Thomas Aquinas and Contemplation

IF 2.8 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI:10.1215/00318108-10294461
Thomas Williams
{"title":"<i>Thomas Aquinas and Contemplation</i>","authors":"Thomas Williams","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10294461","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Everybody knows (for the relevant value of ‘everybody’) that, for Thomas Aquinas, perfect happiness consists in intellectual contemplation of the divine essence, with the will’s delight or enjoyment being a necessary concomitant of that beatific vision but not, strictly speaking, part of the essence of happiness. Beyond this boilerplate statement, however, most of us would be hard-pressed to say much more about contemplation in Aquinas. What sort of act is it, and how does it relate to other acts of intellect? What acts of contemplation are available in this present life, and how do those acts fit into a life of faith or a life devoted to philosophical or theological study? What contribution, if any, does contemplation make to this-worldly happiness? In Thomas Aquinas and Contemplation, Rik Van Nieuwenhove takes up these and related questions and develops Aquinas’s account of contemplation in a systematic way, elaborating even what “everybody knows” in unexpected directions and unearthing important but neglected material. There are even some surprises along the way.Van Nieuwenhove notes that although Aquinas identifies contemplation as the goal or end of human life, he nowhere offers a precise definition of contemplation. In fact, he speaks of contemplation in a variety of ways and contexts, ranging from the perfect vision of God in the next life, through theoretical contemplation in this life, whether theological or philosophical, all the way to the insight that ordinary Christians can have—and indeed are called to have—into divine truth. What unites all these varieties of contemplation, Van Nieuwenhove argues, is that they culminate in “a non-discursive moment of understanding (intuitus simplex), a simple intellective insight into truth, (what is sometimes called an Aha-Erlebnis in German)” (16). In theological and philosophical contemplation, such nondiscursive insight is the hard-won result of a discursive process; in the contemplation that characterizes the ordinary Christian life, by contrast, it arises directly out of a divinely granted kinship (“connaturality”) between the believer and “the deep things of God” (1 Corinthians 2:10). It is an advantage of this broad understanding of contemplation as intuitus simplex that it “can incorporate the acts of contemplation of the Greek sage, as well as those of the vetula who enjoys the benefit of her Christian faith” (47–48).This vetula (Van Nieuwenhove leaves the word untranslated; it means “little old woman”) has a minor recurring part in the book, as she has in Aquinas’s own writing. In his sermon on the Apostles’ Creed, Aquinas writes that “not one of the philosophers before the coming of Christ, however hard they tried, could know as much about God and about what is necessary for eternal life as one vetula after the coming of Christ can know through faith” (In symbolum apostolorum, pr.; all translations of Aquinas are my own). In his sermon Attendite a falsis, Aquinas writes:The vetula may not be the ideal example for Van Nieuwenhove, since the cognition she is said to have in these two passages is clearly propositional knowledge rather than simple intuition. Van Nieuwenhove identifies a better example from ST III, q. 27, a. 5, ad 3, “where Aquinas writes that the Virgin Mary enjoyed ‘the use of wisdom in contemplation’ … but not ‘wisdom as to teaching”’ (4n).Whatever the best example of “ordinary” Christian contemplation may be—and by that I mean the “openness or receptivity to the divine truth that should characterize the life of” (198) Christians who either do not have, or lack the opportunity to exercise, the intellectual capacities required for doing academic theology or philosophy—the possibility of such contemplation requires a rethinking of some of what “everybody knows” about Aquinas’s view of happiness. As Van Nieuwenhove says, there is a near consensus reading among recent interpreters that Aquinas’s “imperfect happiness” is just Aristotelian happiness—happiness achievable in this present life by the exercise of our natural powers, expressed either in philosophical contemplation or in virtuous civic activity—whereas “perfect happiness” is the happiness of the beatific vision, a happiness attainable only in the next life and only through a supernatural gift. Aristotle knew nothing of