretations of Leibniz’s challenging theories of time, space, and motion. Arthur’s performance is a lifetime in the making, and his Leibniz on Time, Space, and Relativity is certain to be essential reading for those interested in the topics it covers for many years to come.Leibniz’s subtle theory of time defies easy summary. According to Arthur, Leibniz’s theory of time is ultimately grounded in relations among states of substances. States of substances are representations of a world from a perspective. States that do not contradict one another occur at the same time. States that do contradict one another are successive. Among successive states, some provide reasons for others. A state that provides a reason for another state is temporally prior to that state. One thing exists before, after, or at the same time as another thing not because of the way both things are related to some special, independent third thing—namely, time—but rather because of the relations they bear to one another (and other similar things). A occurs before, after, or at the same time as B because of the relations between A and B. For Arthur’s Leibniz, time itself is an abstract ordering relation that structures not only all actual temporal relations but also all possible temporal relations. It guarantees not only that my fifth birthday must precede my fiftieth but also that my fiftieth must precede my merely possible five hundredth.Is Leibniz eliminating time? Many commentators have thought so. Leibniz was a nominalist, and nominalists typically deny that abstract objects exist. In holding that time is abstract, mustn’t Leibniz also hold that time doesn’t really exist? “No,” says Arthur. Abstract objects, for Leibniz, have a home in the “divine mind” (61). Thus, while the abstract structure that orders all possible existing things can’t itself exist in the concrete world, that doesn’t mean that it doesn’t exist at all. Furthermore, and perhaps even more importantly, the temporal relations holding between things in the world are not abstract. Even if time itself were not real, Arthur’s Leibniz would still insist that my fifth birthday occurred before my fiftieth birthday and at roughly the same time as my older brother’s seventh birthday. Even if time is abstract, temporal relations are not.But wait, doesn’t Leibniz also hold that relations are ideal? And in holding that temporal relations are ideal, isn’t Leibniz suggesting that temporal relations themselves are not real? Again, Arthur thinks no","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135857679","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Leveraging Distortions: Explanation, Idealization, and Universality in Science 利用扭曲:科学中的解释、理想化和普遍性
1区 哲学 Pub Date : 2023-07-01 DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10469551
H. K. Andersen
Questions about idealizations in science are often framed along the lines of, How can science be so effective when it gets so much wrong? Rice’s book, Leveraging Distortions: Explanation, Idealization, and Universality in Science offers a refinement on this framing, where we need not commit to the premise that idealizations are, in fact, wrong, that they need to be contained to the irrelevant parts of a model, or should be explained away as mere appearance. Rice takes a holist approach in which idealization is more like a process by which models as a whole are leveraged into better fit with their targets. Idealizations should not be carved out one by one on this approach; they make sense in the context of the models in which they figure, and they distort in ways that illuminate features like universal behavior in the systems being modeled. This is a refreshing approach to how idealizations work, one that does not require the common presupposition that idealizations are simply false.By universality, Rice means “the stability of certain patterns or behaviors across systems that are heterogeneous in their features. Universality classes are, then, just the group of systems that will display those universal patterns or behaviors” (155). Universality enables a more abstract description of systems than what scientists may have started with, and this process of making the description of the behavior more universal serves to identify common causal structures implemented in very different physical mediums. Different descriptions of causal relata facilitate identification of more unifying patterns of behavior. Given how often philosophers think of abstraction as somehow eliminating causation, by identifying causation too strongly with microphysical details, universality is a helpful way to bring the process of abstracting description back into contact with the way in which models inevitably involve causal structure, and how that causal structure itself can be better understood by connecting classes of systems with heterogeneous physical media and similar behavior, by showing how the more abstract descriptions of causal structure are deployed in