莱布尼茨论时间、空间和相对论

IF 2.8 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW Pub Date : 2023-07-01 DOI:10.1215/00318108-10469538
Jeffrey K. McDonough
{"title":"莱布尼茨论时间、空间和相对论","authors":"Jeffrey K. McDonough","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10469538","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"In his impressive Leibniz on Time, Space, and Relativity, Ric Arthur manages to juggle a daunting array of tasks: tracking the chronological development of Leibniz’s views over more than half a century; explicating Leibniz’s groundbreaking mathematics; assembling texts—primary and secondary—in at least five languages; and, as if in passing, offering original translations and assessments of countless source materials. All this erudition is put to the service of offering detailed interpretations of Leibniz’s challenging theories of time, space, and motion. Arthur’s performance is a lifetime in the making, and his Leibniz on Time, Space, and Relativity is certain to be essential reading for those interested in the topics it covers for many years to come.Leibniz’s subtle theory of time defies easy summary. According to Arthur, Leibniz’s theory of time is ultimately grounded in relations among states of substances. States of substances are representations of a world from a perspective. States that do not contradict one another occur at the same time. States that do contradict one another are successive. Among successive states, some provide reasons for others. A state that provides a reason for another state is temporally prior to that state. One thing exists before, after, or at the same time as another thing not because of the way both things are related to some special, independent third thing—namely, time—but rather because of the relations they bear to one another (and other similar things). A occurs before, after, or at the same time as B because of the relations between A and B. For Arthur’s Leibniz, time itself is an abstract ordering relation that structures not only all actual temporal relations but also all possible temporal relations. It guarantees not only that my fifth birthday must precede my fiftieth but also that my fiftieth must precede my merely possible five hundredth.Is Leibniz eliminating time? Many commentators have thought so. Leibniz was a nominalist, and nominalists typically deny that abstract objects exist. In holding that time is abstract, mustn’t Leibniz also hold that time doesn’t really exist? “No,” says Arthur. Abstract objects, for Leibniz, have a home in the “divine mind” (61). Thus, while the abstract structure that orders all possible existing things can’t itself exist in the concrete world, that doesn’t mean that it doesn’t exist at all. Furthermore, and perhaps even more importantly, the temporal relations holding between things in the world are not abstract. Even if time itself were not real, Arthur’s Leibniz would still insist that my fifth birthday occurred before my fiftieth birthday and at roughly the same time as my older brother’s seventh birthday. Even if time is abstract, temporal relations are not.But wait, doesn’t Leibniz also hold that relations are ideal? And in holding that temporal relations are ideal, isn’t Leibniz suggesting that temporal relations themselves are not real? Again, Arthur thinks not. He argues that while “Leibniz denies reality to relations as entities in themselves, he does not thereby deny the reality of relational facts, such as the fact of two states of a substance occurring one after the other” (61). Suppose that Plato is older than Aristotle. For various reasons, Leibniz thinks that any relation between Plato and Aristotle can exist neither solely in Plato nor solely in Aristotle, nor in both of them jointly. Any relation between Plato and Aristotle must therefore be grounded at least partially in a mind that considers them both. Relations are, for Leibniz, ideal in precisely that sense. But “Plato is older than Aristotle” is still true even if no one considers Plato and Aristotle. That Plato is older than Aristotle is grounded in Plato’s intrinsic nature and Aristotle’s intrinsic nature. The older-than relation is metaphysically ideal, but relational “facts” are not. Arthur’s Leibniz has a somewhat complex view concerning the foundations of time, but it would be inaccurate, Arthur thinks—and I agree—to say that Leibniz means to eliminate time.Arthur attributes to Leibniz a similar view of space. In his famous exchange of letters with Samuel Clarke, Leibniz contrasts his mature view of space (and time) with Newton’s views. In broad strokes, Clarke and Newton think of space as an immobile, unchanging backdrop. Bodies are in space by being collocated with regions of space. Bodies move through space by collocating with different regions of space at