theological contemplation (at least not in the sense of theology as sacra doctrina); he certainly knew nothing of “a life shaped by charity and infused virtues” (13). Yet both of these can contribute to this-worldly or “imperfect” happiness on Aquinas’s view, and both—to the extent that they involve “the contemplation of divine truth”—are “an early stage (inchoatio) of the happiness that begins here and is brought to completion in the world to come” (ST II-II, q. 180, a, 4).1 Van Nieuwenhove is right to emphasize that “This kind of continuity is not without significance to Aquinas the theologian, for whom grace perfects nature but does not abolish it” (47).After an introductory chapter, Van Nieuwenhove lays out in part I the epistemological and metaphysical foundations for his reading of Aquinas on contemplation. Chapter 2 is devoted to epistemological issues, especially the various acts of the intellect and the place of contemplation among them. The discussion of Aquinas’s reliance on Neoplatonist sources in preference to Aristotle is particularly useful. Chapter 3 is a bit more tentative and speculative, applying the theory of transcendentals to understand contemplation—something Aquinas himself never explicitly does, as Van Nieuwenhove acknowledges (49). An important conclusion here, drawing on the epistemology ably laid out in chapter 2, is that there is no basis for reading a doctrine of divine illumination into Aquinas. As Van Nieuwenhove puts it, “the fact that truth has a metaphysical foundation in the divine ideas does not commit Aquinas to a theological or illuminist epistemological perspective” (59).This observation brings us to an important recurrent theme in Thomas Aquinas and Contemplation: Van Nieuwenhove’s opposition to some recent scholarship that interprets Aquinas “as a thinker whose theology should perhaps best be labelled as sapiential (e.g. J. P. Torrell, B. McGinn), Augustinian-illuminist (John Milbank), or even charismatic … [that is,] deeply shaped by the gifts of the Holy Spirit (e.g. Servais Pinckers, Andrew Pinsent)” (18). What these have in common is a certain tendency to try to turn Aquinas into Bonaventure, and Van Nieuwenhove’s critique is sharp, assured, and compelling, and yet always somehow charitable.Since I have looked briefly at his rejection of the “illuminist” reading, I turn next to the sapiential reading. I found the idea of “sapiential wisdom” quite puzzling at first mention—sapientia is just the Latin for wisdom after all, and what would a wisdom-y wisdom be?—but Van Nieuwenhove explains that it means “a tasting or savouring kind of wisdom” (174). Sapientia does come from the verb sapio, to taste or savor, and Aquinas is not averse to using etymologies to bolster a point when they serve his purposes. It is therefore all the more noteworthy that Aquinas dismisses as irrelevant the etymological connection between wisdom and savor: “it may be that way in Latin, but it’s not in other languages” (178, quoting III Sent. d. 35, q. 2, a. 1, qc. 3, ad 1; Aquinas makes the same point in ST II-II, q. 45, a. 2, ad 2). In general, as Van Nieuwenhove shows, Aquinas resists the idea that theological wisdom is essentially affective. Even the wisdom that is a gift of the Holy Spirit is not essentially affective: it is cognitive, a divine elevation of the intellect that enables its possessor to judge rightly about divine things. Granted, the gift is rooted in charity, which belongs to the will and grants the believer a kind of kinship or “connaturality” with divine things so that she may judge correctly, but the gift itself belongs to the intellect (178–79). That gift is not—and now we turn to the “charismatic” reading of Aquinas—necessary for theological insight: “Of course, the theologian will ideally enjoy the gifts of the Holy Spirit or at least be morally upright. Theologians who are the slave of their carnal desires will be hampered in the pursuit of truth. Still, Aquinas resisted attributing an essential role to the gifts in relation to the academic pursuit of theology” (180).These critiques, and much more so the positive accounts that ground them, are worked out in part III (“Theology, the Christian Life, and Contemplation”). It is not possible to do justice in a short review to the richness of this discussion. (Of particular note are Van Nieuwenhove’s explanation in chapter 5 of the importance of the claim that theology—more strictly speaking, sacra doctrina—is a scientia (science) subalternated to God’s own scientia and his account in chapter 7 of the gradual development in Aquinas’s understanding of the role of the gifts of the Holy Spirit.) Instead