each.There are two specific features of his view that set Rice’s book apart from most other contemporary views on idealizations. The first is the explicit emphasis on holism. Often, idealizations are isolated from models and then assessed on their own after extraction from the modeling context in which they were made. In evaluating idealizations as individual propositions removed from surrounding context, it is somewhat unsurprising that many look inaccurate. Rice aptly shows how idealization plays a key role in identifying universality behavior by distorting a whole, undecomposed model. This focus on holism and the role idealizations play in a larger modeling context helps Rice’s treatment of idealizations stand apart from many others, including those he explicitly engages with, such as Angela Potochnik (2017), Mich
关于科学中理想化的问题通常是这样的,当科学有这么多错误时,它怎么能如此有效?赖斯的书《利用扭曲:科学中的解释、理想化和普遍性》对这一框架进行了改进,我们不需要坚持理想化实际上是错误的前提,不需要将理想化包含在模型的无关部分中,也不需要将其解释为仅仅是表面现象。Rice采用了一种整体的方法,在这种方法中,理想化更像是一个过程,通过这个过程,模型作为一个整体被杠杆化,以更好地适应它们的目标。在这种方法上不应该一个接一个地进行理想化;它们在它们所处的模型环境中是有意义的,它们以扭曲的方式阐明了被建模系统中的普遍行为等特征。这是一种令人耳目一新的理想化工作方式,它不需要通常的假设,即理想化是完全错误的。Rice所说的普适性指的是“某些模式或行为的稳定性,这些模式或行为跨越了具有异质特征的系统”。那么,普遍性类就是将显示这些普遍模式或行为的一组系统”(155)。普适性使得对系统的描述比科学家开始时的描述更加抽象,这种使行为描述更加普适性的过程有助于识别在非常不同的物理介质中实现的共同因果结构。对因果关系的不同描述有助于识别更统一的行为模式。考虑到哲学家经常认为抽象是某种程度上消除因果关系,通过将因果关系过于强烈地与微观物理细节联系起来,普遍性是一种有用的方式,可以将抽象描述的过程重新与模型不可避免地涉及因果结构的方式联系起来,以及如何通过将具有异质物理介质和相似行为的系统类联系起来,更好地理解因果结构本身。通过展示因果结构的更抽象的描述是如何被部署在每个。他的观点有两个特点,使赖斯的书与大多数同时代的理想化观点不同。首先是明确强调整体论。通常,理想化是从模型中分离出来的,然后在从创建理想化的建模环境中提取出来之后,对理想化进行自己的评估。在评估理想化作为从周围环境中移除的单个命题时,许多看起来不准确并不令人惊讶。Rice恰当地展示了理想化如何通过扭曲一个完整的、未分解的模型,在识别普遍性行为方面发挥关键作用。这种对整体主义和理想化在更大的建模背景下所扮演的角色的关注,有助于Rice对理想化的处理与许多其他人区别开来,包括他明确参与的人,如Angela Potochnik (2017), Michael Strevens(2011)和Kareem Khalifa(2017)。这种方法更适合理想化在科学中的应用,因为它不需要解释许多科学中对理想化的广泛依赖。即使有人认为其他的描述成功地解释了为什么理想化可以在科学中被使用,尽管存在虚假和歪曲,但通过将其描述为明显的非理性来解释它们的广泛使用,也会让人感到不舒服。赖斯的描述并不需要从科学家猖獗地从事显然不合理的实践的框架开始,然后解释为什么它不像看起来那么糟糕。而不是不顾错误地使用理想化,理想化是可以用于解释杠杆的连贯包的一部分。使他的观点与众不同的第二个特征是:理想化是一种积极使用的工具,而不是用来解释的怪癖,也不是用来最小化的可疑承诺。通常,理想化被视为某种代表性的失败,是对认知局限性的一种补偿。在一个认识论上更完美的世界里,根据这种思维,理想化可以被废除。赖斯把这一点颠倒过来:理想化不是我们必须忍受或顺从的东西;它们是一个关键的工具,可以积极地用于产生解释和建立理解体系。这就是标题中“利用”部分的由来:积极地依赖理想化来实现建模技术,否则这是不可能的。它们是一个杠杆,通过它可以使模型更好地对齐。理想化的这种积极特性说明了理想化作为一种特性而不是缺陷的优势。 Rice提出了一些非常明确的观点,说明为什么必须从整体上看待模型,并巩固了他的观点,即理想化是那些模型中的扭曲,当通过尝试分解而脱离上下文时,这些模型就没有意义了。普遍性,这是Rice的其他工作之后的一个艺术术语(例如,Rice 2018, 2019;Batterman and Rice 2014),在第6章给出了详细的处理。本章列出了一些详细的案例研究,并说明了在理想化中所涉及的整体扭曲是如何在模型中传达或捕获特定模态信息的。第7章继续讨论Rice在其他地方写过的主题:多尺度模型以及如何将普适性纳入尺度和重整化的考虑。第8章继续考虑模型如何提供理解,即使它们没有通过提供解释来提供理解。赖斯的例子涉及到一些科学家解释不完整的情况,所以有些人可能认为这些已经是解释了,因为人们不需要一个解释完全完整才能算作一个解释。本章还将理解与现实主义和科学进步联系起来。理想化常常被视为现实主义的失败,在现实主义中,一个原本成功的模型被分解成元素,其中一些显然在字面上不具有表征上的准确性人们可能会认为这是一个现实主义者对这一组成部分的必要方式(另一种方式是对真理的朴素对应处理通过假设模型的部分应该一对一地映射到世界的部分如果理想化没有以这种简化的方式映射,那么关于模型的现实主义就会失败)。在本章的第一部分,他利用自己对实际理解的描述,提出了一种替代现实主义的方法,这种方法的重点不是孤立的模型组件,而是模型为科学家产生的理解主体。这种理解主体,同样需要整体主义,可以作为关于由此理解的行为的实在论的认识基础。最后,在第9章中,Rice汇集了书中的所有主题,并提出了迄今为止最清晰的案例,说明理想化如何被用作“整体扭曲”,这不仅是科学的一部分,而且是建模技术在提供解释和理解方面的成功的核心和积极贡献。这一章是一个很好的结论,汇集了书中的不同主题。许多其他主题是Rice在其他地方写过的,这一结语有助于理解所有这些工作所适合的概要性项目。如果有人用这段经文来教学,这可能是一个很好的开始,而不是结束的章节。总的来说,这本书做得很好,汇集了Rice以前的工作,同时也扩展了新的例子和更详细的工作,并以一种有凝聚力的方式将不同的主题联系起来,围绕整体主义和理想化作为整体模型扭曲的方向。这使得它成为一系列关于解释、模型、理解和现实主义的当代讨论的一个很好的补充,也是研究生进入这些主题的一个很好的起点。
{"title":"<i>Leveraging Distortions: Explanation, Idealization, and Universality in Science</i>","authors":"H. K. Andersen","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10469551","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10469551","url":null,"abstract":"Questions about idealizations in science are often framed along the lines of, How can science be so effective when it gets so much wrong? Rice’s book, Leveraging Distortions: Explanation, Idealization, and Universality in Science offers a refinement on this framing, where we need not commit to the premise that idealizations are, in fact, wrong, that they need to be contained to the irrelevant parts of a model, or should be explained away as mere appearance. Rice takes a holist approach in which idealization is more like a process by which models as a whole are leveraged into better fit with their targets. Idealizations should not be carved out one by one on this approach; they make sense in the context of the models in which they figure, and they distort in ways that illuminate features like universal behavior in the systems being modeled. This is a refreshing approach to how idealizations work, one that does not require the common presupposition that idealizations are simply false.By universality, Rice means “the stability of certain patterns or behaviors across systems that are heterogeneous in their features. Universality classes are, then, just the group of systems that will display those universal patterns or behaviors” (155). Universality enables a more abstract description of systems than what scientists may have started with, and this process of making the description of the behavior more universal serves to identify common causal structures implemented in