different times. In opposition to this picture, and in keeping with his own understanding of time, Leibniz suggests that existing things stand directly in spatial relations to one another. As with time, one thing is cospatial with another thing not because of the way that both are related to some special, independent third thing—namely, space—but rather because of the relations they bear to one another (and other similar things). And, again, as with time, space itself is an abstract ordering relation that structures not only all actual spatial relations at a time but also all possible spatial relations at a time. It is, Leibniz tells us, the “order of coexistence,” and, like time, it is an abstract, ideal structure that resides in the divine intellect.Leibniz wrote his letters to Clarke in the final years of his life. (One imagines him dying with pen in hand, one more argument against his great adversary still in his inkwell.) Leibniz’s thinking about the nature of space, however, goes back to some of his very earliest writings. In those early writings, according to Arthur, Leibniz developed the idea that “the divine attribute of immensity is the basis of space” and that divine immensity is divided into a network of regions by the motions of bodies contained in it (123). On Arthur’s telling, Leibniz was then led by his study of Hobbes to develop a new mathematics of situation, Leibniz’s famed analysis situs. Leibniz’s analysis situs, in turn, provided him with formal tools for characterizing space both as a changing network of regions and as a system of relative positions. It became possible to understand space as an abstract system of possible positions structuring the spatial relations between existing things. On Arthur’s reading, there is thus a progressive, mostly continuous line of development in Leibniz’s thinking about the nature of space from the late 1670s until his death in 1716.Arthur’s progressive, mostly continuous reading of Leibniz’s views on space stands in provocative contrast to past and recent work by Vincenzo de Risi. In forthcoming work, De Risi (forthcoming) argues that Leibniz’s views on space can be divided into three periods: an early substantivalist view, a middle Scholastic view rooted in the idea of imaginary space, and his famous late relational view. Most intriguingly, De Risi proposes that Leibniz’s relational view emerges for the first time only in the late 1680s and that it is prompted precisely by Leibniz’s clandestine reading of Newton’s Principia. On De Risi’s reading, Leibniz’s views on space are not an evolving refinement of a core theory but rather a series of essentially distinct theories. Leibniz’s relational theory is not the almost miraculously coincidental twin of Newton’s substantivalism, as it might appear to be from the Leibniz–Clark correspondence. Rather, it was crafted from the ground up by Leibniz as an alternative to the position of his great rival. Arthur and de Risi have opened up an exciting interpretative area of great consequence for early modern philosophy and science. Scholars looking for the next big thing in Leibniz studies may need to look no further.In taking up Leibniz’s views on motion, Arthur emphasizes a distinction Leibniz makes between motion conceived geometrically and motion with respect to cause. Motion conceived geometrically involves nothing more than a mere change of situation. Leibniz maintains that between any two bodies geometrical motion is relative and mutual. If our ships pass in the night, your ship moves relative to mine and mine moves relative to yours. There’s no saying—it doesn’t even make sense to ask—which is really moving. Motion with respect to cause “involves identifying the subject of motion by reference to the best explanation of the change” (321). Suppose there is a breeze and your sails are raised. The best explanation for our change of relative situation is that your boat is being driven by the wind while mine is resting in the water. In this case, the best hypothesis is that your boat is truly moving with respect to cause while mine is not. Motion with respect to cause is thus not—in contrast to geometrical motion—necessarily relative. In the case of motion with respect to cause, we can ask, and even hazard an educated guess, whether it is your boat or my boat that is really moving.Arthur shows how Leibniz’s distinction between geometrical and causal motion may be used to untangle some prima facie puzzles that have been raised for Leibniz’s theory of motion. Take, for example, the apparent tension between Leibniz’s commitment to the “equipollence of hypotheses” and his apparent endorsement of Copernicanism. In explicating the equipollence of hypotheses, Leibniz insists that “all hypotheses about the motions of any bodies whatsoever, however