Epistemic Explanations: A Theory of Telic Normativity, and What it Explains

IF 2.8 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI:10.1215/00318108-10317632
Duncan Pritchard
{"title":"<i>Epistemic Explanations: A Theory of Telic Normativity, and What it Explains</i>","authors":"Duncan Pritchard","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10317632","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"A new book by Ernest Sosa is always an event. In a philosophical age where much of the focus is on piecemeal issues, Sosa has forged ahead with a novel virtue-theoretic treatment of a range of core questions in epistemology that is self-consciously systematic. Note that ‘epistemology’ is here broadly conceived. Indeed, a key part of the Sosa project has been to enlarge the reach of mainstream epistemology and thereby draw out connections with other areas of philosophy that have hitherto been underexplored, especially ethics, philosophy of mind and action, and metaphysics. Moreover, Sosa is also unusual among contemporary philosophers in having an acute grasp of the history of the subject, which he brings to bear in support of his program. The result is an incredibly sophisticated vision of how a range of topics in epistemology fit together.1Epistemic Explanations: A Theory of Telic Normativity, and What it Explains is the new installment in Sosa’s distinctive brand of virtue epistemology. The book is organized into four parts. Part 1 is devoted to articulating the telic virtue epistemology framework that Sosa defends. In light of this framework, he explores how we should account for the undoubted importance of first-hand knowledge and understanding and how we should conceive of the relationship between the theory of knowledge and intellectual ethics. Part 2 offers a comprehensive treatment of the epistemology of suspension. Part 3 is primarily concerned with default assumptions and understanding how they lead to refinements of telic virtue epistemology. Among other things, this part defends a metaphysical hierarchy of epistemic categories that includes a discussion of what Sosa terms secure knowledge, which is a particularly important epistemic category within his framework. Part 4 builds on the account of default assumptions in part 3 by offering an extended discussion of how this bears on the Wittgenstein–Moore debate (roughly, the clash of hinge epistemology with a form of epistemic foundationalism). Like all Sosa’s work, the writing is refreshingly crisp. It is also deceptively readable, in that one can find oneself surprised at just how much philosophical ground is being covered.There is much that I agree with in this book, but I would like to take this opportunity to critically focus on Sosa’s intriguing appeal to default assumptions and how it plays out both in terms of his theory of knowledge and his approach to radical skepticism. As will be familiar to readers of Sosa’s work, he understands knowledge in terms of what he calls aptness. Roughly, a performance is apt (‘accurate because adroit’) when one’s success in the target endeavour is properly attributable to one’s manifestation of relevant skill. As applied to the epistemic realm, we thus get the idea that knowledge is apt belief—that is, one knows when one’s cognitive success (true belief) is properly attributable to one’s manifestation of relevant cognitive agency.2Sosa’s novel claim is that apt performances can legitimately presuppose certain background conditions that the agent might have no way of knowing obtain, and which might in fact obtain simply by luck. Sosa gives the example of the performance of a baseball fielder in a nighttime game who presupposes that the lighting is working (160). Sosa argues that these background conditions can be non-negligently assumed to be in place (at least if one is given no explicit reason to consider them), even if their obtaining is just a matter of luck, and hence is unsafe. Indeed, to concern oneself with the obtaining of these conditions, and thereby weaken one’s focus on the skillful task in hand, would be negligence. (The baseball fielder would likely be less effective at his game if he is concerned about whether the lighting is working safely).3When such an account of apt performance is applied to the epistemic realm in the form of apt belief, we end up with a version of relevant alternatives theory. Recall that the basic idea behind relevant alternatives theory is that in order to know we do not need to exclude all possibilities of error but just the relevant ones. The irrelevant error possibilities can be legitimately assumed to be false (i.e., without one having any specific reason to