very different physical mediums. Different descriptions of causal relata facilitate identification of more unifying patterns of behavior. Given how often philosophers think of abstraction as somehow eliminating causation, by identifying causation too strongly with microphysical details, universality is a helpful way to bring the process of abstracting description back into contact with the way in which models inevitably involve causal structure, and how that causal structure itself can be better understood by connecting classes of systems with heterogeneous physical media and similar behavior, by showing how the more abstract descriptions of causal structure are deployed in each.There are two specific features of his view that set Rice’s book apart from most other contemporary views on idealizations. The first is the explicit emphasis on holism. Often, idealizations are isolated from models and then assessed on their own after extraction from the modeling context in which they were made. In evaluating idealizations as individual propositions removed from surrounding context, it is somewhat unsurprising that many look inaccurate. Rice aptly shows how idealization plays a key role in identifying universality behavior by distorting a whole, undecomposed model. This focus on holism and the role idealizations play in a larger modeling context helps Rice’s treatment of idealizations stand apart from many others, including those he explicitly engages with, such as Angela Potochnik (2017), Mich","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135857680","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Democratic Law 民主法
1区 哲学 Pub Date : 2023-07-01 DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10469616
Melissa Schwartzberg
The question of how communities may author their own laws, thereby manifesting autonomy (“self-legislation”), arises throughout the history of political thought. In Democratic Law, her Berkeley Tanner Lectures, Seana Valentine Shiffrin offers a distinguished contribution to this long inquiry: she argues that law’s value within democratic societies rests on its communicative capacity, enabling citizens to express their recognition of each other’s equal status.Following an insightful introduction by editor Hannah Ginsborg, Shiffrin’s first lecture, “Democratic Law,” provides the philosophical groundwork for the rest of the volume. Shiffrin characterizes democracy as a system that treats its members with equal concern and respect, and one that enables its citizens to serve as the “equal and exclusive co-authors” of its legal norms and directives (20). Law plays a distinctive and crucial role on this account because it allows us to identify and to communicate our shared moral commitments. Foremost among these joint commitments is that members are due equal recognition of their status as citizens (51) and each of us must intend to convey respect for each other as equal comembers (31). We cannot do so severally, given the scope of the community, but neither can we satisfy our obligation merely by endorsing or complying with existing norms (31–32, 38). Rather, “each of us needs to perform (and receive) a form of communicative action that enacts and thereby expresses our commitment to the respectful treatment that each of us merits as a moral equal and a joint member of our social cooperative venture” (39). Shiffrin argues that law—quotidian or constitutional, common or statutory—is the central means of discharging this communicative duty.The second half of the volume features two lectures on legal applications, “Democratic Law and the Erosion of Common Law” and “Constitutional Balancing and State Interests.” The former focuses on what might seem to be a minor, technical Supreme Court decision concerning frequent-flier programs, yet Shiffrin persuasively argues that it raises far-reaching concerns about the nature of public commitments. The question in Northwest, Inc. v. Ginsberg is whether a federal statute, the Airline Deregulation Act, preempts a state rule of common law by which parties to a contract have an implied covenant of good faith and fair dealing. Shiffrin objects to Justice Alito’s opinion for a unanimous court in Ginsberg for two main reasons. First, it wrongly characterizes the duty of good faith and fair dealing as subject to preemption, as a form of state action around which the parties could not contract, rather than characterizing the duty as pertaining to the underlying meaning of voluntary agreements (74–75). By incorporating a duty of good faith into contract law, a democratic society expresses the value of keeping commitments to each other, and that respect for each other as citizens means not deliberately acting to undermine the
