阿威罗伊论智力:从亚里士多德的起源到阿奎那的批判

IF 2.8 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI:10.1215/00318108-10294448
Peter Adamson
{"title":"阿威罗伊论智力:从亚里士多德的起源到阿奎那的批判","authors":"Peter Adamson","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10294448","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"There have been philosophers who sought to preserve and ratify the dictates’ common sense, and there have been philosophers who were willing to overturn and correct those dictates. And then there was Averroes. His most notorious doctrine is not just counterintuitive. It commits him to something that seems self-evidently false, namely that there is only a single mind to which all human thought is related. As his most famous critic, Thomas Aquinas, pointed out, it seems simply obvious that we each have a mind of our own, and that we can each think as individuals. Averroes—to use the Latinized version of his name, Ibn Rushd—seemed to deny this in his Long Commentary on Aristotle’s On the Soul, triggering a protracted debate in Latin medieval and Renaissance philosophy.1 Why spill so much ink over such an implausible theory? Part of the reason was surely Averroes’s stature as the most authoritative commentator on Aristotle. When Aquinas devoted a treatise specifically to the issue, he met Averroes on his own ground by disputing the unity theory as an interpretation of On the Soul. His concern was not mainly to refute a false philosophical view, but to rescue Aristotle from being associated with that view.And there was another reason the topic attracted so much attention: Averroes’s arguments for the unity of intellect were surprisingly powerful. Just how powerful is shown in a superb new book by Stephen Ogden. Applying the sort of sympathetic approach and analytic acuity now standardly brought to the works of Aristotle himself, Ogden explains that Averroes had strong philosophical and exegetical reasons for endorsing the unity of the intellect. With regular reference to Aquinas as a foil, Ogden makes a convincing case that Averroes’s apparently unbelievable view in fact made a great deal of sense within an Aristotelian framework. Indeed, within that framework it often seems to be at an advantage against the apparently far more plausible view of Aquinas, for whom intellect is immaterial but individual: one mind per human, not one mind for the whole human race.Averroes’ position was, as he noted himself, unique within the complex history of interpretations of Aristotle’s On the Soul chapters 3.4–5, the chapters that deal most centrally with intellect. Ogden indeed says that the Averroist view “boasts novelty galore” (92). But it was actually not new to posit a single mind standing over all human individuals. The Aristotelian God was such a mind, as was the nous postulated by Plotinus. Closer to Averroes in time, culture, and intention was Avicenna (again, this name is a Latinization, in this case of Ibn Sīnā). He held that the so called “active intellect” (AI) described by Aristotle in the brief and inscrutable chapter 3.5 of On the Soul is a single transcendent principle that somehow allows individual humans to think. (Exactly how it does so is a matter of extensive dispute among Avicenna scholars.) By contrast, the potential or material intellect (MPI), which is responsible for receiving intelligibles, is for Avicenna unique to each human intellect.Averroes and Aquinas, as Ogden nicely observes, are in agreement that this mismatch between the AI and the MPI is unsustainable. Either both should be individual, or both should be one. Aquinas of course adopted the former view, Averroes the latter. Why? Before reading Ogden’s book, I thought that a chief reason for Averroes’s stance was that matter is the principle of individuation. For instance, two sunflowers share in the species of sunflower, but their forms are individuated by being received in two parcels of spatiotemporally distinct matter. But Aristotle argued explicitly that intellect is an immaterial power. So there is nothing that could distinguish many individual intellects. Ogden, though, makes a convincing case that this is not the argument underlying the Averroist theory (98–100). After all, the intellects associated with the celestial spheres are likewise immaterial, yet they manage to be distinct from one another. Possibly they differ in some way that would be impossible for individual