I want to look more closely at part II (“The Dominican Context”), a single chapter that considers Aquinas’s account of the relationship between the active and contemplative lives in light of his ongoing defense of the Dominican Order against antimendicant writings.Contrary to some recent scholarship, Van Nieuwenhove argues compellingly that “Aquinas’s views on the relation and the merits of the active and contemplative lives remain fairly consistent …: from the very beginning Aquinas defended an ideal which is neither purely contemplative nor purely active, although throughout his career he was willing to acknowledge the inherent superiority (melior) of the contemplative life” (74). In the Sentences commentary, Aquinas acknowledges that the active life is more useful (to the extent that it is concerned with the well-being of our neighbors and not just with one’s own excellence) but the contemplative life is dignior, worthier. Van Nieuwenhove suggests that we rephrase dignior as “more meaningful in its own right” (79), a gloss that made me bristle at first but came to seem more and more right as the discussion went on. As for which life is more meritorious, the Sentences commentary leaves the question somewhat open. In the Secunda secundae and Tertia pars of the Summa theologiae it is definitively resolved: whichever life manifests greater charity is more meritorious. Generally, the contemplative life is more meritorious: “Nonetheless, it can happen that one person gains greater merit in works of the active life than another person gains in works of the contemplative life” (ST II-II q. 182, a. 2). Great charity indeed is manifest in those who “allow themselves from time to time to be separated from the sweetness of divine contemplation for a period” (Ibid.) to transmit by teaching or preaching the fruits of their contemplation, as the Dominicans do. Such a life, Aquinas says, “is more perfect than a life that involves only contemplation” (ST III q. 40, a. 1, ad 2).Thomas Aquinas and Contemplation is much more than a book on one underappreciated aspect of Aquinas’s thought. It is a creative synthesis of aspects of Aquinas’s epistemology, philosophy of mind, and moral theology. It is circumspect without being timid, opinionated without being polemical, attentive to historical context without overwhelming the reader with needless detail. It is a splendid achievement.","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.8000,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10294461","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Everybody knows (for the relevant value of ‘everybody’) that, for Thomas Aquinas, perfect happiness consists in intellectual contemplation of the divine essence, with the will’s delight or enjoyment being a necessary concomitant of that beatific vision but not, strictly speaking, part of the essence of happiness. Beyond this boilerplate statement, however, most of us would be hard-pressed to say much more about contemplation in Aquinas. What sort of act is it, and how does it relate to other acts of intellect? What acts of contemplation are available in this present life, and how do those acts fit into a life of faith or a life devoted to philosophical or theological study? What contribution, if any, does contemplation make to this-worldly happiness? In Thomas Aquinas and Contemplation, Rik Van Nieuwenhove takes up these and related questions and develops Aquinas’s account of contemplation in a systematic way, elaborating even what “everybody knows” in unexpected directions and unearthing important but neglected material. There are even some surprises along the way.Van Nieuwenhove notes that although Aquinas identifies contemplation as the goal or end of human life, he nowhere offers a precise definition of contemplation. In fact, he speaks of contemplation in a variety of ways and contexts, ranging from the perfect vision of God in the next life, through theoretical contemplation in this life, whether theological or philosophical, all the way to the insight that ordinary Christians can have—and indeed are called to have—into divine truth. What unites all these varieties of contemplation, Van Nieuwenhove argues, is that they culminate in “a non-discursive moment of understanding (intuitus simplex), a simple intellective insight into truth, (what is sometimes called an Aha-Erlebnis in German)” (16). In theological and philosophical contemplation, such nondiscursive insight is the hard-won result of a discursive process; in the contemplation that characterizes the ordinary Christian life, by contrast, it arises directly out of a divinely granted