The Many and the One: A Philosophical Study of Plural Logic

IF 2.8 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI:10.1215/00318108-10317593
J. P. Studd
{"title":"<i>The Many and the One: A Philosophical Study of Plural Logic</i>","authors":"J. P. Studd","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10317593","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Logicians and philosophers have had a good 120 years to get used to the idea that not every condition defines a set. One popular coping strategy is to maintain that each instantiated condition does at least determine a ‘plurality’ (i.e., one or more items). This is to say that friends of traditional plural logic accept—often as a trivial or evident or logical truth—each instance of plural comprehension: Unless nothing is φ, some things include everything that is φ, and nothing else. Set-theoretic paradoxes are avoided by recognizing a type distinction between singular quantifiers (‘something’) and plural ones (‘some things’).This book defends a heterodox version of plural logic. Salvatore Florio and Øystein Linnebo advocate a set theory based on a ‘critical plural logic’ that refutes many instances of plural comprehension. In particular, they deny that there are one or more things that include everything. Instead, they argue, when it comes to resolving the paradoxes, a ‘package deal’ that restricts plural comprehension to ‘extensionally definite’ conditions is more attractive than its competitors that either limit the range of our quantifiers (‘generality relativism’) or constrain ‘singularization.’ Florio and Linnebo’s rejection of traditional plural logic permits them to combine two otherwise incompatible views: (i) ‘the set of’ operation is a universal singularization, so that it injectively maps each plurality to an object (namely, its set), and (ii) the domain of ‘everything’ may contain absolutely everything, so that it cannot be surpassed by singularization.The argument for adopting critical plural logic in preference to traditional plural logic comes in the fourth and final part of the book. The first three parts make the authors’ case for taking plural resources seriously in the first place. Part I reappraises the debate between pluralism, ‘which takes plural resources at face value’ (2), and singularism, which takes the opposite view. Part II compares ‘four different ways to talk about many objects simultaneously’ (119), including second-order quantification, and the use of ‘individual sums’, in addition to sets and pluralities. Part III focuses on philosophical applications of plural logic. Along the way, the book tackles many other topics of interest, including whether plural logic counts as ‘pure logic’ (168), or carries distinctive ontological commitments (chap. 8), how plural resources interact with modality (chap. 10), and whether the pluralization operation can be iterated to obtain superplural terms the denote ‘pluralities of pluralities’ (180) (chap. 9).The Many and the One covers an impressive amount of difficult territory in an admirably clear and engaging way. Florio and Linnebo offer a fresh perspective on the pluralism debate and defend a novel response to the paradoxes. The driving force behind their arguments is usually logic, broadly construed, rather than linguistics or the philosophy of language. But Florio and Linnebo have written a book that will also be of interest and accessible to nonlogicians. Even if their opponents are not ultimately converted to the position defended in this book, open-minded readers will find much of value.Should singularists and friends of traditional plural logic be swayed by Florio and Linnebo’s arguments? There are many arguments in this book that merit careful consideration. I will consider just two in particular that give me pause for thought. The first concerns the case for pluralism as opposed to singularism. Florio and Linnebo are clear that the move to a critical plural logic undermines many of the familiar arguments for pluralism. For example, one popular style of argument, ‘the paradox of plurality,’ maintains that a singularist analysis would turn evident truths into demonstrable falsehoods (section 3.4). But this argument is no longer available, since the would-be truths are instances of plural comprehension which Florio and Linnebo reject. Another influential style of argument turns on the fact that pluralities provide a means to encode