human intellects, but that would need further argument. Thus, when Averroes argues that the MPI is a determinate, immaterial substance, this in itself leaves open whether there is one such intellect or many (105–8). Indeed, Avicenna used an argument much like Averroes’s to prove the immateriality of the MPI, while holding that each individual human has an MPI of their own.2So, while he allows that concerns about individuation may help to suggest a unity theory and would certainly pose problems for a view like Aquinas’s (see 220), Ogden thinks the Averroist theory is best proven in a different way. This is by means of what he calls the “Unity Argument,” which states that “the best way to explain how we can all think the same thing is that there is only one and the same thing that is thought—in one intellect” (109). As Ogden allows, it looks as if the arch-Aristotelian Averroes is here indulging a Platonist intuition (113). When you and I both understand the form of sunflower, we should both be grasping one and the same object of thought. But Averroes assumes that an intelligible object must always reside in a mind, not subsist independently like a Platonic form. It follows that the intelligibles are all received in a single mind. The only alternative would be to say that you are getting one idea of sunflower, while I am getting another. But then we would not in fact be thinking about the same thing or, as we might put it, “having the same thought.”This leaves Averroes with the problem of how to explain why it seems that we are thinking as individuals. Actually, that is not the only problem. Ogden makes another nice point here, namely that the difficulty is not only phenomenological, but also ontological (166). The individual human should be the agent of thinking, and the fact that we feel as though this is the case is simply evidence for that ontological claim. When Aquinas pressed this objection in his treatise against Averroes on the unity of the intellect, repeatedly challenging the Averroist to explain the fact that “this human thinks (hic homo intelligit)” (McInerny 1993), the objection functions at both levels. Modern-day interpreters have sought to answer on Averroes’s behalf. Typically, they want to show that each human is in some sense a subject of intellective thought for Averroes, for example, through some sort unification with the single intellect, or because our lower cognitive activity is supplying the necessary basis for that intellect. Thus when my remembered images of sunflowers are used by the single intellect to think about the intelligible form of sunflower, it will seem to me that I am the one engaging in intellection. Ogden allows that this might explain the phenomenological appearance that I am the one thinking. But when it comes to the ontological version of the objection, he thinks that Averroes would just bite the bullet. He would admit that strictly speaking, no human individual is the one understanding or thinking the universal intelligible object. Only the single intellect is doing that. The intellect lies outside individual human cognition, which is why it can only be called “soul” in an equivocal way (51–2, 184).Thus Ogden ascribes to Averroes an “error theory” (174), according to which we mistakenly take ourselves to be engaging in true intellection when in fact we are not. The most that embodied humans can do is operate with abstract or “vague” individual images that approximate universal intelligibility without quite achieving it (199). So it turns out that you and I really do have our own ideas of sunflower, gleaned from our different experiences of particular sunflowers. There is a single thought of sunflower only at the level of the single intellect. Ogden courteously but firmly critiques other scholars’ attempts to escape this conclusion, for instance by saying that there is some sort of formal unity between the intellect and the individual human (the single intellect would, as Richard C. Taylor 2013 has stressed, be “form for us”). Ogden argues that this is true in the sense that there is an operative unity between intellect and individual (205). But the fact that the intellect is using the memories and imagined images in my brain obviously does not mean that I am the intellect, any more than an online server would be identical with my laptop because it uses data uploaded from my laptop’s hard drive (my