社区如何制定自己的法律,从而体现自治(“自我立法”)的问题贯穿于整个政治思想史。Seana Valentine Shiffrin在伯克利坦纳讲座(Berkeley Tanner Lectures)的《民主法》(Democratic Law)中,对这一漫长的探究做出了杰出的贡献:她认为,在民主社会中,法律的价值取决于它的沟通能力,使公民能够表达对彼此平等地位的认可。在编辑汉娜·金斯伯格(Hannah Ginsborg)富有洞察力的介绍之后,西弗林的第一讲“民主法”为本书的其余部分提供了哲学基础。Shiffrin将民主描述为一种以平等的关心和尊重对待其成员的制度,并使其公民能够成为其法律规范和指令的“平等和唯一的共同作者”(20)。在这方面,法律发挥着独特而关键的作用,因为它使我们能够识别和交流我们共同的道德承诺。在这些共同承诺中,最重要的是各成员作为公民的地位应得到平等承认(51),我们每一个成员都必须打算表达对彼此作为平等成员的尊重(31)。鉴于社区的范围,我们不能单独这样做,但我们也不能仅仅通过赞同或遵守现有规范来履行我们的义务(31 - 32,38)。相反,“我们每个人都需要执行(并接受)一种形式的交流行为,这种行为制定并因此表达了我们对尊重对待的承诺,我们每个人都应该作为道德平等者和我们社会合作事业的共同成员得到尊重对待”(39)。Shiffrin认为,日常法或宪法法,普通法或成文法是履行这种沟通义务的主要手段。下半部分有两个关于法律应用的讲座,“民主法与普通法的侵蚀”和“宪法平衡与国家利益”。前者关注的是最高法院关于常旅客计划的一项看似微不足道的技术性裁决,但Shiffrin令人信服地辩称,它引发了对公共承诺性质的深远关注。Northwest, Inc.诉Ginsberg案的问题在于,联邦法规《航空公司放松管制法》(Airline Deregulation Act)是否优先于州普通法规定,即合同各方有诚信和公平交易的默示契约。希夫林反对阿利托大法官关于金斯伯格案一致判决的意见,主要有两个原因。首先,它错误地将诚实信用和公平交易的义务定性为优先原则,将其定性为一种各方不能围绕其订立合同的国家行为形式,而不是将其定性为与自愿协议的基本含义有关(74-75)。通过将诚信义务纳入合同法,民主社会表达了对彼此信守承诺的价值,以及作为公民相互尊重意味着不故意采取行动破坏我们达成的协议的目的。其次,阿利托大法官的意见认为,就《美国残疾人法》的优先条款而言,成文法和普通法实际上是相同的,忽视了普通法作为一种“集体道德表达”形式的独特价值(84)。正如Shiffrin所指出的,最高法院最近扩大了联邦优先购买权的范围,取代了普通法的发展和衔接。由于这种演变主要发生在州法院(特别是在合同法方面),对普通法的优先适用破坏了“地方社会道德文化”的发展(87)。在第三讲中,Shiffrin转向了“宪法平衡”,即法院权衡宪法利益与国家利益。她提出了一个重要的问题,即国家拥有利益到底意味着什么,而不仅仅是这种利益是否足够引人注目,足以与岌岌可危的宪法利益相平衡。在这里,她表达了对“自由裁量利益”的特别关注,即国家行为者可以接受或促进但不需要推进的利益,而不是“强制性利益”。她考虑了仅仅认定一个国家的自由裁量性利益是否足以确定一个国家实际上为了宪法平衡的目的而拥有这样的利益,并给出了否定的答案:一个国家必须表现出对这种利益的承诺,随着时间的推移,以一种有目的和连贯的方式发展,因为它在平衡测试中值得重视。 必须提供国家利益的“力量和诚意”的证据(122),这可能需要证明一个国家已经采取了认真的方法来确保利益,包括回答有关国家采取了明显与所主张的利益不一致的措施的指控(在她的例子中,一个声称保护生命的无条件利益以禁止协助自杀的国家不能同时允许死刑[103])。希夫林的特点是,这些演讲都有精彩的论述。然而,可能是由于讲课类型的原因,Shiffrin并没有真正将她的合著概念置于现有的关于群体代理、共同承诺和共同意图的文献中。关于这些主题有相当多的哲学研究,学者们,尤其是菲利普·佩蒂特(Philip Pettit, 2012),近年来对其对民主的影响进行了有益的研究。政治理论家已经转向迈克尔·布拉特曼(1999)和玛格丽特·吉尔伯特(1996),将民主进程的维度描述为一种共同的有意实践,包括安娜·斯蒂尔兹(2009)关于国家价值的研究,乔西亚·奥伯(2017)关于集体自治的研究,艾米丽·布斯·查普曼(2022)关于选举的研究,以及埃里克·比尔博姆(2012),他特别引用了共同有意作者来解释个人在不公正中的共谋行为。在这些论述中,Shiffrin的贡献是与众不同的,部分原因是她对合著者的描述非常苛刻,她从理想理论的立场出发,提出了“民主和法律在一个国家中扮演什么角色,这个国家的制度在其他方面表现出物质和精神形式的正义,其公民在很大程度上支持正义原则及其实例”(20)。一个自然的担忧是,因为Shiffrin对共同作者的描述以对正义原则的共同认可为前提,这可能意味着共同承诺实际上发生在这个早期阶段,而不是通过立法活动,或者立法的交流行为只是重新描述了这种认可。因此,第二节和第三节课——在非理想理论中——应该通过展示当代民主国家,如美国,虽然不具备这样的条件,但仍然可以实现合作,如果不完美的话——来回应这种担忧。这里出现了一些困难。首先,在第一讲中,Shiffrin认为,要使法律成为民主的,“参与的条件本身必须是平等的,在一些显著的描述下,否则信息将不是我们每个人的,参与结构将至少部分地相信我们相互平等的信息”(39)。然而在第二和第三讲中,Shiffrin转而认为平等参与是不必要的,这对整个论证的连贯性提出了一些挑战。Shiffrin的对话者注意到了这个问题。像其他坦纳讲座卷一样,这本书也有评论:在这种情况下,哲学家尼科·科洛德尼、法律学者理查德·r·w·布鲁克斯和政治理论家安娜·斯蒂茨的杰出贡献。Kolodny和Stilz都提出了反对意见,除了其他之外,尽管Shiffrin坚持认为参与民主法律的创造需要我们每个人都有机会参与到交流中来,并且是公开的(否则信息就不是我们每个人的),但她并没有要求我们有平等的发言权。正如科洛德尼所指出的,我们被要求以平等的身份交流,这样做似乎对我们成员的道德生活非常重要,因为他们的自尊依赖于此。如果我们不需要通过平等的发言权来做到这一点,那么这个过程似乎就会损害内容——就像Kolodny在国外制造MAGA帽子的有趣例子一样(139)。Stilz向Shiffrin施压,探讨诸如法官制定的普通法等明显不平等的制度如何能够满足平等主义的沟通义务(174-76)。和科洛德尼一样,她探讨了平等参与权是否是民主交流的基础,并询问普通法与这些权利有什么联系,部分原因是普通法起源于12世纪英国的非民主领域。回避这些担忧使Shiffrin陷入了一个艰难的境地,即捍卫普通法是一种比成文法更有效的手段,使我们每个人都能沟通平等地位。在她的第二次演讲中,Shiffrin将普通法与“立法过程的许多表现形式”进行了有利的对比(84);她认为,虽然立法机关可能受到利益集团的控制,并不成比例地对更大、更有组织的集团作出反应,但“
{"title":"<i>Democratic Law</i>","authors":"Melissa Schwartzberg","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10469616","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10469616","url":null,"abstract":"The question of how communities may author their own laws, thereby manifesting autonomy (“self-legislation”), arises throughout the history of political thought. In Democratic Law, her Berkeley Tanner Lectures, Seana Valentine Shiffrin offers a distinguished contribution to this long inquiry: she argues that law’s value within democratic societies rests on its communicative capacity, enabling citizens to express their recognition of each other’s equal status.Following an insightful introduction by editor Hannah Ginsborg, Shiffrin’s first lecture, “Democratic Law,” provides the philosophical groundwork for the rest of the volume. Shiffrin characterizes democracy as a system that treats its members with equal concern and respect, and one that enables its citizens to serve as the “equal and exclusive co-authors” of its legal norms and directives (20). Law plays a distinctive and crucial role on this account because it allows us to identify and to communicate our shared moral commitments. Foremost among these joint commitments is that members are due equal recognition of their status as citizens (51) and each of us must intend to convey respect for each other as equal comembers (31). We cannot do so severally, given the scope of the community, but neither can we satisfy our obligation merely by endorsing or complying with existing norms (31–32, 38). Rather, “each of us needs to perform (and receive) a form of communicative action that enacts and thereby expresses our commitment to the respectful treatment that each of us merits as a moral equal and a joint member of our social cooperative venture” (39). Shiffrin argues that law—quotidian or constitutional, common or statutory—is the central means of discharging this communicative duty.The second half of the volume features two lectures on legal applications, “Democratic Law and the Erosion of Common Law” and “Constitutional Balancing and State Interests.” The former focuses on what might seem to be a minor, technical Supreme Court decision concerning frequent-flier