kinship (“connaturality”) between the believer and “the deep things of God” (1 Corinthians 2:10). It is an advantage of this broad understanding of contemplation as intuitus simplex that it “can incorporate the acts of contemplation of the Greek sage, as well as those of the vetula who enjoys the benefit of her Christian faith” (47–48).This vetula (Van Nieuwenhove leaves the word untranslated; it means “little old woman”) has a minor recurring part in the book, as she has in Aquinas’s own writing. In his sermon on the Apostles’ Creed, Aquinas writes that “not one of the philosophers before the coming of Christ, however hard they tried, could know as much about God and about what is necessary for eternal life as one vetula after the coming of Christ can know through faith” (In symbolum apostolorum, pr.; all translations of Aquinas are my own). In his sermon Attendite a falsis, Aquinas writes:The vetula may not be the ideal example for Van Nieuwenhove, since the cognition she is said to have in these two passages is clearly propositional knowledge rather than simple intuition. Van Nieuwenhove identifies a better example from ST III, q. 27, a. 5, ad 3, “where Aquinas writes that the Virgin Mary enjoyed ‘the use of wisdom in contemplation’ … but not ‘wisdom as to teaching”’ (4n).Whatever the best example of “ordinary” Christian contemplation may be—and by that I mean the “openness or receptivity to the divine truth that should characterize the life of” (198) Christians who either do not have, or lack the opportunity to exercise, the intellectual capacities required for doing academic theology or philosophy—the possibility of such contemplation requires a rethinking of some of what “everybody knows” about Aquinas’s view of happiness. As Van Nieuwenhove says, there is a near consensus reading among recent interpreters that Aquinas’s “imperfect happiness” is just Aristotelian happiness—happiness achievable in this present life by the exercise of our natural powers, expressed either in philosophical contemplation or in virtuous civic activity—whereas “perfect happiness” is the happiness of the beatific vision, a happiness attainable only in the next life and only through a supernatural gift. Aristotle knew nothing of theological contemplation (at least not in the sense of theology as sacra doctrina); he certainly knew nothing of “a life shaped by charity and infused virtues” (13). Yet both of these can contribute to this-worldly or “imperfect” happiness on Aquinas’s view, and both—to the extent that they involve “the contemplation of divine truth”—are “an early stage (inchoatio) of the happiness that begins here and is brought to completion in the world to come” (ST II-II, q. 180, a, 4).1 Van Nieuwenhove is right to emphasize that “This kind of continuity is not without significance to Aquinas the theologian, for whom grace perfects nature but does not abolish it” (47).After an introductory chapter, Van Nieuwenhove lays out in part I the epistemological and metaphysical foundations for his reading of Aquinas on contemplation. Chapter 2 is devoted to epistemological issues, especially the various acts of the intellect and the place of contemplation among them. The discussion of Aquinas’s reliance on Neoplatonist sources in preference to Aristotle is particularly useful. Chapter 3 is a bit more tentative and speculative, applying the theory of transcendentals to understand contemplation—something Aquinas himself never explicitly does, as Van Nieuwenhove acknowledges (49). An important conclusion here, drawing on the epistemology ably laid out in chapter 2, is that there is no basis for reading a doctrine of divine illumination into Aquinas. As Van Nieuwenhove puts it, “the fact that truth has a metaphysical foundation in the divine ideas does not commit Aquinas to a theological or illuminist epistemological perspective” (59).This observation brings us to an important recurrent theme in Thomas Aquinas and Contemplation: Van Nieuwenhove’s opposition to some recent scholarship that interprets Aquinas “as a thinker whose theology should perhaps best be labelled as sapiential (e.g. J. P. Torrell, B. McGinn), Augustinian-illuminist (John Milbank), or even charismatic … [that is,] deeply shaped by the gifts of the Holy Spirit (e.g. Servais Pinckers, Andrew Pinsent)” (18). What these have in common is a certain tendency to try to turn Aquinas into Bonaventure, and Van Nieuwenhove’s critique is sharp, assured, and compelling, and yet always somehow charitable.Since I have looked briefly at his rejection of the “illuminist” reading, I turn next to the sapiential reading. I found the idea of “sapiential wisdom” quite puzzling at first mention—sapientia is just the Latin for wisdom after all, and what would a wisdom-y wisdom be?