analogy, not Ogden’s, though he uses similar ones). The intellect would be identical with the human individual if it were that human’s substantial form (174), which is clearly not the case, given that it could not be both my substantial form and yours.While I’m guessing that some modern-day Averroes specialists may balk at this reading, Ogden is able to point to medieval and Renaissance thinkers who had the same no-holds-barred understanding of Averroes. He at the very least puts the onus on interpreters to explain how we humans are, in our multiplicity, somehow the same as one single intellect. Ogden’s reading has a consequence that Averroes seems to admit (see esp. 223), namely that humans have no prospect of an individual afterlife. The human species is everlasting and so is the intellect “fed” by our bodily cognitive processes, but you and I are going to stop existing when we die. More generally, Ogden’s version of Averroes accepts a philosophical anthropology according to which we are fully embodied beings, “like other animals” as Ogden says more than once, with substantial forms that require a material receiver to ensure continued persistence (217). In this respect, Ogden’s Averroes, despite the startling conclusions to which he was led in his protracted attempts to interpret Aristotle aright, had an understanding of the human being that is not so unfamiliar to the modern-day philosopher.","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"41 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":2.8000,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"<i>Averroes on Intellect: from Aristotelian Origins to Aquinas’s Critique</i>\",\"authors\":\"Peter Adamson\",\"doi\":\"10.1215/00318108-10294448\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"There have been philosophers who sought to preserve and ratify the dictates’ common sense, and there have been philosophers who were willing to overturn and correct those dictates. And then there was Averroes. His most notorious doctrine is not just counterintuitive. It commits him to something that seems self-evidently false, namely that there is only a single mind to which all human thought is related. As his most famous critic, Thomas Aquinas, pointed out, it seems simply obvious that we each have a mind of our own, and that we can each think as individuals. Averroes—to use the Latinized version of his name, Ibn Rushd—seemed to deny this in his Long Commentary on Aristotle’s On the Soul, triggering a protracted debate in Latin medieval and Renaissance philosophy.1 Why spill so much ink over such an implausible theory? Part of the reason was surely Averroes’s stature as the most authoritative commentator on Aristotle. When Aquinas devoted a treatise specifically to the issue, he met Averroes on his own ground by disputing the unity theory as an interpretation of On the Soul. His concern was not mainly to refute a false philosophical view, but to rescue Aristotle from being associated with that view.And there was another reason the topic attracted so much attention: Averroes’s arguments for the unity of intellect were surprisingly powerful. Just how powerful is shown in a superb new book by Stephen Ogden. Applying the sort of sympathetic approach and analytic acuity now standardly brought to the works of Aristotle himself, Ogden explains that Averroes had strong philosophical and exegetical reasons for endorsing the unity of the intellect. With regular reference to Aquinas as a foil, Ogden makes a convincing case that Averroes’s apparently unbelievable view in fact made a great deal of sense within an Aristotelian framework. Indeed, within that framework it often seems to be at an advantage against the apparently far more plausible view of Aquinas, for whom intellect is immaterial but individual: one mind per human, not one mind for the whole human race.Averroes’ position was, as he noted himself, unique within the complex history of interpretations of Aristotle’s On the Soul chapters 3.4–5, the chapters that deal most centrally with intellect. Ogden indeed says that the Averroist view “boasts novelty galore” (92). But it was actually not new to posit a single mind standing over all human individuals. The Aristotelian God was such a mind, as was the nous postulated by Plotinus. Closer to Averroes in time, culture, and intention was Avicenna (again, this name is a Latinization, in this