numerous, that are moved solely by corporeal impacts, it follows that not even an angel could discern, in mathematical rigor, which of the many bodies of this kind is at rest, and is the center of motion of the others” (248–49). Copernicanism, however, suggests that we—not to mention the angels—can say that the earth and planets move and that the sun is at rest. Faced with the obvious tension between these two commitments, it is tempting simply to favor one commitment at the expense of the other. It is tempting to suppose either that Leibniz’s equipollence of hypotheses is a disingenuous sop to the powers of Rome or that Leibniz’s commitment to Copernicanism is faint of heart—that Leibniz, for example, is only commending Copernicanism as merely one of many possible systems.On Arthur’s reading, Leibniz’s distinction between geometrical and causal motion suggests a more satisfying middle path. Leibniz does think that from a geometrical point of view, Copernicanism should be counted as merely one among many possible systems. And he really does believe that even an angel couldn’t say, from a geometrical point of view, whether the planets or the sun is in motion. From a geometrical point of view, such questions don’t even make sense. But they do make sense from a causal point of view, and from a causal point of view we can make better and worse hypotheses about which bodies are really moving. Leibniz can thus coherently insist that from a geometrical point of view Copernicanism is merely one among many possible systems, while still maintaining that from a causal point of view the Copernican system is our best hypothesis, that the planets really move, that the sun is really at rest. On Arthur’s reading, even if Leibniz’s language is conciliatory, there is nothing faint-hearted about his commitment to Copernicanism.Leibniz On Time, Space, and Relativity is a masterpiece of scholarship. It is historically, philosophically, and technically rich. (Did I mention that it includes a series of appendixes containing formal expositions, detailed explications of Arthur’s background views, and original translations? There is even a glossary of technical terms!) It is not, it should be conceded, an easy book. Although clearly written and organized, it is long and detailed. There is enough material between its covers for at least three important books, one on each of its principal subjects. Indeed, it is so chock-full of arguments, textual notes, and scholarly details that one might be tempted to suppose that it is dense in the mathematician’s sense, that between any two philosophical arguments, notes, or scholarly details, one will always be able to find another argument, note, or scholarly detail. For those with a taste for virtuosic scholarship and an interest in Leibniz, early modern philosophy, or the philosophy of space and time, Arthur’s masterpiece promises a dense but endless series of delights. Treat yourself.","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.8000,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"<i>Leibniz on Time, Space, and Relativity</i>\",\"authors\":\"Jeffrey K. McDonough\",\"doi\":\"10.1215/00318108-10469538\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"In his impressive Leibniz on Time, Space, and Relativity, Ric Arthur manages to juggle a daunting array of tasks: tracking the chronological development of Leibniz’s views over more than half a century; explicating Leibniz’s groundbreaking mathematics; assembling texts—primary and secondary—in at least five languages; and, as if in passing, offering original translations and assessments of countless source materials. All this erudition is put to the service of offering detailed interpretations of Leibniz’s challenging theories of time, space, and motion. Arthur’s performance is a lifetime in the making, and his Leibniz on Time, Space, and Relativity is certain to be essential reading for those interested in the topics it covers for many years to come.Leibniz’s subtle theory of time defies easy summary. According to Arthur, Leibniz’s theory of time is ultimately grounded in relations among states of substances. States of substances are representations of a world from a perspective. States that do not contradict one another occur at the same time. States that do contradict one another are successive. Among successive states, some provide reasons for others. A state that provides a reason for another state is temporally prior to that state. One thing exists before, after, or at the same time as another thing not because of the way both things are related to some special, independent third thing—namely, time—but rather because of the relations they bear to one another (and other similar things). A occurs before, after, or at the same time as B because of the relations