programs, yet Shiffrin persuasively argues that it raises far-reaching concerns about the nature of public commitments. The question in Northwest, Inc. v. Ginsberg is whether a federal statute, the Airline Deregulation Act, preempts a state rule of common law by which parties to a contract have an implied covenant of good faith and fair dealing. Shiffrin objects to Justice Alito’s opinion for a unanimous court in Ginsberg for two main reasons. First, it wrongly characterizes the duty of good faith and fair dealing as subject to preemption, as a form of state action around which the parties could not contract, rather than characterizing the duty as pertaining to the underlying meaning of voluntary agreements (74–75). By incorporating a duty of good faith into contract law, a democratic society expresses the value of keeping commitments to each other, and that respect for each other as citizens means not deliberately acting to undermine the ","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135857675","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Reasons First 原因第一
1区 哲学 Pub Date : 2023-07-01 DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10469603
Eva Schmidt
Mark Schroeder’s latest book delves deeper into the topic of normativity and reasons, while moving his focus from ethics to epistemology. His central aims are, first, to argue that theorizing in normative epistemology profits from comparison with other normative domains (his “Core Hypothesis” [9]); and second, to defend a picture of epistemic normativity that puts reasons first: they can be used to explain and analyze all other epistemic normative phenomena.Part 1 of the book provides a compelling account of normative reasons as competitors (which compete in determining, for instance, what one ought to do or believe) that are act-oriented rather than outcome-oriented, and can be acted on (my reasons to φ can be the reasons for which I φ). Schroeder assumes that there are both objective reasons, which bear on the correctness of belief, and subjective reasons, which determine its rationality or justification.Part 2 aims to solve the problem of unjustified belief for Reasons First epistemology. On this view, normative standings such as justification/rationality and knowledge bottom out in epistemic reasons. Yet it seems that only justified belief or knowledge can provide a subject S with reasons, so that we cannot take reasons as fundamental. So, apparently, perceptual experience—given that it itself is neither knowledge nor justified—cannot provide us with reasons or evidence. But this cannot be right, since perceptual experience is undoubtedly a privileged source of evidence concerning our surroundings. According to Schroeder, to allow for perceptual justification, we need a world-implicating conception of perceptual evidence, as endorsed by disjunctivism, which takes evidence to entail truths about the external world. At the same time, and contrary to disjunctivism, we must conceive of such evidence as nonfactive—it does not have to be true (or consist in a relation to a truth) and so is available not only in the good case of veridical perception but also in illusion or hallucination. Whether S’s belief is rational cannot hinge on minimal differences, as implied by disjunctivism. Schroeder illustrates this with a pair of cases C1 and C2 that are identical except that in C1, S undergoes a veridical perception, and in C2, she undergoes an indistinguishable illusion. (Say, in C1, S is looking at a red ball, but in C2, she is facing a white ball that appears red due to red lighting.) But, importantly, this illusion is a one-time occurrence—S has an otherwise flawless perceptual track record in C1 and C2. In both cases, S’s belief is equally rational, or so Schroeder argues.Schroeder thus rejects disjunctivism. Instead, he endorses the apparent factive attitude view: basic perceptual reasons are—nonfactive—subjective reasons, such as the proposition that I see that the ball is red. But since they entail worldly facts (such as: the ball is red), they are nonetheless world-implicating. For me to possess the reason, it has to appear to me that I see that
马克·施罗德(Mark Schroeder)的新书深入探讨了规范性和理性的主题,同时将他的关注点从伦理学转移到了认识论。他的中心目标是,首先,论证规范认识论的理论化得益于与其他规范领域的比较(他的“核心假设”[9]);第二,为把理性放在首位的认知规范性理论辩护:理性可以用来解释和分析所有其他认知规范性现象。本书的第1部分提供了一个令人信服的说明,规范性理由作为竞争者(它们在决定,例如,一个人应该做什么或相信什么方面进行竞争),以行动为导向,而不是以结果为导向,并且可以采取行动(我φ的理由可以是我φ的理由)。施罗德认为,客观原因决定信仰的正确性,主观原因决定信仰的合理性或正当性。第二部分旨在解决理性第一认识论的不正当信仰问题。根据这一观点,正当性/合理性和知识等规范性立场在认识论推理中处于最底层。然而,似乎只有正当的信念或知识才能为主体S提供理由,所以我们不能把理由作为根本。因此,显然,知觉经验——假定它本身既不是知识也不是被证明的——不能为我们提供理由或证据。但这不可能是对的,因为感知经验无疑是我们周围环境证据的特权来源。根据施罗德的观点,为了允许知觉证明,我们需要一个包含世界的知觉证据概念,这得到了分离论的支持,它认为证据包含了关于外部世界的真理。与此同时,与分离论相反,我们必须把这样的证据想象成非事实性的——它不一定是真的(或与真理有关系),因此不仅在真实知觉的良好情况下,而且在幻觉或幻觉中都是可用的。S的信念是否理性,不能像分离论所暗示的那样取决于最小的差异。施罗德用两种情况C1和C2说明了这一点,除了在C1中,S经历了真实的感知,而在C2中,她经历了难以区分的错觉。(比如,在C1中,S正看着一个红色的球,但在C2中,她面对的是一个由于红色照明而呈现红色的白球。)但是,重要的是,这种错觉是一次性发生的——s在C1和C2中有一个完美的知觉记录。在这两种情况下,S的信念都是同样理性的,至少施罗德是这样认为的。