以目标为中心的美德伦理学

IF 2.8 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI:10.1215/00318108-10294500
Liezl van Zyl
{"title":"以目标为中心的美德伦理学","authors":"Liezl van Zyl","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10294500","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Christine Swanton is, without question, one of the leading scholars in contemporary virtue ethics. Nevertheless, and somewhat surprisingly, her target-centered account of virtue ethics, which was developed in Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic Account (2003) and a series of articles, has not garnered much support. Part of the reason has to do with the sheer popularity of Aristotelian virtue ethics, in particular Rosalind Hursthouse’s book On Virtue Ethics (1999). However, I suspect that the main reason for its comparative lack of popularity is the complexity of her work. Swanton’s analyses tend to be much deeper and more detailed than her competitors’ work. She draws from, and assumes a familiarity with, a wide range of scholarly literature as well as different philosophical traditions, with the result that her work is inaccessible to students. As George Harris (2004) writes in his review of Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic Account, the book is “[w]ritten for advanced specialists in moral theory [and] … framed within a technical vocabulary that requires concentrated effort to master before its contributions can be appreciated. Even those who are already familiar with a good bit of the virtue-ethics literature will have to orient the issues to her terminological framework.” Target Centred Virtue Ethics is no exception. It is aimed at advanced specialists in normative theory and metaethics. However, I was pleased to see that some of the chapters are accessible to students. In particular, Chapter 5, in which Swanton explains and defends the basic features of target-centered virtue ethics, can (and should!) be incorporated into an upper-level ethics syllabus alongside the standard introductory readings on Aristotelian virtue ethics.I give a summary of the main features of Swanton’s account and then comment on the structure of the book.Target-centered virtue ethics shares two features with other forms of virtue ethics: it takes thick evaluative concepts, such as generous, kind, callous, and cruel, as central, and it evaluates actions and agents through the notions of virtue and vice. It has two distinguishing features. The first is its account of right action. On the Aristotelian view proposed by Hursthouse (1999), an action is right if it is what an ideally virtuous agent would characteristically do in the circumstances. Swanton rejects this view on the grounds that a virtuous agent—someone with practical wisdom—is fallible. Instead, she proposes that an action is right if it hits the target(s) of the relevant virtues. The basic idea is fairly simple: The target of benevolence is to promote the good of others, so an action is right if it succeeds in doing so. Swanton further develops this idea with the help of Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean. Aristotle takes the mean to be multidimensional: It is not simply a matter of hitting the mean between, say, giving too much and giving too little, but also of “acting in the right circumstance, in the right manner, at the right time, to the right extent, for the right reasons, with respect to the right people or objects, deploying the right instruments” (42). A further complication is that the target of a particular virtue depends on the context, including things such as the agent’s role and relationships, as well as cultural and historical features. Swanton argues that virtue ethics needs to move beyond its reliance on “basic” virtues such as honesty, generosity, justice, and so on. These abstract notions are not very useful. To apply to the real world, the basic virtues should be differentiated according to the agent’s role and stage of life, cultural location, historical features, and so on. One possible advantage of this approach is that it allows us to solve the familiar “dilemma of role ethics.” That is, it acknowledges the existence of role-differentiated obligations, while at the same time it denies that role occupiers are sometimes required to act immorally (181–98).The second distinguishing feature of target-centered virtue ethics is that it gives a pluralistic account of what makes a trait a virtue. Aristotelian virtue ethicists subscribe to some version of the eudaimonist thesis: “It is a necessary condition of a trait being a virtue that it characteristically benefits its possessor” (123). Swanton rejected this thesis in her earlier work (2003), but in doing so she invited the objection that