between A and B. For Arthur’s Leibniz, time itself is an abstract ordering relation that structures not only all actual temporal relations but also all possible temporal relations. It guarantees not only that my fifth birthday must precede my fiftieth but also that my fiftieth must precede my merely possible five hundredth.Is Leibniz eliminating time? Many commentators have thought so. Leibniz was a nominalist, and nominalists typically deny that abstract objects exist. In holding that time is abstract, mustn’t Leibniz also hold that time doesn’t really exist? “No,” says Arthur. Abstract objects, for Leibniz, have a home in the “divine mind” (61). Thus, while the abstract structure that orders all possible existing things can’t itself exist in the concrete world, that doesn’t mean that it doesn’t exist at all. Furthermore, and perhaps even more importantly, the temporal relations holding between things in the world are not abstract. Even if time itself were not real, Arthur’s Leibniz would still insist that my fifth birthday occurred before my fiftieth birthday and at roughly the same time as my older brother’s seventh birthday. Even if time is abstract, temporal relations are not.But wait, doesn’t Leibniz also hold that relations are ideal? And in holding that temporal relations are ideal, isn’t Leibniz suggesting that temporal relations themselves are not real? Again, Arthur thinks not. He argues that while “Leibniz denies reality to relations as entities in themselves, he does not thereby deny the reality of relational facts, such as the fact of two states of a substance occurring one after the other” (61). Suppose that Plato is older than Aristotle. For various reasons, Leibniz thinks that any relation between Plato and Aristotle can exist neither solely in Plato nor solely in Aristotle, nor in both of them jointly. Any relation between Plato and Aristotle must therefore be grounded at least partially in a mind that considers them both. Relations are, for Leibniz, ideal in precisely that sense. But “Plato is older than Aristotle” is still true even if no one considers Plato and Aristotle. That Plato is older than Aristotle is grounded in Plato’s intrinsic nature and Aristotle’s intrinsic nature. The older-than relation is metaphysically ideal, but relational “facts” are not. Arthur’s Leibniz has a somewhat complex view concerning the foundations of time, but it would be inaccurate, Arthur thinks—and I agree—to say that Leibniz means to eliminate time.Arthur attributes to Leibniz a similar view of space. In his famous exchange of letters with Samuel Clarke, Leibniz contrasts his mature view of space (and time) with Newton’s views. In broad strokes, Clarke and Newton think of space as an immobile, unchanging backdrop. Bodies are in space by being collocated with regions of space. Bodies move through space by collocating with different regions of space at different times. In opposition to this picture, and in keeping with his own understanding of time, Leibniz suggests that existing things stand directly in spatial relations to one another. As with time, one thing is cospatial with another thing not because of the way that both are related to some special, independent third thing—namely, space—but rather because of the relations they bear to one another (and other similar things). And, again, as with time, space itself is an abstract ordering relation that structures not only all actual spatial relations at a time but also all possible spatial relations at a time. It is, Leibniz tells us, the “order of coexistence,” and, like time, it is an abstract, ideal structure that resides in the divine intellect.Leibniz wrote his letters to Clarke in the final years of his life. (One imagines him dying with pen in hand, one more argument against his great adversary still in his inkwell.) Leibniz’s thinking about the nature of space, however, goes back to some of his very earliest writings. In those early writings, according to Arthur, Leibniz developed the idea that “the divine attribute of immensity is the basis of space” and that divine immensity is divided into a network of regions by the motions of bodies contained in it (123). On Arthur’s telling, Leibniz was then led by his study of Hobbes to develop a new mathematics of situation, Leibniz’s famed analysis situs. Leibniz’s analysis situs, in turn, provided him with formal tools for characterizing space both as a changing network of regions and as a system of relative positions. It became possible to understand space as an abstract system of possible positions structuring the spatial relations between existing things. On Arthur’s reading, there is thus a progressive, mostly continuous line of development in Leibniz’s thinking about the nature of space from the late 1670s until his death in 