The Scope of Consent

IF 2.8 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW Pub Date : 2023-07-01 DOI:10.1215/00318108-10469590
Danielle Bromwich
{"title":"<i>The Scope of Consent</i>","authors":"Danielle Bromwich","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10469590","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Consent covers certain actions but not others. If I lend you my new car, you are now free to use it to run errands but not to compete in a demolition derby. This is obvious enough, but determining exactly what I have permitted is much harder. Since you cannot read my mind, you cannot know for sure which uses of the car fall within the contours of my consent. But if you get this wrong, you use my car without my permission, and that is a rights violation. There is a lot riding on determining which actions are permitted by my consent. Fortunately, Tom Dougherty offers us a novel way to determine this in their excellent book The Scope of Consent.It is natural to think that the scope of consent is fixed by what the consent-giver intended to permit. This captures the intuition that the scope of consent is controlled by the person giving consent. This used to be Dougherty’s view. However, this Permissive Intentions View is implausible. Suppose I had no intention of lending you my car—I only said you could borrow it because I falsely believed it would not start. Despite saying you could use it, this view implies that your use would not fall under the scope of my consent since I did not, in fact, intend you to use it. Cases like these lead Dougherty to reject the Permissive Intentions View in parts 1 and 2 of the book. And, since this view is implied by the Mental View of Consent—the view that we consent only if we have a certain mental attitude—they reject that too.Another plausible idea is that the scope of consent is fixed by what the consent-giver successfully communicates to the consent-receiver. This is intuitive in two respects. First, while most people agree that the consent-giver should determine what has been permitted, they also think that the consent-receiver should have epistemic access to whatever falls within the scope of consent. Second, this view implies that consent is a public phenomenon. Dougherty agrees with the second implication, and this provides them with another reason to reject the Mental View in favor of a Behavioral View of Consent. However, they are not persuaded by the Successful Communication Principle itself. Since successful communication requires uptake, the view implies that the consent-giver has not waived their rights until the consent-receiver finds out. So, even if I leave you a note saying that you can borrow my car, I have not succeeded in consenting until you have read the note. Dougherty finds this counterintuitive, and they therefore reject the view.Dougherty agrees that consent requires public behavior, and so the Successful Communication Account is the closest rival to the view they end up defending. And yet, despite engaging with arguments offered in favor of a view that makes consent and its scope a matter of private intention in part 1 of the book, there is no discussion of arguments offered in favor of a view that makes consent and its scope a matter of public performance in part 2. As a result, Dougherty fails to consider why uptake might be a feature—rather than a bug—of any view that attempts to do justice to the bilateral nature of consent. To see what is attractive about uptake, consider the function consent plays in interpersonal morality. If you have read my note, you can appeal to it to justify your use of my car. However, if the note falls behind the back of the shelf before you could read it or if my partner grabs it, intends to give it to you, and promptly forgets, you have no good reason to think you are now permitted to borrow my car. To justify an action that would be impermissible without my consent, it is not enough that others have good reason to believe you have my permission; you need to have good reason to believe you have it, and that requires uptake. The lack of engagement with actual defenses of the Successful Communication Account is a little unfortunate here given the virtues of that view and the limitations of Dougherty’s own (which to their credit, they discuss at length at the end of the book.)With the goal of reconciling the intuitions that pulled us toward each rejected view—namely, that the consent-giver should determine the scope of consent and yet the consent-receiver must have epistemic access to what is permitted— Dougherty offers us their Evidential Account in part 3 of the book. The account comprises (1) a view about what constitutes consent (the Expression of Will View), (2) a principle that determines the scope of consent (the Due Diligence Principle), and (3) an argument that supports both (the Interpersonal Justification Argument). The Expression of Will View preserves the intuition that the consent-giver plays a role in determining the scope of consent since consent just is a deliberate expression of will. However, the Due Diligence Principle ensures that the scope of consent is fixed by certain evidence that is available to parties to the consent transaction, so the consent-receiver has epistemic access to what is permitted. In turn, each is supported by the Interpersonal Justification Argument, which tells us that “consent is morally significant as a consideration that the consent-receiver could appeal to in order to justify their behaviour to the consent-giver” (149). Now, since