think they are false). That certainly sounds right. Knowledge can be fallible, after all (i.e., acquired via fallible processes), and hence why would it be required for knowledge that all possibility of error be excluded? If that is correct, however, then the view seems to have immediate antiskeptical import, since if any error possibility looks like it would be irrelevant in the target sense of the term it is surely radical sceptical scenarios. Accordingly, our everyday knowledge of shoes, ships, sealing wax, cabbages, and kings can be compatible with our failure to know the denials of radical skeptical hypotheses.All that we need to make this story stick is a principled account of how to delineate the relevant alternatives from the irrelevant ones. Various proposals have been offered in this regard, such as accounts in terms of the modal closeness of the error possibility, its conversational salience, and so on. Sosa is offering his own slant on this topic by arguing that apt performance, and hence apt belief, can legitimately involve assuming default assumptions and that this can be so even when those assumptions concern modally close error possibilities. So long as the default assumptions are false and the subject is given no specific reason for entertaining them, then she can nonetheless manifest apt belief and thereby acquire knowledge. Moreover, Sosa explicitly draws an antiskeptical moral from this point by claiming that everyday knowledge can legitimately coexist with our default assumption that radical skeptical hypotheses are false. As he puts it, “Conscientiously enough, without negligence or recklessness, we normally assume ourselves free of skeptical scenarios. And this assumption is proper even on the rare occasions when it is true but not known to be true and even quite unsafe” (159).Notice that in taking this line Sosa is embracing what is regarded by many as an unfortunate consequence of (a straightforward version of) relevant alternatives theory, which is the denial of the closure principle for knowledge.4 After all, one can now know everyday claims and be fully aware that they entail the denials of radical skeptical hypotheses, but be merely assuming that these denials are false. Sosa also makes a further claim that to my knowledge no other proponent of relevant alternatives theory makes (at least not explicitly anyway), which is that one’s knowledge can be unsafe and no less bona fide as a result. In particular, since it is compatible with one’s knowledge of the target proposition that the background assumptions are only luckily true, and hence could have easily been false, and since the falsity of these background assumptions can make one’s belief in the target proposition false, then one’s belief in the known target proposition can be only luckily true (i.e., it could have easily been false).I think Sosa is quite right about apt performance in general being compatible with unsafety; indeed, I take this to be a deep insight of Sosa’s work. As we can put the point, achievements (i.e., successes that are because of ability, or apt performances in Sosa’s terminology) can be modally fragile (i.e., the target success could have easily been a failure). And Sosa has put his finger on the source of the issue here: all that matters for apt performance is that the legitimate background assumptions are true—in particular, it does not matter whether they are luckily true. That is why the fielder’s apt performance is compatible with the fact that the stadium lights could have easily failed (in which case his attempted catch would have gone awry).Where I would diverge with Sosa is that I do not think the same is true of knowledge. That is, if one’s cognitive success (true belief) could have easily been failure, then it is not knowledge. Knowledge excludes luck (fragility) of this kind because it excludes high levels of epistemic risk (i.e., the epistemic risk that one’s belief is false). That is why, when one knows, one’s basis for belief is such that one could not easily be wrong, which is what safety demands. In contrast, Sosa’s proposed alternative picture would commit us to allowing that knowledge can coexist with high levels of epistemic risk. The upshot then is that knowledge is not apt belief (relatedly, knowledge is not a cognitive achievement).5Even if we grant to Sosa that apt belief (or cognitive achievement), even when unsafe, can amount to knowledge, it is not clear that this affords us a purchase on the problem of radical skepticism as he supposes. Consider what his view amounts to. We can recognize that our everyday knowledge presupposes the falsity of global error possibilities that we can