1716.Arthur’s progressive, mostly continuous reading of Leibniz’s views on space stands in provocative contrast to past and recent work by Vincenzo de Risi. In forthcoming work, De Risi (forthcoming) argues that Leibniz’s views on space can be divided into three periods: an early substantivalist view, a middle Scholastic view rooted in the idea of imaginary space, and his famous late relational view. Most intriguingly, De Risi proposes that Leibniz’s relational view emerges for the first time only in the late 1680s and that it is prompted precisely by Leibniz’s clandestine reading of Newton’s Principia. On De Risi’s reading, Leibniz’s views on space are not an evolving refinement of a core theory but rather a series of essentially distinct theories. Leibniz’s relational theory is not the almost miraculously coincidental twin of Newton’s substantivalism, as it might appear to be from the Leibniz–Clark correspondence. Rather, it was crafted from the ground up by Leibniz as an alternative to the position of his great rival. Arthur and de Risi have opened up an exciting interpretative area of great consequence for early modern philosophy and science. Scholars looking for the next big thing in Leibniz studies may need to look no further.In taking up Leibniz’s views on motion, Arthur emphasizes a distinction Leibniz makes between motion conceived geometrically and motion with respect to cause. Motion conceived geometrically involves nothing more than a mere change of situation. Leibniz maintains that between any two bodies geometrical motion is relative and mutual. If our ships pass in the night, your ship moves relative to mine and mine moves relative to yours. There’s no saying—it doesn’t even make sense to ask—which is really moving. Motion with respect to cause “involves identifying the subject of motion by reference to the best explanation of the change” (321). Suppose there is a breeze and your sails are raised. The best explanation for our change of relative situation is that your boat is being driven by the wind while mine is resting in the water. In this case, the best hypothesis is that your boat is truly moving with respect to cause while mine is not. Motion with respect to cause is thus not—in contrast to geometrical motion—necessarily relative. In the case of motion with respect to cause, we can ask, and even hazard an educated guess, whether it is your boat or my boat that is really moving.Arthur shows how Leibniz’s distinction between geometrical and causal motion may be used to untangle some prima facie puzzles that have been raised for Leibniz’s theory of motion. Take, for example, the apparent tension between Leibniz’s commitment to the “equipollence of hypotheses” and his apparent endorsement of Copernicanism. In explicating the equipollence of hypotheses, Leibniz insists that “all hypotheses about the motions of any bodies whatsoever, however numerous, that are moved solely by corporeal impacts, it follows that not even an angel could discern, in mathematical rigor, which of the many bodies of this kind is at rest, and is the center of motion of the others” (248–49). Copernicanism, however, suggests that we—not to mention the angels—can say that the earth and planets move and that the sun is at rest. Faced with the obvious tension between these two commitments, it is tempting simply to favor one commitment at the expense of the other. It is tempting to suppose either that Leibniz’s equipollence of hypotheses is a disingenuous sop to the powers of Rome or that Leibniz’s commitment to Copernicanism is faint of heart—that Leibniz, for example, is only commending Copernicanism as merely one of many possible systems.On Arthur’s reading, Leibniz’s distinction between geometrical and causal motion suggests a more satisfying middle path. Leibniz does think that from a geometrical point of view, Copernicanism should be counted as merely one among many possible systems. And he really does believe that even an angel couldn’t say, from a geometrical point of view, whether the planets or the sun is in motion. From a geometrical point of view, such questions don’t even make sense. But they do make sense from a causal point of view, and from a causal point of view we can make better and worse hypotheses about which bodies are really moving. Leibniz can thus coherently insist that from a geometrical point of view Copernicanism is merely one among many possible systems, while still maintaining that from a causal point of view the Copernican system is our best hypothesis, that the planets really move, that the sun is really at rest. On Arthur’s reading, even if Leibniz’s language is conciliatory, there is nothing faint-hearted about his commitment to Copernicanism.Leibniz On Time, Space, and Relativity is a masterpiece of scholarship. It is