the Interpersonal Justification Argument also supports the Successful Communication Account, the reason to favor the Evidential Account over its rival is because it has “the explanatory power to predict intuitive results about the various cases … encountered” (149).While the originality of this complex and intuitive account is impressive, its explanatory power is doubtful. To see this, consider the Due Diligence Principle. To fall within the scope of consent, Dougherty claims that an action must meet three necessary and jointly sufficient conditions, and these constitute the Due Diligence Principle. First, consent must be given at a specific time and not retracted. Second, at that time, the available and reliable evidence must sufficiently support the interpretation that consent is given to that act. This evidence not only refers to “what the consent-giver intends to cover” (140), but both parties “must reasonably accept that this evidence bears on how the consent ought to be interpreted” (140). The evidence might include (just) conventions, the conversational context, and knowledge of the consent-giver, and while the evidence must be available to the consent-receiver, they might not be aware of it yet. And so, third, at the time consent is given, the enhanced reliable evidence must also sufficiently support the interpretation that consent has been given to that act. This evidence is obtained when the consent-receiver discharges certain duties of due diligence to investigate what the consent-giver intended to permit.What is supposed to set the Evidential Account apart is its explanatory power, and yet we would be hard pushed to derive anything from the Due Diligence Principle alone. It is silent on a range of normative issues that need settling before we could determine whether an action falls within the scope of consent. For instance, an action only falls within the contours of consent if parties reasonably accept that the reliable and available evidence supports how the consent ought to be interpreted. However, the principle itself tells us nothing about whether and why certain facts ought to be accepted by parties to the consent transaction. Dougherty admits that “a lot of heavy lifting is done by the notion of what evidence someone must reasonably accept” here, and the reliance on normative intuitions about reasonableness renders “the principle … less explanatory” (150). But this is far from the only place we find intuitions shouldering the explanatory load. The principle is also silent on what constitutes adequate investigation of what the consent-giver intended to permit or what constitutes a low- or high-stakes consent decision, and so we need to rely on normative intuitions when applying the principle here too. The upshot is this: when taken alone, the principle cannot explain intuitive verdicts about consent cases, and it offers no guidance about whether actions fall within the scope of consent when intuitions about reasonableness, adequateness of investigation, or stakes of the consent decision are contested.However, these criticisms should not be read as minimizing the importance of this highly original account. The value of the book does not lie in Dougherty’s solution to the problem but in the cases and arguments they provide to deepen our understanding of consent. The Expression of Will View is a case in point. On this view, consent is not a matter of intending to release someone from a duty, it is a matter of doing so with a deliberate expression of will. We can do this by expressing permission, of course, but Dougherty thinks that we can also consent by issuing a directive that is not an expression of permission. This challenges the prevailing view: most scholars agree that to give consent the consent-giver must understand that they are giving consent. However, Dougherty provides a range of fascinating cases in which the consent-giver could not be read as intentionally waiving their rights, and yet they seem to give consent all the same. One such case is Patriarchal Marriage: Wife believes that she has waived her rights against Husband’s sexual trespass by getting married, but now she says to him, “I know that you do not need my permission for sex, but would you like to have sex?” (91) Dougherty thinks that she consents to sex with this proposal, and yet it could not be an expression of permission since she does not believe Husband needs her permission to have sex with her. Even though she does not take herself to be waiving a right against sexual trespass (because she thinks that that right has already been waived), by proposing this joint action she succeeds in giving Husband a good reason to think he is now permitted to have sex with her. The implication is surprising: a consent-giver may be able to give consent without understanding that that is what they are doing.The Scope of Consent is full of similarly novel arguments, stimulating cases, and creative proposals. And, in many ways, Dougherty achieves something remarkable in this book: they envisage a way of determining the scope of consent that perfectly balances the control we think the consent-giver ought to have over what they have consented to without denying the consent-receiver epistemic access to what falls within the contours of that consent. Although there are problems with the account, none is insurmountable, and an account that promises to balance these considerations has high value. Those working in the field—and those outside who want a clear insight into a major debate in the area—will profit from reading this