case of Ibn Sīnā). He held that the so called “active intellect” (AI) described by Aristotle in the brief and inscrutable chapter 3.5 of On the Soul is a single transcendent principle that somehow allows individual humans to think. (Exactly how it does so is a matter of extensive dispute among Avicenna scholars.) By contrast, the potential or material intellect (MPI), which is responsible for receiving intelligibles, is for Avicenna unique to each human intellect.Averroes and Aquinas, as Ogden nicely observes, are in agreement that this mismatch between the AI and the MPI is unsustainable. Either both should be individual, or both should be one. Aquinas of course adopted the former view, Averroes the latter. Why? Before reading Ogden’s book, I thought that a chief reason for Averroes’s stance was that matter is the principle of individuation. For instance, two sunflowers share in the species of sunflower, but their forms are individuated by being received in two parcels of spatiotemporally distinct matter. But Aristotle argued explicitly that intellect is an immaterial power. So there is nothing that could distinguish many individual intellects. Ogden, though, makes a convincing case that this is not the argument underlying the Averroist theory (98–100). After all, the intellects associated with the celestial spheres are likewise immaterial, yet they manage to be distinct from one another. Possibly they differ in some way that would be impossible for individual human intellects, but that would need further argument. Thus, when Averroes argues that the MPI is a determinate, immaterial substance, this in itself leaves open whether there is one such intellect or many (105–8). Indeed, Avicenna used an argument much like Averroes’s to prove the immateriality of the MPI, while holding that each individual human has an MPI of their own.2So, while he allows that concerns about individuation may help to suggest a unity theory and would certainly pose problems for a view like Aquinas’s (see 220), Ogden thinks the Averroist theory is best proven in a different way. This is by means of what he calls the “Unity Argument,” which states that “the best way to explain how we can all think the same thing is that there is only one and the same thing that is thought—in one intellect” (109). As Ogden allows, it looks as if the arch-Aristotelian Averroes is here indulging a Platonist intuition (113). When you and I both understand the form of sunflower, we should both be grasping one and the same object of thought. But Averroes assumes that an intelligible object must always reside in a mind, not subsist independently like a Platonic form. It follows that the intelligibles are all received in a single mind. The only alternative would be to say that you are getting one idea of sunflower, while I am getting another. But then we would not in fact be thinking about the same thing or, as we might put it, “having the same thought.”This leaves Averroes with the problem of how to explain why it seems that we are thinking as individuals. Actually, that is not the only problem. Ogden makes another nice point here, namely that the difficulty is not only phenomenological, but also ontological (166). The individual human should be the agent of thinking, and the fact that we feel as though this is the case is simply evidence for that ontological claim. When Aquinas pressed this objection in his treatise against Averroes on the unity of the intellect, repeatedly challenging the Averroist to explain the fact that “this human thinks (hic homo intelligit)” (McInerny 1993), the objection functions at both levels. Modern-day interpreters have sought to answer on Averroes’s behalf. Typically, they want to show that each human is in some sense a subject of intellective thought for Averroes, for example, through some sort unification with the single intellect, or because our lower cognitive activity is supplying the necessary basis for that intellect. Thus when my remembered images of sunflowers are used by the single intellect to think about the intelligible form of sunflower, it will seem to me that I am the one engaging in intellection. Ogden allows that this might explain the phenomenological appearance that I am the one thinking. But when it comes to the ontological version of the objection, he thinks that Averroes would just bite the bullet. He would admit that strictly speaking, no