she denies the link between virtue and flourishing. Such a denial is implausible because it is easy to demonstrate how being virtuous—kind, honest, compassionate, just—benefits the agent (and, conversely, how being vicious—dishonest, cruel, selfish, unreliable—makes them unhappy). However, the objection is unfounded, for as Swanton explains, she does not reject the claim that “agents need virtue to flourish.” The latter specifies a necessary condition on flourishing, and a noneudaimonist can support this view. Rather, she rejects the claim that it is a necessary condition for virtue that it characteristically benefits its possessor. One of her reasons is that it is simply not true that every virtue characteristically benefits its possessor. For example, a freedom fighter might be truly courageous without it being the case that their courage characteristically promotes their flourishing (124). Eudaimonism also encounters the familiar egoism (or narcissism) objection: If the virtuous person is ultimately motivated by her own flourishing or excellence of character, that is, if she takes her own flourishing to be the finest good for her, then she is intolerably egoistic rather than genuinely virtuous. Swanton argues that eudaimonism can only avoid this problem by establishing a problematic disconnect between the virtuous agent’s final ends (her own flourishing) and her motives for acting (such as helping others, respecting their rights, etc.). A target-centered account avoids the disconnect objection by claiming that “what makes actions right is hitting the targets of (relevant) virtues in relation to action, what makes traits virtues is determined by their targets or aims, and what should motivate an agent at both fundamental and everyday levels are these very features” (134–35). It is, as she puts it, “everywhere direct” (133).The book has three parts. Part I (“Metaphysics”) develops a “new metaphysics” for virtue ethics as an alternative to the metaphysics inspired by Philippa Foot’s influential book, Natural Goodness (2001). Swanton describes it as “a form of response-dependence view inspired by Heidegger, Hume, and McDowell” (8). It is committed to the following metaethical theses: ethical realism (factualism and objectivism), descriptivism, and reasons and/or fittingness fundamentalism. Although the material is clearly structured, part I is written for specialists in metaethics and assumes a familiarity with McDowell’s critique of Aristotelian naturalism as well as Heideggerian ontology.Part II (“Nature”) gives an account of the nature of Swanton’s virtue ethics. Chapter 5 begins with a critique of eudaimonism and then presents the main features of target-centered virtue ethics, including its account of right action. Chapters 6, 7, and 8 explore the idea that virtue is “differentiated.” A virtue such as generosity exists in many different forms, depending on cultural and historical features, the role someone occupies, their stage of life, relationships, and so on. This view raises important questions about the link between differentiated virtue (or “role ethics”) and “ordinary morality,” and Swanton argues for what she calls an “integrated view,” namely that role-differentiated morality is constrained by ordinary morality (158). Chapter 8 draws on research in moral psychology to counter the popular Aristotelian view that the young cannot be virtuous. Swanton argues that virtue is differentiated according to stage of life, so we can speak of children’s virtues and virtues that are proper to old age. Chapter 9 gives a pluralistic account of the “grounds” of virtue (i.e., the features that make a trait a virtue) and is an attractive alternative to monistic accounts such as eudaimonism and consequentialism.Part III (“Application”) addresses a number of theoretical issues related to right action and action guidance. The first two chapters will be of interest to all normative theorists. Chapter 10, “Has Virtue Ethics Sold Out?” addresses an important question about right action: Given Elizabeth Anscombe’s (1958) claim that the notions of “moral obligation and moral duty” should be “jettisoned” (1), is it a mistake for contemporary virtue ethicists to offer an account of right action? Swanton answers in the negative, and she argues that we should not interpret Anscombe as rejecting deontic notions per se. Anscombe rejects the notion of moral obligation or moral rightness, where the moral has a special “mesmeric force” that commits the theorist to a dubious metaphysics (a “supreme lawgiver”), and virtue ethics does not offer an account of moral rightness in this special sense. Does this mean virtue ethics is not playing the same game, that it uses “rightness” in way that differs from