non-set-sized collections (section 4.8). But this argument is also unavailable, since their view only countenances set-sized pluralities. What reason, then, remains to take plural resources seriously?Florio and Linnebo’s main reason is that primitive plurals are needed to ‘give an account of sets’ (62) (section 4.4, chap. 12). The first half of Florio and Linnebo’s account comprises two elegant axioms that characterize the ‘singularization’ that maps each plurality to its set. These axioms are to be justified via the liberal view of definitions that Florio and Linnebo defend in section 12.3. The second half of their account consists of a critical plural logic whose axioms assert the existence of pluralities that correspond to ‘properly circumscribed’ or ‘extensionally definite’ collections. Florio and Linnebo seek to motivate some of these axioms through our intuitive grasp of these notions (which they explain in section 10.10). For example, they maintain, ‘since every single object can be circumscribed, there are singleton pluralities’ (280). In other cases, they rely on abductive considerations. One axiom permits us to obtain infinite pluralities by closing any plurality under a defined function. This axiom is justified on the grounds that taking infinite collections to be extensionally definite has been a ‘tremendous theoretical success’ (282). Combined with axioms licensing further plurality-forming operations, the end result is a set theory closely akin to the standard set theory, ZFC.Here is one reservation I have about this argument. Suppose that our grasp of ‘circumscription’ or ‘extensional definiteness’ is robust enough to vouchsafe Florio and Linnebo’s axioms. What is to stop a singularist from deploying this notion to directly motivate analogous set-forming operations in line with a first-order formulation of ZFC? The singularist may say, for example, ‘since every single object can be circumscribed, there are singleton sets.’ Moreover, given their theoretical success, she may obtain infinite sets, by permitting any set to be closed under a defined function. What would be lost by going direct from extensional definiteness to sets without the detour via pluralities?The second argument I want to pick up on targets the ‘traditional absolutist,’ who rejects generality relativism but adopts traditional plural logic (sections 11.5–11.6). Florio and Linnebo argue that this view, on its ‘most plausible development’ (261), ends up adopting a plural logic akin to their critical plural logic. First, ‘semantic considerations’ push the traditional absolutist to ascend a hierarchy that results from iterated ‘pluralization’ (256). She should countenance not just plural resources (level 1 pluralization), but also superplural resources (level 2 pluralization) and, more generally, pluralization of level n, for any finite n. Second, the infinitely many types of pluralization result in ‘expressibility problems’ (256) unless, as Florio and Linnebo recommend, the traditional absolutist takes one further step and ‘lifts the veil of type distinctions’ (261). The result is a one-sorted language whose ‘all-purpose’ variables simultaneously quantify over each individual, plurality, superplurality, or whatever, available at any level (261). Then, if she tries to ‘pluralize’ the all-purpose variables, the resulting logic does not sustain unrestricted plural comprehension. Each plurality, superplurality, and so on sits at some level in the hierarchy and only has members that belong to lower levels so there is no ‘universal plurality’ with respect to the all-purpose variable (261). The end result, Florio and Linnebo contend, is a view that has ‘much in common’ with their own (261).A traditional absolutist who is reluctant to ascend, or subsequently transcend, the pluralization hierarchy may well want to scrutinize Florio and Linnebo’s assumptions. The semantic considerations relate to Florio and Linnebo’s desire to give an ‘intensionally correct’ Tarski-style account of logical consequence (253), which generalizes not just over the set-based interpretations supplied by standard model theory but over every possible interpretation of the object language. The expressibility problems center on the inability of the infinitely typed language to articulate facts about the whole hierarchy. Even if a traditional absolutist is willing to follow Florio and Linnebo’s argument to its end point, however, I doubt that the resulting position is as similar to their view as they suggest.For one thing, the argument puts no pressure on the traditional absolutist’s contention that some things include everything. The would-be universal ‘plurality’ that Florio and Linnebo argue she should renounce is really—what to call it?