human individual is the one understanding or thinking the universal intelligible object. Only the single intellect is doing that. The intellect lies outside individual human cognition, which is why it can only be called “soul” in an equivocal way (51–2, 184).Thus Ogden ascribes to Averroes an “error theory” (174), according to which we mistakenly take ourselves to be engaging in true intellection when in fact we are not. The most that embodied humans can do is operate with abstract or “vague” individual images that approximate universal intelligibility without quite achieving it (199). So it turns out that you and I really do have our own ideas of sunflower, gleaned from our different experiences of particular sunflowers. There is a single thought of sunflower only at the level of the single intellect. Ogden courteously but firmly critiques other scholars’ attempts to escape this conclusion, for instance by saying that there is some sort of formal unity between the intellect and the individual human (the single intellect would, as Richard C. Taylor 2013 has stressed, be “form for us”). Ogden argues that this is true in the sense that there is an operative unity between intellect and individual (205). But the fact that the intellect is using the memories and imagined images in my brain obviously does not mean that I am the intellect, any more than an online server would be identical with my laptop because it uses data uploaded from my laptop’s hard drive (my analogy, not Ogden’s, though he uses similar ones). The intellect would be identical with the human individual if it were that human’s substantial form (174), which is clearly not the case, given that it could not be both my substantial form and yours.While I’m guessing that some modern-day Averroes specialists may balk at this reading, Ogden is able to point to medieval and Renaissance thinkers who had the same no-holds-barred understanding of Averroes. He at the very least puts the onus on interpreters to explain how we humans are, in our multiplicity, somehow the same as one single intellect. Ogden’s reading has a consequence that Averroes seems to admit (see esp. 223), namely that humans have no prospect of an individual afterlife. The human species is everlasting and so is the intellect “fed” by our bodily cognitive processes, but you and I are going to stop existing when we die. More generally, Ogden’s version of Averroes accepts a philosophical anthropology according to which we are fully embodied beings, “like other animals” as Ogden says more than once, with substantial forms that require a material receiver to ensure continued persistence (217). In this respect, Ogden’s Averroes, despite the startling conclusions to which he was led in his protracted attempts to interpret Aristotle aright, had an understanding of the human being that is not so unfamiliar to the modern-day philosopher.\",\"PeriodicalId\":48129,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW\",\"volume\":\"41 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":2.8000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-04-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10294448\",\"RegionNum\":1,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"0\",\"JCRName\":\"PHILOSOPHY\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10294448","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

有哲学家试图保留和认可命令的常识,也有哲学家愿意推翻和纠正这些命令。然后是阿威罗伊斯。他最臭名昭著的学说不仅仅是违反直觉。它使他陷入一种似乎不证自明的错误,即只有一个心灵与人类的一切思想有关。正如他最著名的批评家托马斯·阿奎那(Thomas Aquinas)所指出的那样,似乎很明显,我们每个人都有自己的思想,我们每个人都可以独立思考。阿威罗伊——用他名字的拉丁化版本,伊本·拉什——似乎在他对亚里士多德的《论灵魂》的长篇评论中否认了这一点,引发了拉丁中世纪和文艺复兴时期哲学史上一场旷日持久的辩论为什么要在这样一个不可信的理论上花那么多笔墨呢?部分原因肯定是阿威罗伊作为最权威的亚里士多德评论家的地位。当阿奎那专门为这个问题写了一篇论文时,他在自己的立场上遇到了阿威罗伊,他争论统一理论作为《论灵魂》的解释。他关心的主要不是驳斥一个错误的哲学观点,而是拯救亚里士多德,使其不与那个观点联系在一起。这个话题吸引如此多关注还有另一个原因:阿威罗伊关于智力统一性的论证令人惊讶地有力。史蒂芬·奥格登(Stephen Ogden)的一本出色的新书展示了这种力量有多强大。奥格登运用了亚里士多德自己的作品中通常采用的那种同情的方法和敏锐的分析能力,他解释说,阿威罗伊有强大的哲学和训诂上的理由来支持智力的统一性。奥格登经常引用阿奎那作为衬托,提出了一个令人信服的例子,即阿威罗伊表面上令人难以置信的观点,实际上在亚里士多德的框架内是有很大意义的。事实上,在这个框架内,它似乎经常比阿奎那的观点更有优势,阿奎那认为智力是非物质的,而是个体的:每个人都有一个头脑,而不是整个人类的一个头脑。阿威罗伊的立场,正如他自己所说,在亚里士多德《论灵魂》第3.4-5章的复杂历史解释中是独一无二的,这几章主要是关于智力的。奥格登确实说过,阿威罗伊主义的观点“拥有丰富的新颖性”(92)。但事实上,假设一个单一的思想凌驾于所有人类个体之上并不是什么新鲜事。亚里士多德的上帝就是这样一种精神,就像普罗提诺所假定的诺斯一样。在时间、文化和意图上更接近阿威罗伊的是阿维森纳(同样,这个名字是拉丁化的,在伊本·s·纳伊的例子中)。他认为,亚里士多德在《论灵魂》简短而晦涩的第3.5章中所描述的所谓“主动智能”(AI)是一种单一的超越原则,它以某种方式允许个体人类思考。(它究竟是如何做到这一点的,在阿维森纳的学者之间存在广泛争议。)相比之下,负责接收可理解信息的潜在智力或物质智力(MPI)对阿维森纳来说是每个人类智力所独有的。