never (even in principle) exclude, and yet be content to continue regardless as if we have knowledge. So long as skeptical scenarios do not in fact obtain (and even if they could very easily obtain), then our beliefs can be aptly formed even though we groundlessly presuppose that we are not radically in error, and hence can amount to knowledge. Relatedly, and in line with the rejection of closure, one can self-consciously be aware that one has knowledge of everyday propositions that one knows entail the denials of skeptical hypotheses (e.g., that one has hands) while being unable to know the entailed proposition (e.g., that one is not a BIV).While I find Sosa’s general line in epistemology very persuasive, I find the line he takes on radical skepticism deeply unpersuasive. To begin with, if radical skeptical scenarios could easily occur, then surely we are all epistemically doomed! Why would we be tempted to suppose otherwise (except unless we were already in the grip of an—undoubtedly compelling—picture that suggested this position)? But our inability to exclude them is troubling even if we do not grant that they are modally close. The worry is that if we cannot exclude them, then how can we be sure that our beliefs have satisfied any bona fide epistemic standard, even of the lowest kind? This is precisely why they are very different from normal, ‘local,’ background conditions, which do not call into question one’s general epistemic relationship to the world.In defense of his antiskeptical line, Sosa notes that “no-one is likely to entirely avoid illusion and every other perceptual error” (138). But what is the relevance of this in the context of radical skepticism? Remember that the radical sceptic is not appealing to a high epistemic standard, as if we need to be infallible in order to know. Their claim is rather that on the face of it, we have satisfied no epistemic standard at all (i.e., not even a fallible one). Consider also this remark: “Because we are essentially rational animals, we have no real option on how to proceed cognitively over the enormous span of the animal knowledge we rely on in any ordinary day” (138). I do not think anyone would dispute this, but what exactly is meant to follow? For note that even the radical sceptic can agree with such a claim. It may well be that we need to act as if we have knowledge. But that does not provide any reason for thinking that we do have knowledge.For what it is worth, I entirely agree with Sosa that we cannot know that we are not radically in error, but I do not think he correctly captures why this is so. For that, we need to embrace Wittgenstein’s conception of hinge commitments, albeit in a very different form to how Sosa conceives of this notion (see Wittgenstein 1969). Our conviction that we are not radically in error is not an assumption, nor is it an incidental lack on our parts. What is needed is an understanding of why such claims are not properly even in the market for knowledge (such that our not knowing them does not amount to ignorance). But that entails, contra Sosa, differentiating our hinge commitments from local background conditions. Wittgenstein’s point is precisely that our failure to know our hinge commitments is not a cognitive limitation on our parts, but reveals an important truth about the structure of rational evaluation, a structure that both the radical skeptic and the traditional antiskeptic (including, I would argue, Sosa) misunderstands.6 But a defense of that claim is a topic for another day.7","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"476 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":2.8000,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10317632","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

A new book by Ernest Sosa is always an event. In a philosophical age where much of the focus is on piecemeal issues, Sosa has forged ahead with a novel virtue-theoretic treatment of a range of core questions in epistemology that is self-consciously systematic. Note that ‘epistemology’ is here broadly conceived. Indeed, a key part of the Sosa project has been to enlarge the reach of mainstream epistemology and thereby draw out connections with other areas of philosophy that have hitherto been underexplored, especially ethics, philosophy of mind and action, and metaphysics. Moreover, Sosa is also unusual among contemporary philosophers in having an acute grasp of the history of the subject, which he brings to bear in support of his program. The result is an incredibly sophisticated vision of how a range of topics in epistemology fit together.1Epistemic Explanations: A Theory of Telic Normativity, and What