historically, philosophically, and technically rich. (Did I mention that it includes a series of appendixes containing formal expositions, detailed explications of Arthur’s background views, and original translations? There is even a glossary of technical terms!) It is not, it should be conceded, an easy book. Although clearly written and organized, it is long and detailed. There is enough material between its covers for at least three important books, one on each of its principal subjects. Indeed, it is so chock-full of arguments, textual notes, and scholarly details that one might be tempted to suppose that it is dense in the mathematician’s sense, that between any two philosophical arguments, notes, or scholarly details, one will always be able to find another argument, note, or scholarly detail. For those with a taste for virtuosic scholarship and an interest in Leibniz, early modern philosophy, or the philosophy of space and time, Arthur’s masterpiece promises a dense but endless series of delights. Treat yourself.\",\"PeriodicalId\":48129,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":2.8000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-07-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10469538\",\"RegionNum\":1,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"0\",\"JCRName\":\"PHILOSOPHY\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10469538","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

在《莱布尼茨论时间、空间和相对论》这本令人印象深刻的书中,里克·阿瑟设法处理了一系列令人望而生畏的任务:追踪半个多世纪以来莱布尼茨观点的时间顺序发展;解释莱布尼茨开创性的数学;汇编至少五种语言的小学和中学文本;而且,似乎是顺带提供了对无数原始材料的原始翻译和评估。所有这些博学都是为了对莱布尼茨具有挑战性的时间、空间和运动理论提供详细的解释。亚瑟的表演是一生的成就,他的《莱布尼茨论时间、空间和相对论》肯定是那些对它所涵盖的主题感兴趣的人在未来许多年里必不可少的读物。莱布尼茨精妙的时间理论难以简单概括。根据亚瑟的说法,莱布尼茨的时间理论最终建立在物质状态之间的关系上。物质状态是从一个角度来表征一个世界。不相互矛盾的状态同时出现。相互矛盾的状态是连续的。在历届州中,有些州为其他州提供了理由。一种状态为另一种状态提供了理由,这种状态在时间上先于另一种状态。一个事物在另一个事物之前、之后或同时存在,不是因为这两个事物与某个特殊的、独立的第三个事物——即时间——的关系,而是因为它们彼此之间(以及其他类似事物)的关系。由于A和B之间的关系,A在B之前、之后或同时发生。对于阿瑟的莱布尼茨来说,时间本身是一种抽象的有序关系,它不仅构建了所有实际的时间关系,也构建了所有可能的时间关系。它不仅保证我的五岁生日必须在我五十岁之前,而且保证我的五十岁生日必须在我可能的五百岁之前。莱布尼茨消除了时间吗?许多评论人士都这么认为。莱布尼茨是一位唯名论者,而唯名论者通常否认抽象对象的存在。在认为时间是抽象的同时,莱布尼茨难道不能也认为时间是不存在的吗?“不,”阿瑟说。对莱布尼茨来说,抽象的物体在“神圣的心灵”中有一个家(61)。因此,虽然对所有可能存在的事物进行排序的抽象结构本身不能存在于具体世界中,但这并不意味着它根本不存在。此外,也许更重要的是,世界上事物之间的时间关系并不是抽象的。即使时间本身不是真实的,阿瑟的莱布尼茨仍然坚持认为,我的五岁生日发生在我五十岁生日之前,与我哥哥的七岁生日大致相同。即使时间是抽象的,时间关系也不是。等等,莱布尼茨不也认为关系是理想的吗?莱布尼茨认为时间关系是理想的,这不是在暗示时间关系本身不是真实的吗?阿瑟还是不这么认为。他认为,虽然“莱布尼茨否认关系作为自身实体的现实性,但他并没有因此否认关系事实的现实性,例如物质的两种状态一个接一个地发生的事实”(61)。假设柏拉图比亚里士多德更老。由于种种原因,莱布尼茨认为,柏拉图和亚里士多德之间的任何关系既不能单独存在于柏拉图身上,也不能单独存在于亚里士多德身上,也不能同时存在于两者身上。因此,柏拉图和亚里士多德之间的任何关系,都必须至少部分地建立在对他们两人都加以考虑的思想基础之上。在莱布尼茨看来,关系正是这种意义上的理想。但“柏拉图比亚里士多德老”仍然是正确的,即使没有人考虑柏拉图和亚里士多德。柏拉图比亚里士多德更老,这是基于柏拉图的内在本质和亚里士多德的内在本质。旧比关系在形而上学上是理想的,但关系的“事实”却不是。亚瑟的莱布尼茨对时间的基础有一种复杂的看法,但亚瑟认为——我同意——说莱布尼茨意味着消除时间是不准确的。亚瑟认为莱布尼茨也有类似的空间观。莱布尼茨在与塞缪尔·克拉克的著名书信往来中,将他成熟的空间(和时间)观与牛顿的观点进行了对比。笼统地说,克拉克和牛顿认为空间是一个固定不变的背景。物体通过与空间区域的搭配而存在于空间中。物体通过在不同时间与空间的不同区域搭配而在空间中移动。莱布尼茨与这种观点相反,并与他自己对时间的理解保持一致,他认为存在的事物彼此之间存在着直接的空间关系。与时间一样,一件事物与另一件事物具有空间性,不是因为两者都与某些特殊的、独立的第三件事物(即空间)相关,而是因为它们彼此之间(以及其他类似事物)的关系。 人们很容易认为,要么莱布尼茨的等量假设是对罗马权力的虚伪奉承,要么莱布尼茨对哥白尼主义的承诺是心虚的——例如,莱布尼茨只是将哥白尼主义视为众多可能体系中的一种。在亚瑟的阅读中,莱布尼茨对几何运动和因果运动的区分提出了一条更令人满意的中间道路。莱布尼茨确实认为,从几何学的观点来看,哥白尼学说应该仅仅是众多可能体系中的一种。他确实相信,从几何学的角度来看,即使是天使也不能说,行星或太阳是在运动的。从几何的角度来看,这样的问题根本没有意义。但从因果关系的角度来看,它们确实是有道理的,从因果关系的角度来看,我们可以对哪些物体真正在运动做出更好或更坏的假设。因此,莱布尼茨可以连贯地坚持,从几何的观点来看,哥白尼学说只是众多可能体系中的一种,而从因果的观点来看,哥白尼学说是我们最好的假设,行星确实在运动,太阳确实是静止的。在亚瑟的阅读中,即使莱布尼茨的语言是和解的,他对哥白尼主义的承诺也没有怯懦。莱布尼茨的《论时间、空间和相对论》是学术上的杰作。它在历史上、哲学上和技术上都很丰富。(我有没有提到,它包括一系列附录,其中包括正式的论述,亚瑟王背景观点的详细说明,以及原始翻译?甚至还有一个专业术语表!)应该承认,这不是一本轻松的书。虽然写得很清楚,组织也很好,但篇幅很长,内容很详细。它的封面之间有足够的材料至少三本重要的书,每个主要主题一本。的确,书中充满了论点、文本注释和学术细节,以至于人们可能会忍不住认为,在数学家的意义上,它是密集的,在任何两个哲学论点、笔记或学术细节之间,人们总能找到另一个论点、笔记或学术细节。对于那些对学术鉴赏家和对莱布尼茨、早期现代哲学或时空哲学感兴趣的人来说,亚瑟的杰作保证了一个密集但无穷无尽的乐趣系列。对待自己。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Leibniz on Time, Space, and Relativity
In his impressive Leibniz on Time, Space, and Relativity, Ric Arthur manages to juggle a daunting array of tasks: tracking the chronological development of Leibniz’s views over more than half a century; explicating Leibniz’s groundbreaking mathematics; assembling texts—primary and secondary—in at least five languages; and, as if in passing, offering original translations and assessments of countless source materials. All this erudition is put to the service of offering detailed interpretations of Leibniz’s challenging theories of time, space, and motion. Arthur’s performance is a lifetime in the making, and his Leibniz on Time, Space, and Relativity is certain to be essential reading for those interested in the topics it covers for many years to come.Leibniz’s subtle theory of time defies easy summary. According to Arthur, Leibniz’s theory of time is ultimately grounded in relations among states of substances. States of substances are representations of a world from a