正如奥格登所言,阿威罗伊和阿奎那一致认为,人工智能和MPI之间的这种不匹配是不可持续的。要么两者都是独立的,要么两者都是一体的。阿奎那当然采纳了前者的观点,而阿威罗伊则反对后者。为什么?在阅读奥格登的书之前,我认为阿威罗伊的立场的一个主要原因是物质是个性化的原则。例如,两朵向日葵属于向日葵的种类,但它们的形式是个性化的,因为它们被接收在两个时空不同的物质中。但亚里士多德明确指出,智力是一种非物质的力量。因此,没有什么可以区分不同的个体智力。然而,奥格登提出了一个令人信服的案例,证明这不是阿威罗伊主义理论背后的论点(98-100)。毕竟,与天界有关的智慧同样是非物质的,然而它们设法彼此区别开来。它们可能在某种程度上有所不同,这对于个体的人类智力来说是不可能的,但这需要进一步的论证。因此,当阿威罗伊认为MPI是一种确定的、非物质的实体时,这本身就留下了一个问题,即是否存在一个这样的智力或多个这样的智力(105-8)。事实上,阿维森纳用了一个很像阿威罗伊的论点来证明MPI的非物质性,同时认为每个人都有自己的MPI。因此,虽然奥格登承认,对个性化的关注可能有助于提出一个统一理论,而且肯定会给阿奎那的观点(见220页)带来问题,但他认为,阿威罗伊主义理论最好以另一种方式得到证明。这是通过他所谓的“统一论证”来实现的,该论证指出,“解释我们如何都能思考同一件事的最好方法是,在一个智力中,只有一件事是被思考的”(109)。 正如奥格登所言,似乎亚里士多德学派的阿威罗伊在这里沉迷于柏拉图主义的直觉(113)。当你我都理解了向日葵的形态,我们就应该抓住同一个思想对象。但阿威罗伊认为,一个可理解的对象必须始终存在于心灵中,而不是像柏拉图式的形式那样独立存在。由此可见,所有可理解的东西都是在一个人的头脑中接受的。唯一的选择是说你对向日葵有一种理解,而我对向日葵有另一种理解。但这样一来,我们实际上就不会在思考同一件事,或者,我们可以说,"有同样的想法"这就给阿威罗伊留下了一个问题:如何解释为什么我们似乎在以个体的方式思考。事实上,这并不是唯一的问题。奥格登在这里提出了另一个很好的观点,即困难不仅是现象学的,而且是本体论的(166)。人类个体应该是思考的主体,我们认为这是事实,这就是本体论主张的证据。当阿奎那在他反对阿威罗伊关于智力统一性的论文中提出这一反对意见时,他反复挑战阿威罗伊主义者解释“这个人思考(hic homo intelligit)”(McInerny 1993)这一事实时,这一反对意见在两个层面上都起作用。现代的诠释者试图代表阿威罗伊回答这个问题。一般来说,他们想要表明,在某种意义上,每个人都是阿威罗伊的智力思维的主体,例如,通过某种单一智力的统一,或者因为我们较低的认知活动为这种智力提供了必要的基础。因此,当我记忆中的向日葵形象被单一的智力用来思考向日葵的可理解形式时,在我看来,我似乎是一个从事思考的人。奥格登认为这也许可以解释现象学上的表象,即我在思考。但当涉及到反对的本体论版本时,他认为阿威罗伊会咬紧牙关。他会承认,严格地说,没有人能够理解或思考普遍可理解的对象。只有一个聪明的人才会这么做。智力存在于个体人类认知之外,这就是为什么它只能以一种模棱两可的方式被称为“灵魂”(51 - 2,184)。因此,奥格登把“错误理论”归于阿威罗伊(174),根据这一理论,我们错误地认为自己在从事真正的思考,而实际上我们并没有。具身人类所能做的最多的是处理抽象或“模糊”的个人形象,这些形象近似于普遍的可理解性,而不是完全实现它(199)。所以事实证明,你和我确实对向日葵有自己的看法,这些看法来自于我们对特定向日葵的不同体验。向日葵只有在单一的智力水平上才有单一的思想。奥格登礼貌而坚定地批评了其他学者试图逃避这一结论的尝试,例如,他说,在智力和个体人类之间存在某种形式的统一(正如理查德·c·泰勒(Richard C. Taylor) 2013年所强调的那样,单一的智力将是“我们的形式”)。奥格登认为,这是正确的,因为在智力和个人之间存在一种有效的统一(205)。但是,智能使用我大脑中的记忆和想象图像这一事实显然并不意味着我就是智能,就像一台在线服务器与我的笔记本电脑并不相同,因为它使用的是从我的笔记本电脑硬盘上上传的数据(我的类比,不是奥格登的,尽管他使用了类似的类比)。如果智力是人类的实体形式,那么它将与人类个体相同(174),但显然不是这样,因为它不可能同时是我的实体形式和你的实体形式。虽然我猜一些现代的阿威罗伊专家可能会对这种阅读犹豫不决,但奥格登能够指出中世纪和文艺复兴时期的思想家对阿威罗伊有着同样的无拘无束的理解。他至少把解释的责任放在了阐释者身上,来解释我们人类是如何,在我们的多样性中,在某种程度上与单一的智慧是一样的。奥格登的阅读有一个结果,阿威罗伊似乎承认(见尤223),即人类没有个人来世的前景。人类是永恒的,由我们身体认知过程“喂养”的智力也是永恒的,但你和我死后将不复存在。更一般地说,奥格登版本的阿威罗接受了一种哲学人类学,根据这种人类学,我们是完全具体化的存在,“就像其他动物一样”,奥格登不止一次说过,具有实体形式,需要一个物质接收器来确保持续存在(217)。 在这方面,奥格登笔下的阿威罗伊,尽管在长期试图正确解释亚里士多德的过程中,得出了令人吃惊的结论,但他对人类的理解,对现代哲学家来说并不陌生。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Averroes on Intellect: from Aristotelian Origins to Aquinas’s Critique
There have been philosophers who sought to preserve and ratify the dictates’ common sense, and there have been philosophers who were willing to overturn and correct those dictates. And then there was Averroes. His most notorious doctrine is not just counterintuitive. It commits him to something that seems self-evidently false, namely that there is only a single mind to which all human thought is related. As his most famous critic, Thomas Aquinas, pointed out, it seems simply obvious that we each have a mind of our own, and that we can each think as individuals. Averroes—to use the Latinized version of his name, Ibn Rushd—seemed to deny this in his Long Commentary on Aristotle’s On the Soul, triggering a protracted debate in Latin medieval and Renaissance philosophy.1 Why spill so much ink over such an implausible theory? Part of the reason was surely Averroes’s stature as the most authoritative commentator on Aristotle. When Aquinas devoted a treatise specifically to the issue, he met Averroes on his own ground by disputing the unity theory as an interpretation of On the Soul. His concern was not mainly to refute a false philosophical view, but to rescue Aristotle from being associated with that view.And there was another reason the topic attracted so much attention: Averroes’s arguments for the unity of intellect were surprisingly powerful. Just how powerful is shown in a superb new book by Stephen Ogden. Applying the sort of sympathetic approach and analytic acuity now standardly brought to the works of Aristotle himself, Ogden explains that Averroes had strong philosophical and exegetical reasons for endorsing the unity of the intellect. With regular reference to Aquinas as a foil, Ogden makes a convincing case that Averroes’s apparently unbelievable view in fact made a great deal of sense within an Aristotelian framework. Indeed, within that framework it often seems to be at an advantage against the apparently far more plausible view of Aquinas, for whom intellect is immaterial but individual: one mind