standard usage? Swanton’s response is that there is no standard conception of rightness. It is, as W. B. Gallie puts it, an “essentially contested” concept (249). Unlike some virtue ethicists, Swanton thinks we should accommodate rightness understood in terms of requirements, permissions, and obligations, and that virtue ethics can do so without using the concept in the problematic special sense. Chapter 11 addresses the familiar objection that virtue ethics cannot provide action guidance because it is committed to particularism and therefore “uncodifiable.” Swanton embraces a fairly radical (but reasonable) form of particularism. She argues that the fact that an action is honest, say, does not necessarily count as a reason in its favor. However, she thinks virtue ethics is sufficiently codifiable through the “virtue rules” as long as these are understood as providing “default reasons.” Thus, for example, one should “be honest” unless “certain complicating factors intervene” (266). The final two chapters revisit topics discussed in part I relating to the logos of ethics (Chapter 12) and epistemology (Chapter 13).Swanton makes some helpful suggestions about how different chapters can be grouped together according to themes (11). To readers who are not familiar with Swanton’s virtue ethics, I would suggest reading the introduction, in which Swanton identifies two theses that characterize virtue ethics as a family, and then moving on to Chapter 5 (“Eudaimonistic versus Target Centred Virtue Ethics”), Chapter 9 (“On the Grounds of Virtue”), and Chapter 10 (“Has Virtue Ethics Sold Out?”). Readers who are familiar with Swanton’s work will notice that the volume contains material that is published elsewhere in some form. To them, I would strongly suggest reading the volume from cover to cover. It contains a significant amount of new material, and the previously published work is suitably modified such that the volume gives a comprehensive and systematic framework for understanding ethics. Swanton’s target-centered virtue ethics shares many of the attractive features of Aristotelian virtue ethics, but it is much more refined and sophisticated and thereby (arguably) avoids many of the weaknesses of Aristotelianism.","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"4 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":2.8000,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"<i>Target Centred Virtue Ethics</i>\",\"authors\":\"Liezl van Zyl\",\"doi\":\"10.1215/00318108-10294500\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Christine Swanton is, without question, one of the leading scholars in contemporary virtue ethics. Nevertheless, and somewhat surprisingly, her target-centered account of virtue ethics, which was developed in Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic Account (2003) and a series of articles, has not garnered much support. Part of the reason has to do with the sheer popularity of Aristotelian virtue ethics, in particular Rosalind Hursthouse’s book On Virtue Ethics (1999). However, I suspect that the main reason for its comparative lack of popularity is the complexity of her work. Swanton’s analyses tend to be much deeper and more detailed than her competitors’ work. She draws from, and assumes a familiarity with, a wide range of scholarly literature as well as different philosophical traditions, with the result that her work is inaccessible to students. As George Harris (2004) writes in his review of Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic Account, the book is “[w]ritten for advanced specialists in moral theory [and] … framed within a technical vocabulary that requires concentrated effort to master before its contributions can be appreciated. Even those who are already familiar with a good bit of the virtue-ethics literature will have to orient the issues to her terminological framework.” Target Centred Virtue Ethics is no exception. It is aimed at advanced specialists in normative theory and metaethics. However, I was pleased to see that some of the chapters are accessible to students. In particular, Chapter 5, in which Swanton explains and defends the basic features of target-centered virtue ethics, can (and should!) be incorporated into an upper-level ethics syllabus alongside the standard introductory readings on Aristotelian virtue ethics.I give a summary of the main features of Swanton’s account and then comment on the structure of the book.Target-centered virtue ethics shares two features with other forms of virtue ethics: it takes thick evaluative concepts, such as generous, kind, callous, and cruel, as central, and it evaluates actions and agents through the notions of virtue and vice. It has two distinguishing features. The