perspective. States that do not contradict one another occur at the same time. States that do contradict one another are successive. Among successive states, some provide reasons for others. A state that provides a reason for another state is temporally prior to that state. One thing exists before, after, or at the same time as another thing not because of the way both things are related to some special, independent third thing—namely, time—but rather because of the relations they bear to one another (and other similar things). A occurs before, after, or at the same time as B because of the relations between A and B. For Arthur’s Leibniz, time itself is an abstract ordering relation that structures not only all actual temporal relations but also all possible temporal relations. It guarantees not only that my fifth birthday must precede my fiftieth but also that my fiftieth must precede my merely possible five hundredth.Is Leibniz eliminating time? Many commentators have thought so. Leibniz was a nominalist, and nominalists typically deny that abstract objects exist. In holding that time is abstract, mustn’t Leibniz also hold that time doesn’t really exist? “No,” says Arthur. Abstract objects, for Leibniz, have a home in the “divine mind” (61). Thus, while the abstract structure that orders all possible existing things can’t itself exist in the concrete world, that doesn’t mean that it doesn’t exist at all. Furthermore, and perhaps even more importantly, the temporal relations holding between things in the world are not abstract. Even if time itself were not real, Arthur’s Leibniz would still insist that my fifth birthday occurred before my fiftieth birthday and at roughly the same time as my older brother’s seventh birthday. Even if time is abstract, temporal relations are not.But wait, doesn’t Leibniz also hold that relations are ideal? And in holding that temporal relations are ideal, isn’t Leibniz suggesting that temporal relations themselves are not real? Again, Arthur thinks not. He argues that while “Leibniz denies reality to relations as entities in themselves, he does not thereby deny the reality of relational facts, such as the fact of two states of a substance occurring one after the other” (61). Suppose that Plato is older than Aristotle. For various reasons, Leibniz thinks that any relation between Plato and Aristotle can exist neither solely in Plato nor solely in Aristotle, nor in both of them jointly. Any relation between Plato and Aristotle must therefore be grounded at least partially in a mind that considers them both. Relations are, for Leibniz, ideal in precisely that sense. But “Plato is older than Aristotle” is still true even if no one considers Plato and Aristotle. That Plato is older than Aristotle is grounded in Plato’s intrinsic nature and Aristotle’s intrinsic nature. The older-than relation is metaphysically ideal, but relational “facts” are not. Arthur’s Leibniz has a somewhat complex view concerning the foundations of time, but it would be inaccurate, Arthur thinks—and I agree—to say that Leibniz means to eliminate time.Arthur attributes to Leibniz a similar view of space. In his famous exchange of letters with Samuel Clarke, Leibniz contrasts his mature view of space (and time) with Newton’s views. In broad strokes, Clarke and Newton think of space as an immobile, unchanging backdrop. Bodies are in space by being collocated with regions of space. Bodies move through space by collocating with different regions of space at different times. In opposition to this picture, and in keeping with his own understanding of time, Leibniz suggests that existing things stand directly in spatial relations to one another. As with time, one thing is cospatial with another thing not because of the way that both are related to some special, independent third thing—namely, space—but rather because of the relations they bear to one another (and other similar things). And, again, as with time, space itself is an abstract ordering relation that structures not only all actual spatial relations at a time but also all possible spatial relations at a time. It is, Leibniz tells us, the “order of coexistence,” and, like time, it is an abstract, ideal structure that resides in the divine intellect.Leibniz wrote his letters to Clarke in the final years of his life. (One imagines him dying with pen in hand, one more argument against his great adversary still in his inkwell.) Leibniz’s thinking about the nature of space, however, goes back to some of his very earliest writings. In those early writings, according to Arthur, Leibniz developed the idea that “the divine attribute of immensity is the basis of space” and that divine immensity is divided into a network of regions by the motions of bodies contained in it (123). On Arthur’s telling, Leibniz