beautifully written, imaginative, and ambitious book.","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"158 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":2.8000,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10469590","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Consent covers certain actions but not others. If I lend you my new car, you are now free to use it to run errands but not to compete in a demolition derby. This is obvious enough, but determining exactly what I have permitted is much harder. Since you cannot read my mind, you cannot know for sure which uses of the car fall within the contours of my consent. But if you get this wrong, you use my car without my permission, and that is a rights violation. There is a lot riding on determining which actions are permitted by my consent. Fortunately, Tom Dougherty offers us a novel way to determine this in their excellent book The Scope of Consent.It is natural to think that the scope of consent is fixed by what the consent-giver intended to permit. This captures the intuition that the scope of consent is controlled by the person giving consent. This used to be Dougherty’s view. However, this Permissive Intentions View is implausible. Suppose I had no intention of lending you my car—I only said you could borrow it because I falsely believed it would not start. Despite saying you could use it, this view implies that your use would not fall under the scope of my consent since I did not, in fact, intend you to use it. Cases like these lead Dougherty to reject the Permissive Intentions View in parts 1 and 2 of the book. And, since this view is implied by the Mental View of Consent—the view that we consent only if we have a certain mental attitude—they reject that too.Another plausible idea is that the scope of consent is fixed by what the consent-giver successfully communicates to the consent-receiver. This is intuitive in two respects. First, while most people agree that the consent-giver should determine what has been permitted, they also think that the consent-receiver should have epistemic access to whatever falls within the scope of consent. Second, this view implies that consent is a public phenomenon. Dougherty agrees with the second implication, and this provides them with another reason to reject the Mental View in favor of a Behavioral View of Consent. However, they are not persuaded by the Successful Communication Principle itself. Since successful communication requires uptake, the view implies that the consent-giver has not waived their rights until the consent-receiver finds out. So, even if I leave you a note saying that you can borrow my car, I have not succeeded in consenting until you have read the note. Dougherty finds this counterintuitive, and they therefore reject the view.Dougherty agrees that consent requires public behavior, and so the Successful Communication Account is the closest rival to the view they end up defending. And yet, despite engaging with arguments offered in favor of a view that makes consent and its scope a matter of private intention in part 1 of the book, there is no discussion of arguments offered in favor of a view that makes consent and its scope a matter of public performance in part 2. As a result, Dougherty fails to consider why uptake might be a feature—rather than a bug—of any view that attempts to do justice to the bilateral nature of consent. To see what is attractive about uptake, consider the function consent plays in interpersonal morality. If you have read my note, you can appeal to it to justify your use of my car. However, if the note falls behind the back of the shelf before you could read it or if my partner grabs it, intends to give it to you, and promptly forgets, you have no good reason to think you are now permitted to borrow my car. To justify an action that would be impermissible without my consent, it is not enough that others have good reason to believe you have my permission; you need to have good reason to believe you have it, and that requires uptake. The lack of engagement with actual defenses of the Successful Communication Account is a little unfortunate here given the virtues of that view and the limitations of Dougherty’s own (which to their credit, they discuss at length at the end of the book.)With the goal of reconciling the intuitions that pulled us toward each rejected view—namely, that the consent-giver should determine the scope of consent and yet the consent-receiver must have epistemic access to what is permitted— Dougherty offers us their Evidential Account in part 3 of the book. The account comprises (1) a view about what constitutes consent (the Expression of Will View), (2) a principle that determines the scope of consent (the Due Diligence Principle), and (3) an argument that supports both (the Interpersonal Justification Argument). The Expression of Will View preserves the intuition that the consent-giver plays a role in determining the scope of consent since consent just is a deliberate expression of will. However, the Due Diligence Principle ensures that the scope of consent is fixed by certain evidence that is available to parties to the consent transaction, so the consent-receiver has epistemic access to what is permitted. In turn, each is supported by the Interpersonal Justification Argument, which tells us that “consent is morally significant as a consideration that the consent-receiver could appeal to in order to justify their behaviour to the consent-giver” (149). Now, since the Interpersonal Justification Argument also supports