first is its account of right action. On the Aristotelian view proposed by Hursthouse (1999), an action is right if it is what an ideally virtuous agent would characteristically do in the circumstances. Swanton rejects this view on the grounds that a virtuous agent—someone with practical wisdom—is fallible. Instead, she proposes that an action is right if it hits the target(s) of the relevant virtues. The basic idea is fairly simple: The target of benevolence is to promote the good of others, so an action is right if it succeeds in doing so. Swanton further develops this idea with the help of Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean. Aristotle takes the mean to be multidimensional: It is not simply a matter of hitting the mean between, say, giving too much and giving too little, but also of “acting in the right circumstance, in the right manner, at the right time, to the right extent, for the right reasons, with respect to the right people or objects, deploying the right instruments” (42). A further complication is that the target of a particular virtue depends on the context, including things such as the agent’s role and relationships, as well as cultural and historical features. Swanton argues that virtue ethics needs to move beyond its reliance on “basic” virtues such as honesty, generosity, justice, and so on. These abstract notions are not very useful. To apply to the real world, the basic virtues should be differentiated according to the agent’s role and stage of life, cultural location, historical features, and so on. One possible advantage of this approach is that it allows us to solve the familiar “dilemma of role ethics.” That is, it acknowledges the existence of role-differentiated obligations, while at the same time it denies that role occupiers are sometimes required to act immorally (181–98).The second distinguishing feature of target-centered virtue ethics is that it gives a pluralistic account of what makes a trait a virtue. Aristotelian virtue ethicists subscribe to some version of the eudaimonist thesis: “It is a necessary condition of a trait being a virtue that it characteristically benefits its possessor” (123). Swanton rejected this thesis in her earlier work (2003), but in doing so she invited the objection that she denies the link between virtue and flourishing. Such a denial is implausible because it is easy to demonstrate how being virtuous—kind, honest, compassionate, just—benefits the agent (and, conversely, how being vicious—dishonest, cruel, selfish, unreliable—makes them unhappy). However, the objection is unfounded, for as Swanton explains, she does not reject the claim that “agents need virtue to flourish.” The latter specifies a necessary condition on flourishing, and a noneudaimonist can support this view. Rather, she rejects the claim that it is a necessary condition for virtue that it characteristically benefits its possessor. One of her reasons is that it is simply not true that every virtue characteristically benefits its possessor. For example, a freedom fighter might be truly courageous without it being the case that their courage characteristically promotes their flourishing (124). Eudaimonism also encounters the familiar egoism (or narcissism) objection: If the virtuous person is ultimately motivated by her own flourishing or excellence of character, that is, if she takes her own flourishing to be the finest good for her, then she is intolerably egoistic rather than genuinely virtuous. Swanton argues that eudaimonism can only avoid this problem by establishing a problematic disconnect between the virtuous agent’s final ends (her own flourishing) and her motives for acting (such as helping others, respecting their rights, etc.). A target-centered account avoids the disconnect objection by claiming that “what makes actions right is hitting the targets of (relevant) virtues in relation to action, what makes traits virtues is determined by their targets or aims, and what should motivate an agent at both fundamental and everyday levels are these very features” (134–35). It is, as she puts it, “everywhere direct” (133).The book has three parts. Part I (“Metaphysics”) develops a “new metaphysics” for virtue ethics as an alternative to the metaphysics inspired by Philippa Foot’s influential book, Natural Goodness (2001). Swanton describes it as “a form of response-dependence view inspired by Heidegger, Hume, and McDowell” (8). It is committed to the following metaethical theses: ethical realism (factualism and objectivism), descriptivism, and reasons and/or fittingness fundamentalism. Although the material is clearly structured, part I is written for specialists in metaethics and assumes a familiarity with McDowell’s critique