it Explains is the new installment in Sosa’s distinctive brand of virtue epistemology. The book is organized into four parts. Part 1 is devoted to articulating the telic virtue epistemology framework that Sosa defends. In light of this framework, he explores how we should account for the undoubted importance of first-hand knowledge and understanding and how we should conceive of the relationship between the theory of knowledge and intellectual ethics. Part 2 offers a comprehensive treatment of the epistemology of suspension. Part 3 is primarily concerned with default assumptions and understanding how they lead to refinements of telic virtue epistemology. Among other things, this part defends a metaphysical hierarchy of epistemic categories that includes a discussion of what Sosa terms secure knowledge, which is a particularly important epistemic category within his framework. Part 4 builds on the account of default assumptions in part 3 by offering an extended discussion of how this bears on the Wittgenstein–Moore debate (roughly, the clash of hinge epistemology with a form of epistemic foundationalism). Like all Sosa’s work, the writing is refreshingly crisp. It is also deceptively readable, in that one can find oneself surprised at just how much philosophical ground is being covered.There is much that I agree with in this book, but I would like to take this opportunity to critically focus on Sosa’s intriguing appeal to default assumptions and how it plays out both in terms of his theory of knowledge and his approach to radical skepticism. As will be familiar to readers of Sosa’s work, he understands knowledge in terms of what he calls aptness. Roughly, a performance is apt (‘accurate because adroit’) when one’s success in the target endeavour is properly attributable to one’s manifestation of relevant skill. As applied to the epistemic realm, we thus get the idea that knowledge is apt belief—that is, one knows when one’s cognitive success (true belief) is properly attributable to one’s manifestation of relevant cognitive agency.2Sosa’s novel claim is that apt performances can legitimately presuppose certain background conditions that the agent might have no way of knowing obtain, and which might in fact obtain simply by luck. Sosa gives the example of the performance of a baseball fielder in a nighttime game who presupposes that the lighting is working (160). Sosa argues that these background conditions can be non-negligently assumed to be in place (at least if one is given no explicit reason to consider them), even if their obtaining is just a matter of luck, and hence is unsafe. Indeed, to concern oneself with the obtaining of these conditions, and thereby weaken one’s focus on the skillful task in hand, would be negligence. (The baseball fielder would likely be less effective at his game if he is concerned about whether the lighting is working safely).3When such an account of apt performance is applied to the epistemic realm in the form of apt belief, we end up with a version of relevant alternatives theory. Recall that the basic idea behind relevant alternatives theory is that in order to know we do not need to exclude all possibilities of error but just the relevant ones. The irrelevant error possibilities can be legitimately assumed to be false (i.e., without one having any specific reason to think they are false). That certainly sounds right. Knowledge can be fallible, after all (i.e., acquired via fallible processes), and hence why would it be required for knowledge that all possibility of error be excluded? If that is correct, however, then the view seems to have immediate antiskeptical import, since if any error possibility looks like it would be irrelevant in the target sense of the term it is surely radical sceptical scenarios. Accordingly, our everyday knowledge of shoes, ships, sealing wax, cabbages, and kings can be compatible with our failure to know the denials of radical skeptical hypotheses.All that we need to make this story stick is a principled account of how to delineate the relevant alternatives from the irrelevant ones. Various proposals have been offered in this regard, such as accounts in terms of the modal closeness of the error possibility, its conversational salience, and so on. Sosa is offering his own slant on this topic by arguing that apt performance, and hence apt belief, can legitimately involve assuming default assumptions and that this can be so even when those assumptions concern modally close error possibilities. So long as the default assumptions are false and the subject is given no specific reason for entertaining them, then she can nonetheless manifest apt belief and