因此,施罗德拒绝分离主义。相反,他赞同明显的事实态度观点:基本的知觉原因是非事实的主观原因,比如我看到球是红色的命题。但由于它们包含了世俗的事实(例如:球是红色的),它们仍然具有世界意义。要让我拥有理性,就必须让我看到球是红色的。在第三部分中,施罗德提出了充分性的问题——他担心认知理性的平衡本身不能恰当地决定一种信念是正当的还是知识。因为不清楚S关于p的证据要比她关于非p的证据多多少才能使她相信p是合理的或者是知识。解决这个问题似乎迫使我们放弃理性第一认识论,因为它以理性的概念为前提:我们需要的是足够的证据来证明信仰是理性的。近联系的相关问题是证明p的证据至少和证明非p的证据一样好并不总是使相信p合理化;在证据支持和反对(接近)联系的情况下,保留信念反而是理性的。相反,在实际情况中,φ的理由至少与不φ的理由同样有力,以确保φ-ing是理性的。如何解释这种差异呢?施罗德讨论的另一个谜题是由促使哲学家为实用主义侵犯辩护的案例提出的。例如,在Jason Stanley(2005)著名的银行案例中,与相应的低风险情景相比,在高风险情景中,信仰者似乎需要更多的证据才能形成合理的信念或了解。施罗德用这些和其他的谜题来论证,一定有非证据性的认知理由来反对进入理由平衡的信仰;然后,整体平衡决定了哪种态度在认识论上是合理的,从而保留了“原因第一”的认识论。反对信念的非证据性理由包括有关未来证据可获得性的事实或有关错误代价的事实——即拥有或根据错误信念行事的代价。 这样的理由是无处不在的,因此可以解释为什么在紧密联系的情况下,除了(几乎)平衡的证据理由之外,还包括反对信仰的非证据理由的总体平衡,并没有使p的信念合理化。关于充分性问题:考虑到非证据理由,认知理由的平衡本身就可以决定信仰的认知立场。忠实于他的核心假设,Schroeder通过与其他态度(如钦佩)的原因进行比较,来论证一些反对信仰的非证据性原因是正确的原因,它会影响信仰的认知论地位。为了在我们的认知经济中成功地发挥作用,信念必须敏感地考虑到正确的原因——在默认推理或作为政策问题时,为我们提供依赖的考虑因素。与信任相比,信念通过简化推理和决策来做到这一点,因为它们允许我们忽略遥远的错误可能性。根据施罗德的实用主义理智主义,关于错误的(实际的或道德的)代价的事实是反对信仰的正确理由,因为它们是信仰必须对其真理敏感的考虑因素,才能很好地发挥其认知作用。错误的代价解释了为什么在高风险的情况下,充足的证据无法证明信念是正确的:错误的代价如此之高,以至于超过了受试者的证据,以至于p.在第四部分中,施罗德详细介绍了他对知识的康德式描述。他把知识分析为良好的信念,其中信念是对主观上和客观上共同足以压倒所有反对信念的现有理由的原因的反应,从而足以使其成为理性和正确的。他通过类比正确的理性来解释行为的道德价值,并关注理性如何不仅产生某种反应的正确标准,而且作为我们可以采取行动的东西,还产生了行为良好的标准。现在,我转而对施罗德上面所概述的反对分离主义的论点进行批评。他以命题式的习语表达了感性的理由——即我们可以通过相关的命题来赋予理由,而不必受制于任何特定的理由本体论(41)。例如,短语" S看到球是红色的"同样可以用来描述S看到球是红色的心理状态或者S看到球是红色的考虑,作为她的认知原因。我担心的是,使用命题式成语会助长对分离主义的误解——也就是说,它坚持在真实感知与幻觉和幻觉之间划清界限。换句话说,命题习语鼓励了这样一种想法,即认识论的析取论者唯一能得到的形而上学析取论版本是V - V - h观点。这种误解巩固了施罗德反对分离主义的论点。让我详细说明一下。我们可以将认识论的分离论者与书中施罗德的分离论者区分开来,后者支持感知提供了实际的,暗示世界的原因的观点。相比之下,形而上学的分离主义关注的是感性经验的本质。粗略地说,它认为真实知觉是一种本质上与幻觉完全不同的精神状态。关于幻觉的进一步感知状态,它有两种类型,V V IH和VI V H (Byrne和Logue 2009: xi) V V IH认为,作为好情况的真实感知从根本上不同于错觉或幻觉的坏情况;VI v H认为,好情况包括真实知觉和幻觉,它们具有相同的性质,与幻觉的坏情况有根本区别。如果我们以命题的方式来描述由感知经验提供的原因,那么V / h的真理似乎是显而易见的。把我的视觉体验当成一个红球。一个相关的命题是球是红色的。我的经验是真实的就是这个命题是真实的,就像在知觉中一样。在幻觉和幻觉中,相关的命题被证明是错误的——例如,在幻觉中,白球看起来是红色的,尽管它不是;在幻觉中,甚至没有一个球被视觉呈现。这暗示了一种形而上学的错觉分类,幻觉是一种糟糕的情况。然而,如果我们认为知觉经验从根本上是非命题性的,而是指向对象的,那么我们很自然地就会说——用VI v h——知觉和幻觉都成功地使我们熟悉了对象。因此,我真实的和虚幻的经验都使我熟悉我面前的球。错觉仅仅涉及到物体如何呈现的错误——在这个例子中,白球被误认为是红色的。 这种感性经验的形而上学图景可以与认识论的主张相结合,即由知觉提供的原因正是我们所熟悉的对象(Brewer 2018)。对于认识论的分离主义者来说,这开启了一种可能性,即主体在虚幻和真实情
{"title":"<i>Reasons First</i>","authors":"Eva Schmidt","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10469603","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10469603","url":null,"abstract":"Mark Schroeder’s latest book delves deeper into the topic of normativity and reasons, while moving his focus from ethics to epistemology. His central aims are, first, to argue that theorizing in normative epistemology profits from comparison with other normative domains (his “Core Hypothesis” [9]); and second, to defend a picture of epistemic normativity that puts reasons first: they can be used to explain and analyze all other epistemic normative phenomena.Part 1 of the book provides a compelling account of normative reasons as competitors (which compete in determining, for instance, what one ought to do or believe) that are act-oriented rather than outcome-oriented, and can be acted on (my reasons to φ can be the reasons for which I φ). Schroeder assumes that there are both objective reasons, which bear on the correctness of belief, and subjective reasons, which determine its rationality or justification.Part 2 aims to solve the problem of unjustified belief for Reasons First epistemology. On this view, normative standings such as justification/rationality and knowledge bottom out in epistemic reasons. Yet it seems that only justified belief or knowledge can provide a subject S with reasons, so that we cannot take reasons as fundamental. So, apparently, perceptual experience—given that it itself is neither knowledge nor justified—cannot provide us with reasons or evidence. But this cannot be right, since perceptual experience is undoubtedly a privileged source of evidence concerning our surroundings. According to Schroeder, to allow for perceptual justification, we need a world-implicating conception of perceptual evidence, as endorsed by disjunctivism, which takes evidence to entail truths about the external world. At the same time, and contrary to disjunctivism, we must conceive of such evidence as nonfactive—it does not have to be true (or consist in a relation to a truth) and so is available not only in the good case of veridical perception but also in illusion or hallucination. Whether S’s belief is rational cannot hinge on minimal differences, as implied by disjunctivism. Schroeder illustrates this with a pair of cases C1 and C2 that are identical except that in C1, S undergoes a veridical perception, and in C2, she undergoes an indistinguishable illusion. (Say, in C1, S is looking at a red ball, but in C2, she is facing a white ball that appears red due to red lighting.) But, importantly, this illusion is a one-time occurrence—S has an otherwise flawless perceptual track record in C1 and C2. In both cases, S’s belief is equally rational, or so Schroeder argues.Schroeder thus rejects disjunctivism. Instead, he endorses the apparent factive attitude view: basic perceptual reasons are—nonfactive—subjective reasons, such as the proposition that I see that the ball is red. But since they entail worldly facts (such as: the ball is red), they are nonetheless world-implicating. For me to possess the reason, it has to appear to me that I see that","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135857673","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Mind and World in Aristotle’s De Anima 亚里士多德《论动物》中的精神与世界