of Aristotelian naturalism as well as Heideggerian ontology.Part II (“Nature”) gives an account of the nature of Swanton’s virtue ethics. Chapter 5 begins with a critique of eudaimonism and then presents the main features of target-centered virtue ethics, including its account of right action. Chapters 6, 7, and 8 explore the idea that virtue is “differentiated.” A virtue such as generosity exists in many different forms, depending on cultural and historical features, the role someone occupies, their stage of life, relationships, and so on. This view raises important questions about the link between differentiated virtue (or “role ethics”) and “ordinary morality,” and Swanton argues for what she calls an “integrated view,” namely that role-differentiated morality is constrained by ordinary morality (158). Chapter 8 draws on research in moral psychology to counter the popular Aristotelian view that the young cannot be virtuous. Swanton argues that virtue is differentiated according to stage of life, so we can speak of children’s virtues and virtues that are proper to old age. Chapter 9 gives a pluralistic account of the “grounds” of virtue (i.e., the features that make a trait a virtue) and is an attractive alternative to monistic accounts such as eudaimonism and consequentialism.Part III (“Application”) addresses a number of theoretical issues related to right action and action guidance. The first two chapters will be of interest to all normative theorists. Chapter 10, “Has Virtue Ethics Sold Out?” addresses an important question about right action: Given Elizabeth Anscombe’s (1958) claim that the notions of “moral obligation and moral duty” should be “jettisoned” (1), is it a mistake for contemporary virtue ethicists to offer an account of right action? Swanton answers in the negative, and she argues that we should not interpret Anscombe as rejecting deontic notions per se. Anscombe rejects the notion of moral obligation or moral rightness, where the moral has a special “mesmeric force” that commits the theorist to a dubious metaphysics (a “supreme lawgiver”), and virtue ethics does not offer an account of moral rightness in this special sense. Does this mean virtue ethics is not playing the same game, that it uses “rightness” in way that differs from standard usage? Swanton’s response is that there is no standard conception of rightness. It is, as W. B. Gallie puts it, an “essentially contested” concept (249). Unlike some virtue ethicists, Swanton thinks we should accommodate rightness understood in terms of requirements, permissions, and obligations, and that virtue ethics can do so without using the concept in the problematic special sense. Chapter 11 addresses the familiar objection that virtue ethics cannot provide action guidance because it is committed to particularism and therefore “uncodifiable.” Swanton embraces a fairly radical (but reasonable) form of particularism. She argues that the fact that an action is honest, say, does not necessarily count as a reason in its favor. However, she thinks virtue ethics is sufficiently codifiable through the “virtue rules” as long as these are understood as providing “default reasons.” Thus, for example, one should “be honest” unless “certain complicating factors intervene” (266). The final two chapters revisit topics discussed in part I relating to the logos of ethics (Chapter 12) and epistemology (Chapter 13).Swanton makes some helpful suggestions about how different chapters can be grouped together according to themes (11). To readers who are not familiar with Swanton’s virtue ethics, I would suggest reading the introduction, in which Swanton identifies two theses that characterize virtue ethics as a family, and then moving on to Chapter 5 (“Eudaimonistic versus Target Centred Virtue Ethics”), Chapter 9 (“On the Grounds of Virtue”), and Chapter 10 (“Has Virtue Ethics Sold Out?”). Readers who are familiar with Swanton’s work will notice that the volume contains material that is published elsewhere in some form. To them, I would strongly suggest reading the volume from cover to cover. It contains a significant amount of new material, and the previously published work is suitably modified such that the volume gives a comprehensive and systematic framework for understanding ethics. Swanton’s target-centered virtue ethics shares many of the attractive features of Aristotelian virtue ethics, but it is much more refined and sophisticated and thereby (arguably) avoids many of the weaknesses of Aristotelianism.\",\"PeriodicalId\":48129,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW\",\"volume\":\"4 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":2.8000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-04-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10294500\",\"RegionNum\":1,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"0\",\"JCRName\":\"PHILOSOPHY\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10294500","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