—but Van Nieuwenhove explains that it means “a tasting or savouring kind of wisdom” (174). Sapientia does come from the verb sapio, to taste or savor, and Aquinas is not averse to using etymologies to bolster a point when they serve his purposes. It is therefore all the more noteworthy that Aquinas dismisses as irrelevant the etymological connection between wisdom and savor: “it may be that way in Latin, but it’s not in other languages” (178, quoting III Sent. d. 35, q. 2, a. 1, qc. 3, ad 1; Aquinas makes the same point in ST II-II, q. 45, a. 2, ad 2). In general, as Van Nieuwenhove shows, Aquinas resists the idea that theological wisdom is essentially affective. Even the wisdom that is a gift of the Holy Spirit is not essentially affective: it is cognitive, a divine elevation of the intellect that enables its possessor to judge rightly about divine things. Granted, the gift is rooted in charity, which belongs to the will and grants the believer a kind of kinship or “connaturality” with divine things so that she may judge correctly, but the gift itself belongs to the intellect (178–79). That gift is not—and now we turn to the “charismatic” reading of Aquinas—necessary for theological insight: “Of course, the theologian will ideally enjoy the gifts of the Holy Spirit or at least be morally upright. Theologians who are the slave of their carnal desires will be hampered in the pursuit of truth. Still, Aquinas resisted attributing an essential role to the gifts in relation to the academic pursuit of theology” (180).These critiques, and much more so the positive accounts that ground them, are worked out in part III (“Theology, the Christian Life, and Contemplation”). It is not possible to do justice in a short review to the richness of this discussion. (Of particular note are Van Nieuwenhove’s explanation in chapter 5 of the importance of the claim that theology—more strictly speaking, sacra doctrina—is a scientia (science) subalternated to God’s own scientia and his account in chapter 7 of the gradual development in Aquinas’s understanding of the role of the gifts of the Holy Spirit.) Instead I want to look more closely at part II (“The Dominican Context”), a single chapter that considers Aquinas’s account of the relationship between the active and contemplative lives in light of his ongoing defense of the Dominican Order against antimendicant writings.Contrary to some recent scholarship, Van Nieuwenhove argues compellingly that “Aquinas’s views on the relation and the merits of the active and contemplative lives remain fairly consistent …: from the very beginning Aquinas defended an ideal which is neither purely contemplative nor purely active, although throughout his career he was willing to acknowledge the inherent superiority (melior) of the contemplative life” (74). In the Sentences commentary, Aquinas acknowledges that the active life is more useful (to the extent that it is concerned with the well-being of our neighbors and not just with one’s own excellence) but the contemplative life is dignior, worthier. Van Nieuwenhove suggests that we rephrase dignior as “more meaningful in its own right” (79), a gloss that made me bristle at first but came to seem more and more right as the discussion went on. As for which life is more meritorious, the Sentences commentary leaves the question somewhat open. In the Secunda secundae and Tertia pars of the Summa theologiae it is definitively resolved: whichever life manifests greater charity is more meritorious. Generally, the contemplative life is more meritorious: “Nonetheless, it can happen that one person gains greater merit in works of the active life than another person gains in works of the contemplative life” (ST II-II q. 182, a. 2). Great charity indeed is manifest in those who “allow themselves from time to time to be separated from the sweetness of divine contemplation for a period” (Ibid.) to transmit by teaching or preaching the fruits of their contemplation, as the Dominicans do. Such a life, Aquinas says, “is more perfect than a life that involves only contemplation” (ST III q. 40, a. 1, ad 2).Thomas Aquinas and Contemplation is much more than a book on one underappreciated aspect of Aquinas’s thought. It is a creative synthesis of aspects of Aquinas’s epistemology, philosophy of mind, and moral theology. It is circumspect without being timid, opinionated without being polemical, attentive to historical context without overwhelming the reader with needless detail. It is a splendid achievement.