per human, not one mind for the whole human race.Averroes’ position was, as he noted himself, unique within the complex history of interpretations of Aristotle’s On the Soul chapters 3.4–5, the chapters that deal most centrally with intellect. Ogden indeed says that the Averroist view “boasts novelty galore” (92). But it was actually not new to posit a single mind standing over all human individuals. The Aristotelian God was such a mind, as was the nous postulated by Plotinus. Closer to Averroes in time, culture, and intention was Avicenna (again, this name is a Latinization, in this case of Ibn Sīnā). He held that the so called “active intellect” (AI) described by Aristotle in the brief and inscrutable chapter 3.5 of On the Soul is a single transcendent principle that somehow allows individual humans to think. (Exactly how it does so is a matter of extensive dispute among Avicenna scholars.) By contrast, the potential or material intellect (MPI), which is responsible for receiving intelligibles, is for Avicenna unique to each human intellect.Averroes and Aquinas, as Ogden nicely observes, are in agreement that this mismatch between the AI and the MPI is unsustainable. Either both should be individual, or both should be one. Aquinas of course adopted the former view, Averroes the latter. Why? Before reading Ogden’s book, I thought that a chief reason for Averroes’s stance was that matter is the principle of individuation. For instance, two sunflowers share in the species of sunflower, but their forms are individuated by being received in two parcels of spatiotemporally distinct matter. But Aristotle argued explicitly that intellect is an immaterial power. So there is nothing that could distinguish many individual intellects. Ogden, though, makes a convincing case that this is not the argument underlying the Averroist theory (98–100). After all, the intellects associated with the celestial spheres are likewise immaterial, yet they manage to be distinct from one another. Possibly they differ in some way that would be impossible for individual human intellects, but that would need further argument. Thus, when Averroes argues that the MPI is a determinate, immaterial substance, this in itself leaves open whether there is one such intellect or many (105–8). Indeed, Avicenna used an argument much like Averroes’s to prove the immateriality of the MPI, while holding that each individual human has an MPI of their own.2So, while he allows that concerns about individuation may help to suggest a unity theory and would certainly pose problems for a view like Aquinas’s (see 220), Ogden thinks the Averroist theory is best proven in a different way. This is by means of what he calls the “Unity Argument,” which states that “the best way to explain how we can all think the same thing is that there is only one and the same thing that is thought—in one intellect” (109). As Ogden allows, it looks as if the arch-Aristotelian Averroes is here indulging a Platonist intuition (113). When you and I both understand the form of sunflower, we should both be grasping one and the same object of thought. But Averroes assumes that an intelligible object must always reside in a mind, not subsist independently like a Platonic form. It follows that the intelligibles are all received in a single mind. The only alternative would be to say that you are getting one idea of sunflower, while I am getting another. But then we would not in fact be thinking about the same thing or, as we might put it, “having the same thought.”This leaves Averroes with the problem of how to explain why it seems that we are thinking as individuals. Actually, that is not the only problem. Ogden makes another nice point here, namely that the difficulty is not only phenomenological, but also ontological (166). The individual human should be the agent of thinking, and the fact that we feel as though this is the case is simply evidence for that ontological claim. When Aquinas pressed this objection in his treatise against Averroes on the unity of the intellect, repeatedly challenging the Averroist to explain the fact that “this human thinks (hic homo intelligit)” (McInerny 1993), the objection functions at both levels. Modern-day interpreters have sought to answer on Averroes’s behalf. Typically, they want to show that each human is in some sense a subject of intellective thought for Averroes, for example, through