毫无疑问,克里斯汀·斯旺顿是当代美德伦理学的主要学者之一。然而,有些令人惊讶的是,她在《美德伦理:多元化的解释》(2003)和一系列文章中发展起来的以目标为中心的美德伦理解释并没有获得太多支持。部分原因与亚里士多德的美德伦理学的绝对流行有关,特别是罗莎琳德·赫斯豪斯的《论美德伦理学》(1999)。然而,我怀疑其相对不受欢迎的主要原因是她的工作的复杂性。斯旺顿的分析往往比她的竞争对手的研究更深入、更详细。她从广泛的学术文献和不同的哲学传统中汲取灵感,并假设自己熟悉这些文献,结果是她的作品对学生来说是难以理解的。正如乔治·哈里斯(2004)在他的《美德伦理学:一个多元化的叙述》书评中所写的那样,这本书是“为道德理论的高级专家而写的[并且]……在一个技术词汇框架内,需要集中精力掌握,才能欣赏它的贡献。”即使是那些已经熟悉一些虚拟伦理学文献的人,也必须根据她的术语框架来定位问题。”以目标为中心的美德伦理学也不例外。它的目标是规范理论和元伦理学的高级专家。然而,我很高兴地看到,有些章节对学生来说是可以访问的。特别是,在第5章中,斯旺顿解释并捍卫了以目标为中心的美德伦理学的基本特征,这一章可以(也应该!)与关于亚里士多德美德伦理学的标准入门读物一起纳入高级伦理学教学大纲。我对斯旺顿叙述的主要特点作了一个总结,然后对这本书的结构作了评论。以目标为中心的美德伦理学与其他形式的美德伦理学有两个共同的特点:它以慷慨、善良、冷酷、残忍等厚重的评价概念为中心,通过善与恶的概念来评价行为和行为人。它有两个显著的特点。首先是它对正确行为的描述。根据赫斯特豪斯(1999)提出的亚里士多德观点,如果一个行为是一个理想的善良的行为者在这种情况下的典型行为,那么这个行为就是正确的。斯旺顿反对这种观点,理由是一个有道德的代理人——具有实践智慧的人——是容易犯错的。相反,她提出,如果一项行动达到了相关美德的目标,那么它就是正确的。其基本思想相当简单:仁慈的目标是促进他人的利益,因此,如果一项行动成功地做到了这一点,那么它就是正确的。斯旺顿在亚里士多德的中庸学说的帮助下进一步发展了这一观点。亚里士多德认为中庸是多维的:这不仅仅是在给予太多和给予太少之间达到中庸的问题,而且也是“在正确的情况下,以正确的方式,在正确的时间,以正确的程度,出于正确的原因,对正确的人或对象,使用正确的工具”(42)。更复杂的是,特定美德的目标取决于环境,包括行动者的角色和关系,以及文化和历史特征等。斯旺顿认为,美德伦理学需要超越对诚实、慷慨、正义等“基本”美德的依赖。这些抽象的概念不是很有用。为了适用于现实世界,应该根据代理人的角色和生活阶段、文化位置、历史特征等来区分基本美德。这种方法的一个可能的优点是,它允许我们解决熟悉的“角色伦理困境”。也就是说,它承认角色区分义务的存在,同时否认角色占有者有时被要求做出不道德的行为(181-98)。以目标为中心的美德伦理学的第二个显著特征是,它对什么使一种特质成为美德给出了多元化的解释。亚里士多德的美德伦理学家赞同唯美论的某些论点:“一种特质作为美德的必要条件是它的特征有利于它的拥有者”(123)。斯旺顿在她早期的作品(2003年)中否定了这一论点,但这样做招致了反对,即她否认了美德与繁荣之间的联系。这样的否认是难以置信的,因为很容易证明善良——善良、诚实、富有同情心、公正——如何使行为人受益(相反,邪恶——不诚实、残忍、自私、不可靠——如何使行为人不快乐)。然而,这种反对意见是没有根据的,因为正如斯旺顿解释的那样,她并不反对“代理人需要美德才能蓬勃发展”的说法。后者规定了繁荣的必要条件,非现实主义者可以支持这一观点。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Target Centred Virtue Ethics
Christine Swanton is, without question, one of the leading scholars in contemporary virtue ethics. Nevertheless, and somewhat surprisingly, her target-centered account of virtue ethics, which was developed in Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic Account (2003) and a series of articles, has not garnered much support. Part of the reason has to do with the sheer popularity of Aristotelian virtue ethics, in particular Rosalind Hursthouse’s book On Virtue Ethics (1999). However, I suspect that the main reason for its comparative lack of popularity is the complexity of her work. Swanton’s analyses tend to be much deeper and more detailed than her competitors’ work. She draws from, and assumes a familiarity with, a wide range of scholarly literature as well as different philosophical traditions, with the result that her work is inaccessible to students. As George Harris (2004) writes in his review of Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic Account, the book is “[w]ritten for advanced specialists in moral theory [and] … framed within a technical vocabulary that requires concentrated effort to master before its contributions can be appreciated. Even those who are already familiar with a good bit of the virtue-ethics literature will have to orient the issues to her terminological framework.” Target Centred Virtue Ethics is no exception. It is aimed at advanced specialists in normative theory and metaethics. However, I was pleased to see that some of the chapters are accessible to students. In particular, Chapter 5, in which Swanton explains and defends the basic features of target-centered virtue ethics, can (and should!) be incorporated into an upper-level ethics syllabus alongside the standard introductory readings on Aristotelian virtue ethics.I give a summary of the main features of Swanton’s account and then comment on the structure of the book.Target-centered virtue ethics shares two features with other forms of virtue ethics: it takes thick evaluative concepts, such as generous, kind, callous, and cruel, as central, and it evaluates actions and agents through the notions of virtue and vice. It has two distinguishing features. The first is its account of right action. On the Aristotelian view proposed by Hursthouse (1999), an action is right if it is what an ideally virtuous agent would characteristically do in the circumstances. Swanton rejects this view on the grounds that a virtuous agent—someone with practical wisdom—is fallible. Instead, she proposes that an action is right if it hits the target(s) of the relevant virtues. The basic idea is fairly simple: The target of benevolence is to promote the good of others, so an action is right if it succeeds in doing so. Swanton further develops this idea with the help of Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean. Aristotle takes the mean to be multidimensional: It is not simply a matter of hitting the mean between, say, giving too much and giving too little, but also of “acting in the right circumstance, in the right manner, at the right time, to the right extent, for the right reasons, with respect to the right people or objects, deploying the right instruments” (42). A further complication is that the target of a particular virtue depends on the context, including things such as the agent’s role and relationships, as well as cultural and historical features. Swanton argues that virtue ethics needs to move beyond its reliance on “basic” virtues such as honesty, generosity, justice, and so on. These abstract notions are not very useful. To apply to the real world, the basic virtues should be differentiated according to the agent’s role and stage of life, cultural location, historical features, and so on. One possible advantage of this approach is that it allows us to solve the familiar “dilemma of role ethics.” That is, it acknowledges the existence of role-differentiated obligations, while at the same time it denies that role occupiers are sometimes required to act immorally (181–98).The second distinguishing feature of target-centered virtue ethics is that it gives a pluralistic account of what makes a trait a virtue. Aristotelian virtue ethicists subscribe to some version of the eudaimonist thesis: “It is a necessary condition of a trait being a virtue that it characteristically benefits its possessor” (123). Swanton rejected this thesis in her earlier work (2003), but in doing so she invited the objection that she denies the link between virtue and flourishing. Such a denial is implausible because it is easy to demonstrate how being virtuous—kind, honest, compassionate, just—benefits the agent (and, conversely, how being vicious—dishonest, cruel, selfish, unreliable—makes them unhappy). However, the objection is unfounded, for as Swanton explains, she does not reject the claim that “agents need virtue to flourish.” The latter specifies a necessary condition on flourishing, and a noneudaimonist can support this view. Rather, she rejects the claim that it is a necessary condition for virtue that it characteristically benefits its possessor. One of her reasons is that it is simply not true that every virtue characteristically benefits its possessor. For example, a freedom fighter might be truly courageous without it being the case that their courage characteristically promotes their flourishing (124). Eudaimonism also encounters the familiar egoism (or narcissism) objection: If the virtuous person is ultimately motivated by her own flourishing or excellence of character, that is, if she takes her own flourishing to be the finest good for her, then she is intolerably egoistic rather than genuinely virtuous. Swanton argues that eudaimonism can only avoid this problem by establishing a problematic disconnect between the virtuous agent’s final ends (her own flourishing) and her motives for acting (such as helping others, respecting their rights, etc.). A target-centered account avoids the disconnect objection by claiming that “what makes actions right is hitting the targets of (relevant) virtues in relation to action, what makes traits virtues is determined by their targets or aims, and what should motivate an agent at both fundamental and everyday levels are these very features” (134–35). It is, as she puts it, “everywhere direct” (133).The book has three parts. Part I (“Metaphysics”) develops a “new metaphysics” for virtue ethics as an alternative to the metaphysics inspired by Philippa Foot’s influential book, Natural Goodness (2001). Swanton describes it as “a form of response-dependence view inspired by Heidegger, Hume, and McDowell” (8). It is committed to the following metaethical theses: ethical realism (factualism and objectivism), descriptivism, and reasons and/or fittingness fundamentalism. Although the material is clearly structured, part I is written for specialists in metaethics and assumes a familiarity with McDowell’s critique of Aristotelian naturalism as well as Heideggerian ontology.Part II (“Nature”) gives an account of the nature of Swanton’s virtue ethics. Chapter 5 begins with a critique of eudaimonism and then presents the main features of target-centered virtue ethics, including its account of right action. Chapters 6, 7, and 8 explore the idea that virtue is “differentiated.” A virtue such as generosity exists in many different forms, depending on cultural and historical features, the role someone occupies, their stage of life, relationships, and so on. This view raises important questions about the link between differentiated virtue (or “role ethics”) and “ordinary morality,” and Swanton argues for what she