thereby acquire knowledge. Moreover, Sosa explicitly draws an antiskeptical moral from this point by claiming that everyday knowledge can legitimately coexist with our default assumption that radical skeptical hypotheses are false. As he puts it, “Conscientiously enough, without negligence or recklessness, we normally assume ourselves free of skeptical scenarios. And this assumption is proper even on the rare occasions when it is true but not known to be true and even quite unsafe” (159).Notice that in taking this line Sosa is embracing what is regarded by many as an unfortunate consequence of (a straightforward version of) relevant alternatives theory, which is the denial of the closure principle for knowledge.4 After all, one can now know everyday claims and be fully aware that they entail the denials of radical skeptical hypotheses, but be merely assuming that these denials are false. Sosa also makes a further claim that to my knowledge no other proponent of relevant alternatives theory makes (at least not explicitly anyway), which is that one’s knowledge can be unsafe and no less bona fide as a result. In particular, since it is compatible with one’s knowledge of the target proposition that the background assumptions are only luckily true, and hence could have easily been false, and since the falsity of these background assumptions can make one’s belief in the target proposition false, then one’s belief in the known target proposition can be only luckily true (i.e., it could have easily been false).I think Sosa is quite right about apt performance in general being compatible with unsafety; indeed, I take this to be a deep insight of Sosa’s work. As we can put the point, achievements (i.e., successes that are because of ability, or apt performances in Sosa’s terminology) can be modally fragile (i.e., the target success could have easily been a failure). And Sosa has put his finger on the source of the issue here: all that matters for apt performance is that the legitimate background assumptions are true—in particular, it does not matter whether they are luckily true. That is why the fielder’s apt performance is compatible with the fact that the stadium lights could have easily failed (in which case his attempted catch would have gone awry).Where I would diverge with Sosa is that I do not think the same is true of knowledge. That is, if one’s cognitive success (true belief) could have easily been failure, then it is not knowledge. Knowledge excludes luck (fragility) of this kind because it excludes high levels of epistemic risk (i.e., the epistemic risk that one’s belief is false). That is why, when one knows, one’s basis for belief is such that one could not easily be wrong, which is what safety demands. In contrast, Sosa’s proposed alternative picture would commit us to allowing that knowledge can coexist with high levels of epistemic risk. The upshot then is that knowledge is not apt belief (relatedly, knowledge is not a cognitive achievement).5Even if we grant to Sosa that apt belief (or cognitive achievement), even when unsafe, can amount to knowledge, it is not clear that this affords us a purchase on the problem of radical skepticism as he supposes. Consider what his view amounts to. We can recognize that our everyday knowledge presupposes the falsity of global error possibilities that we can never (even in principle) exclude, and yet be content to continue regardless as if we have knowledge. So long as skeptical scenarios do not in fact obtain (and even if they could very easily obtain), then our beliefs can be aptly formed even though we groundlessly presuppose that we are not radically in error, and hence can amount to knowledge. Relatedly, and in line with the rejection of closure, one can self-consciously be aware that one has knowledge of everyday propositions that one knows entail the denials of skeptical hypotheses (e.g., that one has hands) while being unable to know the entailed proposition (e.g., that one is not a BIV).While I find Sosa’s general line in epistemology very persuasive, I find the line he takes on radical skepticism deeply unpersuasive. To begin with, if radical skeptical scenarios could easily occur, then surely we are all epistemically doomed! Why would we be tempted to suppose otherwise (except unless we were already in the grip of an—undoubtedly compelling—picture that suggested this position)? But our inability to exclude them is troubling even if we do not grant that they are modally close. The worry is that if we cannot exclude them, then how can we be sure that our beliefs have satisfied any bona fide epistemic standard, even of the lowest kind? This is precisely why they