some sort unification with the single intellect, or because our lower cognitive activity is supplying the necessary basis for that intellect. Thus when my remembered images of sunflowers are used by the single intellect to think about the intelligible form of sunflower, it will seem to me that I am the one engaging in intellection. Ogden allows that this might explain the phenomenological appearance that I am the one thinking. But when it comes to the ontological version of the objection, he thinks that Averroes would just bite the bullet. He would admit that strictly speaking, no human individual is the one understanding or thinking the universal intelligible object. Only the single intellect is doing that. The intellect lies outside individual human cognition, which is why it can only be called “soul” in an equivocal way (51–2, 184).Thus Ogden ascribes to Averroes an “error theory” (174), according to which we mistakenly take ourselves to be engaging in true intellection when in fact we are not. The most that embodied humans can do is operate with abstract or “vague” individual images that approximate universal intelligibility without quite achieving it (199). So it turns out that you and I really do have our own ideas of sunflower, gleaned from our different experiences of particular sunflowers. There is a single thought of sunflower only at the level of the single intellect. Ogden courteously but firmly critiques other scholars’ attempts to escape this conclusion, for instance by saying that there is some sort of formal unity between the intellect and the individual human (the single intellect would, as Richard C. Taylor 2013 has stressed, be “form for us”). Ogden argues that this is true in the sense that there is an operative unity between intellect and individual (205). But the fact that the intellect is using the memories and imagined images in my brain obviously does not mean that I am the intellect, any more than an online server would be identical with my laptop because it uses data uploaded from my laptop’s hard drive (my analogy, not Ogden’s, though he uses similar ones). The intellect would be identical with the human individual if it were that human’s substantial form (174), which is clearly not the case, given that it could not be both my substantial form and yours.While I’m guessing that some modern-day Averroes specialists may balk at this reading, Ogden is able to point to medieval and Renaissance thinkers who had the same no-holds-barred understanding of Averroes. He at the very least puts the onus on interpreters to explain how we humans are, in our multiplicity, somehow the same as one single intellect. Ogden’s reading has a consequence that Averroes seems to admit (see esp. 223), namely that humans have no prospect of an individual afterlife. The human species is everlasting and so is the intellect “fed” by our bodily cognitive processes, but you and I are going to stop existing when we die. More generally, Ogden’s version of Averroes accepts a philosophical anthropology according to which we are fully embodied beings, “like other animals” as Ogden says more than once, with substantial forms that require a material receiver to ensure continued persistence (217). In this respect, Ogden’s Averroes, despite the startling conclusions to which he was led in his protracted attempts to interpret Aristotle aright, had an understanding of the human being that is not so unfamiliar to the modern-day philosopher.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW PHILOSOPHY-
CiteScore
7.40
自引率
0.00%
发文量
17
期刊介绍: In continuous publication since 1892, the Philosophical Review has a long-standing reputation for excellence and has published many papers now considered classics in the field, such as W. V. O. Quine"s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” Thomas Nagel"s “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” and the early work of John Rawls. The journal aims to publish original scholarly work in all areas of analytic philosophy, with an emphasis on material of general interest to academic philosophers, and is one of the few journals in the discipline to publish book reviews.
期刊最新文献
Reasons First Dark Matters: Pessimism and the Problem of Suffering Democratic Law Sustaining Democracy: What We Owe to the Other Side Mind and World in Aristotle’s De Anima
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1