calls an “integrated view,” namely that role-differentiated morality is constrained by ordinary morality (158). Chapter 8 draws on research in moral psychology to counter the popular Aristotelian view that the young cannot be virtuous. Swanton argues that virtue is differentiated according to stage of life, so we can speak of children’s virtues and virtues that are proper to old age. Chapter 9 gives a pluralistic account of the “grounds” of virtue (i.e., the features that make a trait a virtue) and is an attractive alternative to monistic accounts such as eudaimonism and consequentialism.Part III (“Application”) addresses a number of theoretical issues related to right action and action guidance. The first two chapters will be of interest to all normative theorists. Chapter 10, “Has Virtue Ethics Sold Out?” addresses an important question about right action: Given Elizabeth Anscombe’s (1958) claim that the notions of “moral obligation and moral duty” should be “jettisoned” (1), is it a mistake for contemporary virtue ethicists to offer an account of right action? Swanton answers in the negative, and she argues that we should not interpret Anscombe as rejecting deontic notions per se. Anscombe rejects the notion of moral obligation or moral rightness, where the moral has a special “mesmeric force” that commits the theorist to a dubious metaphysics (a “supreme lawgiver”), and virtue ethics does not offer an account of moral rightness in this special sense. Does this mean virtue ethics is not playing the same game, that it uses “rightness” in way that differs from standard usage? Swanton’s response is that there is no standard conception of rightness. It is, as W. B. Gallie puts it, an “essentially contested” concept (249). Unlike some virtue ethicists, Swanton thinks we should accommodate rightness understood in terms of requirements, permissions, and obligations, and that virtue ethics can do so without using the concept in the problematic special sense. Chapter 11 addresses the familiar objection that virtue ethics cannot provide action guidance because it is committed to particularism and therefore “uncodifiable.” Swanton embraces a fairly radical (but reasonable) form of particularism. She argues that the fact that an action is honest, say, does not necessarily count as a reason in its favor. However, she thinks virtue ethics is sufficiently codifiable through the “virtue rules” as long as these are understood as providing “default reasons.” Thus, for example, one should “be honest” unless “certain complicating factors intervene” (266). The final two chapters revisit topics discussed in part I relating to the logos of ethics (Chapter 12) and epistemology (Chapter 13).Swanton makes some helpful suggestions about how different chapters can be grouped together according to themes (11). To readers who are not familiar with Swanton’s virtue ethics, I would suggest reading the introduction, in which Swanton identifies two theses that characterize virtue ethics as a family, and then moving on to Chapter 5 (“Eudaimonistic versus Target Centred Virtue Ethics”), Chapter 9 (“On the Grounds of Virtue”), and Chapter 10 (“Has Virtue Ethics Sold Out?”). Readers who are familiar with Swanton’s work will notice that the volume contains material that is published elsewhere in some form. To them, I would strongly suggest reading the volume from cover to cover. It contains a significant amount of new material, and the previously published work is suitably modified such that the volume gives a comprehensive and systematic framework for understanding ethics. Swanton’s target-centered virtue ethics shares many of the attractive features of Aristotelian virtue ethics, but it is much more refined and sophisticated and thereby (arguably) avoids many of the weaknesses of Aristotelianism.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW PHILOSOPHY-
CiteScore
7.40
自引率
0.00%
发文量
17
期刊介绍: In continuous publication since 1892, the Philosophical Review has a long-standing reputation for excellence and has published many papers now considered classics in the field, such as W. V. O. Quine"s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” Thomas Nagel"s “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” and the early work of John Rawls. The journal aims to publish original scholarly work in all areas of analytic philosophy, with an emphasis on material of general interest to academic philosophers, and is one of the few journals in the discipline to publish book reviews.
期刊最新文献
Reasons First Dark Matters: Pessimism and the Problem of Suffering Democratic Law Sustaining Democracy: What We Owe to the Other Side Mind and World in Aristotle’s De Anima
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1