the Successful Communication Account, the reason to favor the Evidential Account over its rival is because it has “the explanatory power to predict intuitive results about the various cases … encountered” (149).While the originality of this complex and intuitive account is impressive, its explanatory power is doubtful. To see this, consider the Due Diligence Principle. To fall within the scope of consent, Dougherty claims that an action must meet three necessary and jointly sufficient conditions, and these constitute the Due Diligence Principle. First, consent must be given at a specific time and not retracted. Second, at that time, the available and reliable evidence must sufficiently support the interpretation that consent is given to that act. This evidence not only refers to “what the consent-giver intends to cover” (140), but both parties “must reasonably accept that this evidence bears on how the consent ought to be interpreted” (140). The evidence might include (just) conventions, the conversational context, and knowledge of the consent-giver, and while the evidence must be available to the consent-receiver, they might not be aware of it yet. And so, third, at the time consent is given, the enhanced reliable evidence must also sufficiently support the interpretation that consent has been given to that act. This evidence is obtained when the consent-receiver discharges certain duties of due diligence to investigate what the consent-giver intended to permit.What is supposed to set the Evidential Account apart is its explanatory power, and yet we would be hard pushed to derive anything from the Due Diligence Principle alone. It is silent on a range of normative issues that need settling before we could determine whether an action falls within the scope of consent. For instance, an action only falls within the contours of consent if parties reasonably accept that the reliable and available evidence supports how the consent ought to be interpreted. However, the principle itself tells us nothing about whether and why certain facts ought to be accepted by parties to the consent transaction. Dougherty admits that “a lot of heavy lifting is done by the notion of what evidence someone must reasonably accept” here, and the reliance on normative intuitions about reasonableness renders “the principle … less explanatory” (150). But this is far from the only place we find intuitions shouldering the explanatory load. The principle is also silent on what constitutes adequate investigation of what the consent-giver intended to permit or what constitutes a low- or high-stakes consent decision, and so we need to rely on normative intuitions when applying the principle here too. The upshot is this: when taken alone, the principle cannot explain intuitive verdicts about consent cases, and it offers no guidance about whether actions fall within the scope of consent when intuitions about reasonableness, adequateness of investigation, or stakes of the consent decision are contested.However, these criticisms should not be read as minimizing the importance of this highly original account. The value of the book does not lie in Dougherty’s solution to the problem but in the cases and arguments they provide to deepen our understanding of consent. The Expression of Will View is a case in point. On this view, consent is not a matter of intending to release someone from a duty, it is a matter of doing so with a deliberate expression of will. We can do this by expressing permission, of course, but Dougherty thinks that we can also consent by issuing a directive that is not an expression of permission. This challenges the prevailing view: most scholars agree that to give consent the consent-giver must understand that they are giving consent. However, Dougherty provides a range of fascinating cases in which the consent-giver could not be read as intentionally waiving their rights, and yet they seem to give consent all the same. One such case is Patriarchal Marriage: Wife believes that she has waived her rights against Husband’s sexual trespass by getting married, but now she says to him, “I know that you do not need my permission for sex, but would you like to have sex?” (91) Dougherty thinks that she consents to sex with this proposal, and yet it could not be an expression of permission since she does not believe Husband needs her permission to have sex with her. Even though she does not take herself to be waiving a right against sexual trespass (because she thinks that that right has already been waived), by proposing this joint action she succeeds in giving Husband a good reason to think he is now permitted to have sex with her. The implication is surprising: a consent-giver may be able to give consent without understanding that that is what they are doing.The Scope of Consent is full of similarly novel arguments, stimulating cases, and creative proposals. And, in many ways, Dougherty achieves something remarkable in this book: they envisage a way of determining the scope of consent that perfectly balances the control we think the consent-giver ought to have over what they have consented to without denying the consent-receiver epistemic access to what falls within the contours of that consent. Although there are problems with the account, none is insurmountable, and an account that promises to balance these considerations has high value. Those working in the field—and those outside who want a clear insight into a major debate in the area—will profit from reading this beautifully written, imaginative, and ambitious book.