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
托马斯·阿奎那与沉思
每个人都知道(因为“每个人”的相关价值),对托马斯·阿奎那来说,完美的幸福包括对神圣本质的理智思考,而意志的愉悦或享受是这种美好愿景的必要伴随物,但严格地说,不是幸福本质的一部分。然而,除了这句陈词滥调之外,我们大多数人都很难对阿奎那的沉思多说些什么。这是一种什么样的行为,它与其他智力行为有什么关系?在现在的生活中有哪些沉思的行为,这些行为如何适合信仰的生活或致力于哲学或神学研究的生活?如果有的话,沉思对现世的幸福有什么贡献?在《托马斯·阿奎那与沉思》一书中,里克·范nieuwenhove接受了这些和相关的问题,并以系统的方式发展了阿奎那对沉思的描述,甚至在意想不到的方向上详细阐述了“每个人都知道”的东西,并发掘了重要但被忽视的材料。一路上甚至还有一些惊喜。范nieuwenhove注意到,虽然阿奎那认为沉思是人类生活的目标或终点,但他没有给出沉思的精确定义。事实上,他以各种不同的方式和背景来谈论沉思,从对上帝来生的完美想象,到今生的理论沉思,无论是神学的还是哲学的,一直到普通基督徒能够拥有的——实际上是被召唤去拥有的——对神圣真理的洞察。凡·Nieuwenhove认为,将所有这些不同的沉思统一起来的是,它们的高潮是“一个非话语的理解时刻(intuitus simplex),一个对真理的简单的理性洞察(有时在德语中称为ah - erlebnis)”(16)。在神学和哲学的沉思中,这种非话语的洞察力是话语过程中来之不易的结果;相比之下,在普通基督徒生活所特有的沉思中,它直接产生于信徒与“神的深层事物”(哥林多前书2:10)之间的神圣授予的亲属关系(“自然”)。这种将沉思作为单纯直觉的广泛理解的优势在于,它“可以结合希腊圣贤的沉思行为,以及那些享受基督教信仰好处的女祭司的沉思行为”(47-48)。这篇短文(范nieuwenhove)没有翻译这个词;它的意思是“小老妇人”)在书中有一个次要的反复出现的部分,就像她在阿奎那自己的作品中一样。在他关于使徒信经的布道中,阿奎那写道:“在基督降临之前,没有一个哲学家,无论他们多么努力,都不能像基督降临之后的一个维特拉那样,通过信仰了解上帝和永生的必要条件。”所有阿奎那的译本都是我自己的)。在他的布道中,阿奎那写道:,vetula可能不是范nieuwenhove的理想例子,因为她在这两段中所说的认知显然是命题知识,而不是简单的直觉。Van Nieuwenhove从ST III, q. 27, a. 5, ad . 3中找到了一个更好的例子,“阿奎那写道圣母玛利亚享受‘在沉思中使用智慧’……但不是‘在教学中使用智慧’”(4n)。无论“普通”基督徒沉思的最好例子是什么——我指的是“对神圣真理的开放或接受,这应该是基督徒生活的特征”(198),这些基督徒要么没有,要么缺乏机会去锻炼,从事学术神学或哲学研究所需的智力——这种沉思的可能性需要重新思考一些“人人都知道”的关于阿奎那的幸福观的东西。正如范nieuwenhove所说,在最近的解释者中有一种近乎一致的解读,那就是阿奎那的“不完美的幸福”只是亚里士多德式的幸福——通过运用我们的自然力量在今生获得的幸福,可以通过哲学思考或有道德的公民活动来表达——而“完美的幸福”是一种幸福的愿景,一种只有在来世才能获得的幸福,只有通过超自然的礼物才能获得。亚里士多德对神学的沉思一无所知(至少不是在神学作为神圣教义的意义上);他当然不知道什么是“由慈善和美德塑造的生活”(13)。然而,在阿奎那看来,这两者都可以促成现世的或“不完美的”幸福,而且两者——就它们涉及“对神圣真理的沉思”而言——都是“幸福的早期阶段(inchoatio),从这里开始,在未来的世界中完成”(ST II-II, q. 180, a, 4)范nieuwenhove强调“这种连续性对神学家阿奎那来说并非没有意义,对他来说,恩典使自然完美,但没有废除它”是正确的(47)。 在导论一章之后,范nieuwenhove在第一部分中列出了他阅读阿奎那关于沉思的认识论和形而上学基础。第二章专门讨论认识论问题,特别是智力的各种行为和沉思在其中的地位。关于阿奎那对新柏拉图主义来源的依赖而不是亚里士多德的讨论尤其有用。第三章更具试探性和思辨性,运用先验理论来理解沉思——这是阿奎那本人从未明确做过的,正如范nieuwenhove所承认的(49)。这里有一个重要的结论,根据第2章的认识论,是没有基础来解读阿奎那的神圣启示学说。正如范nieuwenhove所说,“真理在神的观念中有形而上学的基础,这一事实并没有使阿奎那陷入神学或光明主义的认识论观点”(59)。这一观察将我们带到了托马斯·阿奎那和沉思中一个重要的反复出现的主题:范nieuwenhove反对一些最近的学术,这些学术将阿奎那解释为“一个思想家,他的神学也许最好被贴上智慧的标签(例如J. P. Torrell, B. McGinn),奥古斯丁-光明主义者(约翰·米尔班克),甚至是有魅力的……[也就是]深受圣灵恩赐的影响(例如Servais Pinckers, Andrew Pinsent)”(18)。