—a ‘hyperplurality’ comprising every individual, plurality, superplural, or whatever, available at any level of the pluralization hierarchy. Rejecting this ‘hyperplurality’ is perfectly compatible with accepting an ordinary, level 1 plurality comprising everything. More generally—and dropping the loose ‘plurality’ talk for a moment—the mooted restrictions to plural comprehension arise only on an unintended interpretation, which gives ‘singular’ and ‘plural’ quantifiers meanings far removed from the ordinary ones. A traditional absolutist who accepts these restrictions may still maintain that plural comprehension is subject to no restriction under its intended interpretation in which singular and plural quantifiers express ordinary singular and plural quantification.The importance of this difference comes out when we set aside the higher levels of the pluralization hierarchy and focus on the plural resources available in natural languages. One unusual feature of Florio and Linnebo’s pluralism is that pluralities appear to play no essential role in the semantics of natural language plural terms. Consider, for example, a sentence such as ‘Most things are nonconcrete things.’ As Florio and Linnebo point out, the standard account of determiners like ‘most’ relies on the assumption that the underlying domain of discourse is a set (90). In these cases, they argue, sets or individual sums would serve just as well as, or perhaps better than, pluralities in the semantic analysis of plural terms (85–88, 295).What should we make of these set-based semantic theories? It is open to a generality relativist to take such a theory at face value. On this view, any universe of discourse available in natural language may be encoded as a set in a suitable metalanguage. But as Florio and Linnebo acknowledge, the same option is not available to someone who rejects generality relativism in a case when she takes the universe of discourse to comprise absolutely everything (295). Traditional absolutists have a fallback option. In cases where set-based semantic values are no longer available, a traditional absolutist may hope to salvage the linguistic core of the set-based semantic theory using plural resources. A universe comprising every individual, for example, may be encoded using the corresponding plurality. But this option is not available for an advocate of critical plural logic. Let me close then by raising what seems to me an important future task for Florio and Linnebo: if the semantics of natural language plural terms cannot always be understood in the standard way in terms of either individual sums or sets or pluralities, how is it to be understood?","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"3 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":2.8000,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10317593","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Logicians and philosophers have had a good 120 years to get used to the idea that not every condition defines a set. One popular coping strategy is to maintain that each instantiated condition does at least determine a ‘plurality’ (i.e., one or more items). This is to say that friends of traditional plural logic accept—often as a trivial or evident or logical truth—each instance of plural comprehension: Unless nothing is φ, some things include everything that is φ, and nothing else. Set-theoretic paradoxes are avoided by recognizing a type distinction between singular quantifiers (‘something’) and plural ones (‘some things’).This book defends a heterodox version of plural logic. Salvatore Florio and Øystein Linnebo advocate a set theory based on a ‘critical plural logic’ that refutes many instances of plural comprehension. In particular, they deny that there are one or more things that include everything. Instead, they argue, when it comes to resolving the paradoxes, a ‘package deal’ that restricts plural comprehension to ‘extensionally definite’ conditions is more attractive than its competitors that either limit the range of our quantifiers (‘generality relativism’) or constrain ‘singularization.’ Florio and Linnebo’s rejection of traditional plural logic permits them to combine two otherwise incompatible views: (i) ‘the set of’ operation is a universal singularization, so that it injectively maps each plurality to an object (namely, its set), and (ii) the domain of ‘everything’ may contain absolutely everything, so that it cannot be surpassed by singularization.The argument for adopting critical plural logic in preference to traditional plural logic comes in the fourth and final part of the book. The first three parts make the authors’ case for taking plural resources seriously in the first place. Part I reappraises the debate between pluralism, ‘which takes plural resources at face value’ (2), and singularism, which takes the opposite view. Part II compares ‘four different ways to talk about many objects simultaneously’ (119), including second-order quantification, and the use of ‘individual sums’, in addition to sets and pluralities. Part III focuses on philosophical applications of plural logic. Along the way, the book tackles many other topics of interest, including whether plural logic counts as ‘pure logic’ (168), or carries distinctive ontological commitments (chap. 8), how plural resources interact with modality (chap. 10), and whether the pluralization operation can be iterated to obtain superplural terms the denote ‘pluralities of pluralities’ (180) (chap. 9).The Many and the One covers an impressive amount of difficult territory in an admirably clear and engaging way. Florio and Linnebo offer a fresh perspective on the pluralism debate and defend a novel response to the paradoxes. The driving force behind their arguments is usually logic, broadly construed, rather than linguistics or the philosophy of language. But Florio and Linnebo have written a book that will also be of interest and accessible to nonlogicians. Even if their opponents are not ultimately converted to the position defended in this book, open-minded readers will find much of value.Should singularists and friends of traditional plural logic be swayed by Florio and Linnebo’s arguments? There are many arguments in this book that merit careful consideration. I will consider just two in particular that give me pause for thought. The first concerns the case for pluralism as opposed to singularism. Florio and Linnebo are clear that the move to a critical plural logic undermines many of the familiar arguments for pluralism. For example, one popular style of argument, ‘the paradox of plurality,’ maintains that a singularist analysis would turn evident truths into demonstrable falsehoods (section 3.4). But this argument is no longer available, since the would-be truths are instances of plural comprehension which Florio and Linnebo reject. Another influential style of argument turns on the fact that pluralities provide a means to encode non-set-sized collections (section 4.8). But this argument is also unavailable, since their view only countenances set-sized pluralities. What reason, then, remains to take plural resources seriously?Florio and Linnebo’s main reason is that primitive plurals are needed to ‘give an account of sets’ (62) (section 4.4, chap. 12). The first half of Florio and Linnebo’s account comprises two elegant axioms that characterize the ‘singularization’ that maps each plurality to its set. These axioms are to be justified via the liberal view of definitions that Florio and Linnebo defend in section 12.3. The second half of their account consists of a critical plural logic whose axioms assert the existence of pluralities that correspond to ‘properly circumscribed’ or ‘extensionally definite’ collections. Florio and Linnebo seek to motivate some of these axioms through our intuitive grasp of these notions (which they explain in section 10.10). For example, they maintain, ‘since every single object can be circumscribed, there are singleton pluralities’ (280). In other cases, they rely on abductive considerations. One axiom permits us to obtain infinite pluralities by closing any plurality under a defined function. This axiom is justified on the grounds that taking infinite collections to be extensionally definite has been a ‘tremendous theoretical success’ (282). Combined with axioms licensing further plurality-forming operations, the end result is a set theory closely akin to the standard set theory, ZFC.Here is one reservation I have about this argument. Suppose that our grasp of ‘circumscription’ or ‘extensional definiteness’ is robust enough to vouchsafe Florio and Linnebo’s axioms. What is to stop a singularist from deploying this notion to directly motivate analogous set-forming operations in line with a first-order formulation of ZFC? The singularist may say, for example, ‘since every single object can be circumscribed, there are singleton sets.’ Moreover, given their theoretical success, she may obtain infinite sets, by permitting any set to be closed under a defined function. What would be lost by going direct from extensional definiteness to sets without the detour via pluralities?The second argument I want to pick up on targets the ‘traditional absolutist,’ who rejects generality relativism but adopts traditional plural logic (sections 11.5–11.6). Florio and Linnebo argue that this view, on its ‘most plausible development’ (261), ends up adopting a plural logic akin to their critical plural logic. First, ‘semantic considerations’ push the traditional absolutist to ascend a hierarchy that results from iterated ‘pluralization’ (256). She should countenance not just plural resources (level 1 pluralization), but also superplural resources (level 2 pluralization) and, more generally, pluralization of level n, for any finite n. Second, the infinitely many types of pluralization result in ‘expressibility problems’ (256) unless, as Florio and Linnebo recommend, the traditional absolutist takes one further step and ‘lifts the veil of type distinctions’ (261). The result is a one-sorted language whose ‘all-purpose’ variables simultaneously quantify over each individual, plurality, superplurality, or whatever, available at any level (261). Then, if she tries to ‘pluralize’ the all-purpose variables, the resulting logic does not sustain unrestricted plural comprehension. Each plurality, superplurality, and so on sits at some level in the hierarchy and only has members that belong to lower levels so there is no ‘universal plurality’ with respect to the all-purpose variable (261). The end result, Florio and Linnebo contend, is a view that has ‘much in common’ with their own (261).A traditional absolutist who is reluctant to ascend, or subsequently transcend, the pluralization hierarchy may well want to scrutinize Florio and Linnebo’s assumptions. The semantic considerations relate to Florio and Linnebo’s desire to give an ‘intensionally correct’ Tarski-style account of logical consequence (253), which generalizes not just over the set-based interpretations supplied by standard model theory but over every possible interpretation of the object language. The expressibility problems center on the inability of the infinitely typed language to articulate facts about the whole hierarchy. Even if a traditional absolutist is willing to follow Florio and Linnebo’s argument to its end point, however, I doubt that the resulting position is as similar to their view as they suggest.For one thing, the argument puts no pressure on the traditional absolutist’s contention that some things include everything. The would-be universal ‘plurality’ that Florio and Linnebo argue she should renounce is really—what to call it?—a ‘hyperplurality’ comprising every individual, plurality, superplural, or whatever, available at any level of the pluralization hierarchy. Rejecting this ‘hyperplurality’ is perfectly compatible with accepting an ordinary, level 1 plurality comprising everything. More generally—and dropping the loose ‘plurality’ talk for a moment—the mooted restrictions to plural comprehension arise only on an unintended interpretation, which gives ‘singular’ and ‘plural’ quantifiers meanings far removed from the ordinary ones. A traditional absolutist who accepts these restrictions may still maintain that plural comprehension is subject to no restriction under its intended interpretation in which singular and plural quantifiers express ordinary singular and plural quantification.The importance of this difference comes out when we set aside the higher levels of the pluralization hierarchy and focus on the plural resources available in natural languages. One unusual feature of Florio and Linnebo’s pluralism is that pluralities appear to play no essential role in the semantics of natural language plural terms. Consider, for example, a sentence such as ‘Most things are nonconcrete things.’ As Florio and Linnebo point out, the standard account of determiners like ‘most’ relies on the assumption that the underlying domain of discourse is a set (90). In these cases, they argue, sets or individual sums would serve just as well as, or perhaps better than, pluralities in the semantic analysis of plural terms (85–88, 295).What should we make of these set-based semantic theories? It is open to a generality relativist to take such a theory at face value. On this view, any universe of discourse available in natural language may be encoded as a set in a suitable metalanguage. But as Florio and Linnebo acknowledge, the same option is not available to someone who rejects generality relativism in a case when she takes the universe of discourse to comprise absolutely everything (295). Traditional absolutists have a fallback option. In cases where set-based semantic values are no longer available, a traditional absolutist may hope to salvage the linguistic core of the set-based semantic theory using plural resources. A universe comprising every individual, for example, may be encoded using the corresponding plurality. But this option is not available for an advocate of critical plural logic. Let me close then by raising what seems to me an important future task for Florio and Linnebo: if the semantics of natural language plural terms cannot always be understood in the standard way in terms of either individual sums or sets or pluralities, how is it to be understood?
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
多与一:多元逻辑的哲学研究
Florio和Linnebo试图通过我们对这些概念的直觉把握来激发这些公理(他们在10.10节中对此进行了解释)。例如,他们认为,“因为每一个单一的对象都可以被限定,所以存在单一的复数”(280)。在其他情况下,它们依赖于溯因性考虑。一个公理允许我们通过在一个定义函数下封闭任何复数来获得无限复数。这一公理的理由是,将无限集合视为外延确定已经取得了“巨大的理论成功”(282)。与允许进一步的多元形成操作的公理相结合,最终的结果是一个与标准集合理论ZFC非常相似的集合理论。我对这个论点有一点保留意见。假设我们对“限定”或“外延确定性”的把握足够牢固,足以证明弗洛里奥和林内博的公理是正确的。是什么阻止一个奇点主义者利用这个概念来直接激发符合ZFC一阶公式的类似集合形成操作?例如,奇点论者可能会说,“因为每一个单独的对象都可以被限定,所以就有单独的集合。”此外,由于他们在理论上的成功,她可以通过允许任何集合在一个定义函数下闭合而得到无限集。如果直接从外延确定性到集合,而不绕道复数,会失去什么?第二个论点,我想选择的目标是“传统绝对主义者”,谁拒绝一般相对主义,但采用传统的多元逻辑(第11.5-11.6节)。Florio和Linnebo认为,这种观点,在其“最合理的发展”(261)上,最终采用了一种类似于他们的批判性多元逻辑的多元逻辑。首先,“语义考虑”推动传统的绝对主义者上升一个由反复的“多元化”产生的层次结构(256)。她不仅应该支持复数资源(第1级复数),而且应该支持超复数资源(第2级复数),更一般地说,对于任何有限的n,都应该支持n级的复数。其次,无限多类型的复数会导致“可表达性问题”(256),除非像Florio和Linnebo建议的那样,传统的绝对主义者更进一步,“揭开类型区别的面纱”(261)。其结果是一种单一排序的语言,其“通用”变量同时量化每个个体、复数、超复数或其他任何级别的变量(261)。然后,如果她试图将万能变量“复数化”,那么结果逻辑就不能维持不受限制的复数理解。每个复数、超复数等等都位于层次结构的某个层次上,只有属于较低层次的成员,因此就万能变量而言,不存在“普遍复数”(261)。Florio和Linnebo认为,最终的结果与他们自己的观点“有很多共同之处”(261)。一个传统的专制主义者不愿意提升,或随后超越,多元化的等级制度可能很想仔细检查弗洛里奥和林内博的假设。语义方面的考虑与Florio和Linnebo的愿望有关,即给出一个“高度正确的”塔斯基式的逻辑推论(253),它不仅概括了标准模型理论提供的基于集合的解释,而且概括了对对象语言的每一种可能的解释。可表达性问题集中在无限类型语言无法表达关于整个层次结构的事实。然而,即使一个传统的绝对主义者愿意追随Florio和Linnebo的论点,我也怀疑最终的立场是否像他们所暗示的那样与他们的观点相似。一方面,这一论点没有对传统的绝对主义者认为某些事物包括一切的论点施加压力。弗洛里奥和林内波认为她应该放弃的所谓的普遍的“多元化”实际上——该怎么称呼它呢?-“超复数”,包括每个个体、复数、超复数,或任何复数层次上可用的东西。拒绝这种“超多元”与接受包含一切的普通的、第一层次的多元是完全相容的。更一般地说——暂时抛开松散的“复数”话题——对复数理解的有争议的限制只会出现在一种意想不到的解释上,这种解释赋予了“单数”和“复数”量词与普通量词相去甚远的含义。接受这些限制的传统绝对主义者可能仍然认为,复数理解不受其预期解释的限制,即单数和复数量词表达普通的单数和复数量词。当我们抛开复数层次的更高层次,专注于自然语言中可用的复数资源时,这种差异的重要性就显现出来了。 Florio和Linnebo的多元论的一个不同寻常的特点是,在自然语言的复数术语的语义中,复数似乎没有发挥重要作用。例如,考虑这样一个句子:“大多数事物都是非具体事物。”正如Florio和Linnebo指出的那样,像“most”这样的限定词的标准描述依赖于这样一个假设,即话语的潜在领域是一个集合(90)。在这些情况下,他们认为,集合或单独的总和在复数术语的语义分析中可以起到和复数一样的作用,甚至可能比复数更好(85 - 88,295)。我们应该如何理解这些基于集合的语义理论呢?广义相对论主义者可以接受这种理论的表面价值。在这种观点下,自然语言中任何可用的话语域都可以被编码为合适的元语言的集合。但是正如Florio和Linnebo所承认的那样,当一个人拒绝广义相对主义的时候,当她把话语的宇宙绝对包含一切的时候,她就没有同样的选择了(295)。传统的绝对主义者有一个退路。在基于集合的语义值不再可用的情况下,传统的绝对主义者可能希望利用多元资源来挽救基于集合的语义理论的语言核心。例如,包含每个个体的宇宙可以使用相应的多个来编码。但是这个选项对于批判多元逻辑的倡导者来说是不可用的。让我以一个在我看来对Florio和Linnebo来说很重要的未来任务来结束这个问题:如果自然语言复数词的语义不能总是以标准的方式被理解,不管是单个的总和,集合还是复数,那该如何理解它呢?
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW PHILOSOPHY-
CiteScore
7.40
自引率
0.00%
发文量
17
期刊介绍: In continuous publication since 1892, the Philosophical Review has a long-standing reputation for excellence and has published many papers now considered classics in the field, such as W. V. O. Quine"s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” Thomas Nagel"s “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” and the early work of John Rawls. The journal aims to publish original scholarly work in all areas of analytic philosophy, with an emphasis on material of general interest to academic philosophers, and is one of the few journals in the discipline to publish book reviews.
期刊最新文献
Reasons First Dark Matters: Pessimism and the Problem of Suffering Democratic Law Sustaining Democracy: What We Owe to the Other Side Mind and World in Aristotle’s De Anima
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1