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
同意范围
同意涵盖某些行为,但不包括其他行为。如果我把我的新车借给你,你现在可以自由地用它跑腿,但不能参加拆迁比赛。这是显而易见的,但要确定我究竟允许了什么就困难得多了。既然你不能读懂我的心思,你就不能确切地知道这辆车的哪些用途在我同意的范围内。但如果你弄错了,你未经我允许就用了我的车,这是侵犯人权。在我的同意下,哪些行动是允许的,这是很重要的。幸运的是,汤姆·多尔蒂在他的优秀著作《同意的范围》中为我们提供了一种新颖的方法来确定这一点。人们很自然地认为,同意的范围是由同意的人打算允许什么来确定的。这抓住了一种直觉,即同意的范围由给予同意的人控制。这曾经是多尔蒂的观点。然而,这种宽容的意图观点是不可信的。假设我无意把我的车借给你——我只是说你可以借,因为我错误地认为它发动不了。尽管说你可以使用它,但这种观点意味着你的使用不属于我同意的范围,因为事实上我并没有打算让你使用它。像这样的案例导致多尔蒂在书的第1部分和第2部分中拒绝了宽容意图观点。而且,由于这一观点隐含在同意的心理观点中,即只有当我们有某种心理态度时,我们才会同意,他们也拒绝了这一观点。另一个似是而非的观点是,同意的范围是由同意者与同意接受者成功沟通的内容决定的。这在两个方面是直观的。首先,虽然大多数人同意同意的人应该决定什么是允许的,但他们也认为同意的接受者应该对同意范围内的任何东西都有认知上的访问权。其次,这种观点暗示同意是一种公共现象。Dougherty同意第二种暗示,这为他们提供了另一个理由来拒绝心理观点而支持行为观点。然而,他们并没有被成功沟通原则本身所说服。由于成功的沟通需要理解,这种观点意味着,在同意的接受者发现之前,同意的给予者并没有放弃他们的权利。所以,即使我给你留了一张纸条,说你可以借我的车,在你看了纸条之前,我还没有成功地同意。多尔蒂发现这是违反直觉的,因此他们拒绝接受这种观点。多尔蒂同意同意需要公众行为,因此成功沟通账户是他们最终捍卫的观点最接近的对手。然而,尽管在书的第一部分中讨论了支持同意及其范围是私人意图问题的观点,但在第二部分中没有讨论支持同意及其范围是公共行为问题的观点。因此,Dougherty没有考虑到为什么对于任何试图公正对待双方同意本质的观点来说,“接受”可能是一个特征——而不是一个缺陷。要了解“接受”的吸引力,可以考虑“同意”在人际道德中所起的作用。如果你读了我的笔记,你可以用它来证明你使用我的车是合理的。然而,如果你还没来得及看,纸条就掉在书架后面了,或者我的伴侣抓住它,打算给你,但很快就忘了,你就没有理由认为你现在可以借我的车了。要证明没有我的同意就不被允许的行为是正当的,别人有充分的理由相信你得到了我的允许是不够的;你需要有充分的理由相信你拥有它,这需要吸收。考虑到这种观点的优点和多尔蒂自己的局限性(值得赞扬的是,他们在书的最后详细讨论了这一点),这里缺乏对成功沟通理论的实际辩护的参与有点不幸。为了调和把我们拉向每一个被拒绝的观点的直觉——也就是说,同意的给予者应该决定同意的范围,而同意的接受者必须在认知上获得允许的范围——多尔蒂在书的第三部分为我们提供了他们的证据说明。该解释包括(1)关于什么构成同意的观点(意志表达观点),(2)确定同意范围的原则(尽职调查原则),以及(3)支持两者的论点(人际辩护论点)。意志表达观点保留了同意给予者在决定同意范围中起作用的直觉,因为同意只是一种有意的意志表达。 即使她不认为自己放弃了反对性侵犯的权利(因为她认为这种权利已经被放弃了),通过提出这种联合行动,她成功地给了丈夫一个很好的理由,让他认为他现在被允许和她发生性关系。这其中的含义令人惊讶:一个同意的人可能会在不明白自己在做什么的情况下表示同意。《同意的范围》中充满了同样新颖的论点、刺激的案例和创造性的建议。而且,在很多方面,多尔蒂在这本书中取得了一些了不起的成就:他们设想了一种确定同意范围的方法,这种方法完美地平衡了我们认为同意给予者应该对他们所同意的内容拥有的控制权,而不否认同意接受者对该同意范围内的内容的认知访问。虽然账户存在问题,但没有什么是无法克服的,一个承诺平衡这些因素的账户具有很高的价值。那些在这一领域工作的人,以及那些想要对这一领域的主要争论有一个清晰见解的局外人,都将从阅读这本文笔优美、想象力丰富、雄心勃勃的书中获益。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW PHILOSOPHY-
CiteScore
7.40
自引率
0.00%
发文量
17
期刊介绍: In continuous publication since 1892, the Philosophical Review has a long-standing reputation for excellence and has published many papers now considered classics in the field, such as W. V. O. Quine"s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” Thomas Nagel"s “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” and the early work of John Rawls. The journal aims to publish original scholarly work in all areas of analytic philosophy, with an emphasis on material of general interest to academic philosophers, and is one of the few journals in the discipline to publish book reviews.
期刊最新文献
Reasons First Dark Matters: Pessimism and the Problem of Suffering Democratic Law Sustaining Democracy: What We Owe to the Other Side Mind and World in Aristotle’s De Anima
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1