这些人的共同之处在于,他们都倾向于试图把阿奎那变成博纳文蒂尔,而范nieuwenhove的批判是尖锐的,有保证的,令人信服的,但总是有些仁慈。既然我已经简要地看了他对“光明主义”解读的拒绝,接下来我要转向智慧解读。我发现“智慧的智慧”这个概念一开始很令人困惑——毕竟,sapientia只是拉丁语中智慧的意思,那么智慧的智慧是什么呢?但范尼文霍夫解释说,它的意思是“一种品尝或品味的智慧”(174)。Sapientia确实来自动词sapio,意思是品尝或品味,阿奎那并不反对使用词源学来支持一个观点,只要它们符合他的目的。因此,更值得注意的是,阿奎那认为智慧和品味之间的词源联系无关紧要:“在拉丁语中可能是这样,但在其他语言中不是这样”(178,引用III Sent)。D. 35, q. 2, a. 1, qc。3、ad1;阿奎那使同样的观点在ST II-II, q. 45, a. 2, ad . 2)。在一般情况下,如范nieuwenhove显示,阿奎那抵制的想法,神学智慧本质上是有效的。即使是圣灵所赐的智慧,本质上也不是情感上的:它是认知上的,是一种神圣的智力提升,使其拥有者能够正确地判断神圣的事物。当然,这种恩赐根植于慈善,它属于意志,并赋予信徒一种与神圣事物的亲属关系或“自然”,以便她可以正确地判断,但这种恩赐本身属于智力(178-79)。这种恩赐并不是——现在我们转向对阿奎那的“魅力”解读——神学洞察力所必需的:“当然,神学家将理想地享受圣灵的恩赐,或者至少在道德上是正直的。受肉体欲望奴役的神学家在追求真理的道路上会受到阻碍。然而,阿奎那拒绝在神学的学术追求中赋予天赋一个重要的角色”(180)。这些批评,以及更多的积极的描述,都是在第三部分(“神学,基督徒生活和沉思”)中提出的。对这一讨论的丰富性作一个简短的回顾是不可能公正的。(特别值得注意的是,范nieuwenhove在第5章中解释了神学——更严格地说,sacra doctrina——是一门次于上帝自己的科学的科学的重要性,以及他在第7章中对阿奎那对圣灵恩赐作用的理解逐渐发展的描述。)相反,我想更仔细地看第二部分(“多明尼加背景”),这一章考虑了阿奎那对积极生活和沉思生活之间关系的描述,根据他对多明尼加教团反对反修道会著作的持续辩护。与最近的一些学术研究相反,Van Nieuwenhove令人信服地认为“阿奎那关于积极和沉思生活的关系和优点的观点是相当一致的……:从一开始,阿奎那就捍卫了一个既不是纯粹沉思也不是纯粹积极的理想,尽管在他的整个职业生涯中,他愿意承认沉思生活固有的优越性(melior)”(74)。在《句子》的评论中,阿奎那承认积极的生活更有用(在某种程度上,它与我们邻居的幸福有关,而不仅仅是自己的卓越),但沉思的生活更高贵,更有价值。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW PHILOSOPHY-
CiteScore
7.40
自引率
0.00%
发文量
17
期刊介绍: In continuous publication since 1892, the Philosophical Review has a long-standing reputation for excellence and has published many papers now considered classics in the field, such as W. V. O. Quine"s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” Thomas Nagel"s “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” and the early work of John Rawls. The journal aims to publish original scholarly work in all areas of analytic philosophy, with an emphasis on material of general interest to academic philosophers, and is one of the few journals in the discipline to publish book reviews.
期刊最新文献
Reasons First Dark Matters: Pessimism and the Problem of Suffering Democratic Law Sustaining Democracy: What We Owe to the Other Side Mind and World in Aristotle’s De Anima
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1