are very different from normal, ‘local,’ background conditions, which do not call into question one’s general epistemic relationship to the world.In defense of his antiskeptical line, Sosa notes that “no-one is likely to entirely avoid illusion and every other perceptual error” (138). But what is the relevance of this in the context of radical skepticism? Remember that the radical sceptic is not appealing to a high epistemic standard, as if we need to be infallible in order to know. Their claim is rather that on the face of it, we have satisfied no epistemic standard at all (i.e., not even a fallible one). Consider also this remark: “Because we are essentially rational animals, we have no real option on how to proceed cognitively over the enormous span of the animal knowledge we rely on in any ordinary day” (138). I do not think anyone would dispute this, but what exactly is meant to follow? For note that even the radical sceptic can agree with such a claim. It may well be that we need to act as if we have knowledge. But that does not provide any reason for thinking that we do have knowledge.For what it is worth, I entirely agree with Sosa that we cannot know that we are not radically in error, but I do not think he correctly captures why this is so. For that, we need to embrace Wittgenstein’s conception of hinge commitments, albeit in a very different form to how Sosa conceives of this notion (see Wittgenstein 1969). Our conviction that we are not radically in error is not an assumption, nor is it an incidental lack on our parts. What is needed is an understanding of why such claims are not properly even in the market for knowledge (such that our not knowing them does not amount to ignorance). But that entails, contra Sosa, differentiating our hinge commitments from local background conditions. Wittgenstein’s point is precisely that our failure to know our hinge commitments is not a cognitive limitation on our parts, but reveals an important truth about the structure of rational evaluation, a structure that both the radical skeptic and the traditional antiskeptic (including, I would argue, Sosa) misunderstands.6 But a defense of that claim is a topic for another day.7
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
认识论解释:一种目的性规范理论及其解释
我们所需要做的就是有原则地描述如何从不相关的选项中区分出相关的选项。在这方面,人们提出了各种各样的建议,例如从错误可能性的模态接近度、会话显著性等方面进行描述。索萨在这个话题上提出了他自己的观点,他认为恰当的表现,因此恰当的信念,可以合理地涉及假设默认假设,即使这些假设涉及模态接近的错误可能性,也是如此。只要预设的假设是错误的,并且受试者没有被给予接受这些假设的具体理由,那么她仍然可以表现出恰当的信念,从而获得知识。此外,索萨从这一点上明确地得出了一个反怀疑主义的道德,他声称日常知识可以合理地与我们的默认假设共存,即激进的怀疑假设是错误的。正如他所说,“足够认真,没有疏忽或鲁莽,我们通常假设自己没有怀疑的情况。”这种假设是正确的,即使是在极少数情况下,当它是正确的,但不知道是正确的,甚至是相当不安全的”(159)。请注意,在采取这条路线时,索萨正在接受被许多人认为是相关替代理论(一个直截了当的版本)的不幸后果,即否认知识的封闭原则毕竟,一个人现在可以知道日常的主张,并充分意识到它们包含了对激进怀疑假设的否认,但仅仅假设这些否认是错误的。索萨还提出了一个进一步的主张,据我所知,没有其他相关替代理论的支持者提出过(至少没有明确提出过),那就是,一个人的知识可能是不安全的,因此也不会失去真实性。特别是,由于背景假设只是幸运地为真,因此很容易是假的,这与一个人对目标命题的知识是相容的,并且由于这些背景假设的虚假性可以使一个人对目标命题的信念是假的,那么他对已知目标命题的信念只能是幸运地为真(即,它很容易是假的)。我认为索萨说得很对,一般来说,恰当的表现与不安全是相容的;事实上,我认为这是对索萨作品的深刻见解。正如我们所指出的那样,成就(即由于能力或Sosa术语中的恰当表现而获得的成功)可能在模式上是脆弱的(即目标成功可能很容易失败)。索萨在这里指出了问题的根源:对恰当的表现来说,重要的是合理的背景假设是正确的——特别是,它们是否幸运地正确并不重要。这就是为什么外野手的出色表现与球场的灯光很容易熄灭的事实是一致的(在这种情况下,他的接球尝试可能会出错)。我与索萨的不同之处在于,我不认为知识也是如此。也就是说,如果一个人的认知成功(真正的信念)很容易失败,那么它就不是知识。知识排除了这种运气(脆弱性),因为它排除了高水平的认知风险(即,一个人的信念是错误的认知风险)。这就是为什么,当一个人知道的时候,他的信仰基础是这样的,他不可能轻易出错,这是安全所要求的。相比之下,索萨提出的另一种图景将使我们允许知识与高水平的认知风险共存。结论是,知识不是恰当的信念(相对而言,知识不是一种认知成就)。即使我们同意索萨的观点,即恰当的信念(或认知成就),即使在不安全的情况下,也可以等同于知识,我们也不清楚这是否能像他所假设的那样,让我们对激进怀疑主义的问题有所了解。想想他的观点意味着什么。我们可以认识到,我们的日常知识预设了我们永远无法(即使在原则上)排除的全局错误可能性的虚假性,但我们仍然满足于继续,就好像我们有知识一样。只要怀疑的情景实际上没有出现(即使它们可以很容易地出现),那么我们的信念就可以恰当地形成,即使我们毫无根据地假设我们没有根本错误,因此可以算作知识。与此相关,与拒绝封闭性一致,一个人可以自觉地意识到,他知道自己对日常命题有知识,他知道这些命题包含了对怀疑假设的否认(例如,他有手),而无法知道所包含的命题(例如,他不是一个BIV)。虽然我觉得索萨在认识论上的总路线非常有说服力,但我觉得他在激进怀疑主义上的路线非常没有说服力。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW PHILOSOPHY-
CiteScore
7.40
自引率
0.00%
发文量
17
期刊介绍: In continuous publication since 1892, the Philosophical Review has a long-standing reputation for excellence and has published many papers now considered classics in the field, such as W. V. O. Quine"s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” Thomas Nagel"s “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” and the early work of John Rawls. The journal aims to publish original scholarly work in all areas of analytic philosophy, with an emphasis on material of general interest to academic philosophers, and is one of the few journals in the discipline to publish book reviews.
期刊最新文献
Reasons First Dark Matters: Pessimism and the Problem of Suffering Democratic Law Sustaining Democracy: What We Owe to the Other Side Mind and World in Aristotle’s De Anima
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1