1区 哲学 Pub Date : 2023-07-01 DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10469525
Emily Kress
Here is a fact about humans: we use our senses to pick up on things around us and our intellect to understand whatever is out there to be understood. In Mind and World in Aristotle’s De Anima, Kelsey argues that this fact is, in Aristotle’s view, in need of an explanation. He finds one in De Anima 3.8’s suggestion that “intelligence [is] form of forms, and sensibility form of sensibilia” (432a2–3; quoted on p. 2). Roughly, his proposal is that our sensibility and intelligence “enter into the very idea” of their objects; they know them because they help make them what they are (20).This is an admirably adventurous thesis, and Kelsey’s arguments for it are likewise so. A particular strength, in fact, is the way the book brings out what is at stake philosophically in familiar and seemingly obscure doctrines alike. Two highlights, which I discuss below, are its discussions of how Aristotle’s engagement with his predecessors shapes his questions (and then makes it hard to answer them) and of how his account of perceptible qualities helps him meet this challenge. This book is therefore a significant contribution to scholarship on the De Anima (DA), and it will be of great value to scholars working on Aristotle’s philosophy of mind. Part of what makes it valuable, moreover, is how it encourages us to ask better questions about core Aristotelian doctrines: while some of Kelsey’s proposals (especially his account of per se causation, which I discuss below) are provocative, they are always productively so.The introduction sets up Kelsey’s core question. It is: “What about” our sensibility and intelligence “makes” them “subject[s] of” some “attribute” (6)? What must they be they like—in their essence (8)—to know what they do? The next three chapters argue that the DA is concerned to answer this question, and, moreover, to do so in a particular way: to show why sensibility and intelligence know “real beings” as they really are—not as they appear.Kelsey’s argument for this claim is a highlight of the book. It takes off from the observation that DA 2.5 answers two foundational questions in a way that, according to DA 3.3, should be problematic. These are: (A) whether perceivers and perceptibles “are like or unlike,” and (B) “whether perceiving is a matter of ‘being affected’ or ‘altered’” (40). The difficulty is that 2.5 wants to answer that perception is (A∗) like-by-like and (B∗) a case of being altered—where 3.3 suggests that those very commitments got Aristotle’s predecessors into trouble. Those thinkers held that “both understanding and judging are held to be like a kind of perceiving” (427a17–b6), apparently because they thought these are (A∗) like-by-like and (B∗) being altered (43).This “diagnosis,” Kelsey argues, is interesting because it “connects” (A∗) and (B∗) to another question: whether “how things are” just is “how they appear” (43). (A∗), for instance, reflects the view that “our judgments are … the mere projecting of a random and fluctuating p
这是一个关于人类的事实:我们用我们的感官来感知我们周围的事物,用我们的智力来理解任何需要理解的东西。在亚里士多德的《论阿尼玛》中的《心灵与世界》中,凯尔西认为,在亚里士多德看来,这个事实需要一个解释。他在《论阿尼玛》3.8中找到了一个,即“智力是形式的形式,感性是感性的形式”(432a2-3;粗略地说,他的建议是,我们的感性和智慧“进入到它们的对象的理念之中”;他们了解他们,因为他们帮助他们成为现在的样子。这是一个令人钦佩的冒险命题,凯尔西对此的论证也同样如此。事实上,这本书的一个特别之处在于,它揭示了在熟悉的和看似模糊的教义中,哲学上的利害关系。我将在下面讨论两个重点,一是讨论亚里士多德与前人的接触如何塑造了他的问题(然后使这些问题难以回答),二是他对可感知品质的描述如何帮助他应对这一挑战。因此,这本书是对《阿尼马论》(DA)学术研究的重要贡献,对研究亚里士多德心灵哲学的学者具有重要价值。此外,本书之所以有价值,部分原因在于它鼓励我们对亚里士多德的核心学说提出更好的问题:虽然凯尔西的一些建议(尤其是他对自身因果关系的解释,我将在下面讨论)具有挑衅性,但它们总是富有成效的。引言部分提出了凯尔西的核心问题。它是:“为什么”我们的“感性和智慧”使“他们”成为“某些属性”的主体?他们必须是什么样的人——他们的本质(8)——才能知道他们在做什么?接下来的三章认为,DA关注的是回答这个问题,而且,以一种特殊的方式来回答这个问题:说明为什么感性和智力知道“真实的存在”是什么样子,而不是它们看起来的样子。凯尔西对这一观点的论证是本书的一大亮点。它源于这样一种观察,即DA 2.5以一种根据DA 3.3应该存在问题的方式回答了两个基本问题。它们是:(A)感知者和被感知者是否“相似或不同”,以及(B)“感知是‘被影响’还是‘被改变’的问题”(40)。困难在于,第2.5节要回答的是,知觉是(A *)同类的知觉,(B *)被改变的知觉——而第3.3节指出,正是这些行为使亚里士多德的前人陷入麻烦。那些思想家认为“理解和判断都被认为是类似于一种感知”(427a17-b6),显然是因为他们认为这两者是(a *)相似的,(B *)被改变的(43)。Kelsey认为,这个“诊断”很有趣,因为它将(A∗)和(B∗)与另一个问题“联系起来”:“事物是怎样的”是否只是“它们是怎样出现的”(43)。例如,(A *)反映了这样一种观点,即“我们的判断……仅仅是我们自身随机和波动部分的投射”,因此,我们的“判断”就像我们一样,而不是事物的本来面貌(45)。并且(B *)(粗略地)表达了这样一种观点,即在获得我们赖以感知和判断的状态时,我们的判断会变得不同(因为我们被改变了),而不是更好。这就把由此产生的判断——也包括变化——都“平起平坐”,因此所有的表象都是真实的(47-49)。结论是,(A)和(B)的背后是一个问题,即知识和知觉是否了解事物的本来面目。那么,2.5怎么能有把握地宣称感知是相似的,是被改变的呢?Kelsey的回答是,它修正了(A∗)和(B∗)以避免3.3指出的困难。(A *)的改进版本被证明是一种观点的应用,即“受到某物的影响是指已经成为影响因素在使事物成为那样的事情”(53)。这一原则随后发挥了重要作用:将其应用于感知,它意味着它属于“自然可见的颜色”。这意味着我们与我们所感知的事物相似,因为它们的本性使我们与它们相似——因此我们感知它们的是它们的本来面目,而不是它们的表象(54-55)。(B *)也得到了同样的限定:一种被改变的方式——感知者在感知中体验到的——是“忙于[某人]指定的工作”。这是一个具有重要意义的巧妙论点。一个是对2.5对(a)和(B)的重要性有了更丰富的认识。另一个是对亚里士多德因果关系本身理论所能做的工作有了更清晰的认识,以及我们需要提出的问题。这是从Kelsey关于“被某物影响就是成为影响者在创造事物中所扮演的角色”这一原则的讨论中出现的,他将这一原则解释为“(除了意外)事物相互作用的方式符合它们各自的性质”(54)。 凯尔西对这一原则的描述是对文献的一个受欢迎和重要的补充,它无疑会引发辩论。在凯尔西的表述中,这个原则是相当有力的——事实上,为了证明我们能看到颜色的本质这一主张是正确的,它需要是强有力的。凯尔西的观点似乎是,这个原则让我们能够充分说明代理人对病人行使某种权力所产生的影响,并从中读出这种权力的正确说明。在Kelsey的例子中,“人行道并不是碰巧为汽车提供了一个平稳的行驶,这就是它的作用”(54)。路面的作用是让你平稳地行驶,因为它本身就有这种能力。(因此,代理的“业务”是它拥有的“使事物成为现实的能力”——它的“定义工作”[53])。如果这是正确的,那么我们就有压力确保我们以正确的方式读出代理人的权力所产生的影响。至少,我们必须找到其本身的影响。毕竟,虽然泥滩确实能让汽车平稳行驶,但它们本身对汽车的影响是另一回事——因为与人行道不同,泥滩肯定没有让汽车平稳行驶的能力。我们从中得到的教训是,我们对效果的描述应该忽略那些认为行为人有能力做不到的事情。然而,这种锐化可能会让我们怀疑这样一种观点,即在被感知的过程中,一个可感知的物体行使了一种向有知觉的生物“揭示自身”的力量(55)——这一主张是凯尔西最终观点的重要基础,即感性是可感知物体形式的一部分。另一个问题是关于如何最好地描述亚里士多德和他的前辈关于(A *)的辩证法。在Kelsey第3.3节的讨论中,相似性的关联词是“做出判决的人的品质”和他们做出的“判决”(“法官‘看到’的东西”)(45)。在他对第2.5节的讨论中,它们是“有知觉的生物”和“它们感知的对象”——“它们之所以出现,部分是由于它们自身的某些东西”(54-55)。这两种表述提出了一个有趣的问题,即亚里士多德在多大程度上维持了他的前辈对解释的描述:如果客体以这种方式“出现”是我们的“结论”,他将保留了他的前辈对关系的表述,并修改了他对它们相似性的解释——但如果这是它们在感知时对有知觉的生物的影响,他也将修改他们对关系的概念。有了这些基础,接下来的两章将介绍凯尔西对他最初问题的回答中的两个成分。第一个是建立在他的同类因果关系的基础上;他认为,这需要“形式上的相似”(69)。第二种是在这些形式的基础上进行扩展,诉诸于“度量”的概念。Kelsey认为,度量不仅与已知的对象相似,而且“在概念上先于已知的对象”(85)。例如,紫色位于以“平均”或“中间”为特征的光谱上;此外,紫色的“本质”是躺在中间的“一边或另一边”(92-95)。但是,下一章认为,这种中间本身是根据感性来规定的,感性是它的尺度(参见434a9;引自第100页)。当DA 2.12将感性定义为“一种比率”(424a27-28)——它本身是一个中间(424a4-5)——它的要点是感性是一种形式,是可感知形式的尺度(103-17)。结果是感性认识紫色,因为感性“进入”了紫色的本性(90-91;参见112-17)。类似的情况也适用于智力。因此,最后两章大致认为,智力是对其对象的一种衡量,因为“表征其活动的清晰性和独特性(就其本身而言)正是”这些对象的“形式”——使它们具有可理解性的东西(154)。本节再次对我们熟悉的教
{"title":"<i>Mind and World in Aristotle’s</i> De Anima","authors":"Emily Kress","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10469525","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10469525","url":null,"abstract":"Here is a fact about humans: we use our senses to pick up on things around us and our intellect to understand whatever is out there to be understood. In Mind and World in Aristotle’s De Anima, Kelsey argues that this fact is, in Aristotle’s view, in need of an explanation. He finds one in De Anima 3.8’s suggestion that “intelligence [is] form of forms, and sensibility form of sensibilia” (432a2–3; quoted on p. 2). Roughly, his proposal is that our sensibility and intelligence “enter into the very idea” of their objects; they know them because they help make them what they are (20).This is an admirably adventurous thesis, and Kelsey’s arguments for it are likewise so. A particular strength, in fact, is the way the book brings out what is at stake philosophically in familiar and seemingly obscure doctrines alike. Two highlights, which I discuss below, are its discussions of how Aristotle’s engagement with his predecessors shapes his questions (and then makes it hard to answer them) and of how his account of perceptible qualities helps him meet this challenge. This book is therefore a significant contribution to scholarship on the De Anima (DA), and it will be of great value to scholars working on Aristotle’s philosophy of mind. Part of what makes it valuable, moreover, is how it encourages us to ask better questions about core Aristotelian doctrines: while some of Kelsey’s proposals (especially his account of per se causation, which I discuss below) are provocative, they are always productively so.The introduction sets up Kelsey’s core question. It is: “What about” our sensibility and intelligence “makes” them “subject[s] of” some “attribute” (6)? What must they be they like—in their essence (8)—to know what they do? The next three chapters argue that the DA is concerned to answer this question, and, moreover, to do so in a particular way: to show why sensibility and intelligence know “real beings” as they really are—not as they appear.Kelsey’s argument for this claim is a highlight of the book. It takes off from the observation that DA 2.5 answers two foundational questions in a way that, according to DA 3.3, should be problematic. These are: (A) whether perceivers and perceptibles “are like or unlike,” and (B) “whether perceiving is a matter of ‘being affected’ or ‘altered’” (40). The difficulty is that 2.5 wants to answer that perception is (A∗) like-by-like and (B∗) a case of being altered—where 3.3 suggests that those very commitments got Aristotle’s predecessors into trouble. Those thinkers held that “both understanding and judging are held to be like a kind of perceiving” (427a17–b6), apparently because they thought these are (A∗) like-by-like and (B∗) being altered (43).This “diagnosis,” Kelsey argues, is interesting because it “connects” (A∗) and (B∗) to another question: whether “how things are” just is “how they appear” (43). (A∗), for instance, reflects the view that “our judgments are … the mere projecting of a random and fluctuating p","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135857677","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1