was then led by his study of Hobbes to develop a new mathematics of situation, Leibniz’s famed analysis situs. Leibniz’s analysis situs, in turn, provided him with formal tools for characterizing space both as a changing network of regions and as a system of relative positions. It became possible to understand space as an abstract system of possible positions structuring the spatial relations between existing things. On Arthur’s reading, there is thus a progressive, mostly continuous line of development in Leibniz’s thinking about the nature of space from the late 1670s until his death in 1716.Arthur’s progressive, mostly continuous reading of Leibniz’s views on space stands in provocative contrast to past and recent work by Vincenzo de Risi. In forthcoming work, De Risi (forthcoming) argues that Leibniz’s views on space can be divided into three periods: an early substantivalist view, a middle Scholastic view rooted in the idea of imaginary space, and his famous late relational view. Most intriguingly, De Risi proposes that Leibniz’s relational view emerges for the first time only in the late 1680s and that it is prompted precisely by Leibniz’s clandestine reading of Newton’s Principia. On De Risi’s reading, Leibniz’s views on space are not an evolving refinement of a core theory but rather a series of essentially distinct theories. Leibniz’s relational theory is not the almost miraculously coincidental twin of Newton’s substantivalism, as it might appear to be from the Leibniz–Clark correspondence. Rather, it was crafted from the ground up by Leibniz as an alternative to the position of his great rival. Arthur and de Risi have opened up an exciting interpretative area of great consequence for early modern philosophy and science. Scholars looking for the next big thing in Leibniz studies may need to look no further.In taking up Leibniz’s views on motion, Arthur emphasizes a distinction Leibniz makes between motion conceived geometrically and motion with respect to cause. Motion conceived geometrically involves nothing more than a mere change of situation. Leibniz maintains that between any two bodies geometrical motion is relative and mutual. If our ships pass in the night, your ship moves relative to mine and mine moves relative to yours. There’s no saying—it doesn’t even make sense to ask—which is really moving. Motion with respect to cause “involves identifying the subject of motion by reference to the best explanation of the change” (321). Suppose there is a breeze and your sails are raised. The best explanation for our change of relative situation is that your boat is being driven by the wind while mine is resting in the water. In this case, the best hypothesis is that your boat is truly moving with respect to cause while mine is not. Motion with respect to cause is thus not—in contrast to geometrical motion—necessarily relative. In the case of motion with respect to cause, we can ask, and even hazard an educated guess, whether it is your boat or my boat that is really moving.Arthur shows how Leibniz’s distinction between geometrical and causal motion may be used to untangle some prima facie puzzles that have been raised for Leibniz’s theory of motion. Take, for example, the apparent tension between Leibniz’s commitment to the “equipollence of hypotheses” and his apparent endorsement of Copernicanism. In explicating the equipollence of hypotheses, Leibniz insists that “all hypotheses about the motions of any bodies whatsoever, however numerous, that are moved solely by corporeal impacts, it follows that not even an angel could discern, in mathematical rigor, which of the many bodies of this kind is at rest, and is the center of motion of the others” (248–49). Copernicanism, however, suggests that we—not to mention the angels—can say that the earth and planets move and that the sun is at rest. Faced with the obvious tension between these two commitments, it is tempting simply to favor one commitment at the expense of the other. It is tempting to suppose either that Leibniz’s equipollence of hypotheses is a disingenuous sop to the powers of Rome or that Leibniz’s commitment to Copernicanism is faint of heart—that Leibniz, for example, is only commending Copernicanism as merely one of many possible systems.On Arthur’s reading, Leibniz’s distinction between geometrical and causal motion suggests a more satisfying middle path. Leibniz does think that from a geometrical point of view, Copernicanism should be counted as merely one among many possible systems. And he really does believe that even an angel couldn’t say, from a geometrical point of view, whether the planets or the sun is in motion. From a geometrical point of view, such questions don’t even make sense. But they do make sense from a causal point of view, and from a causal point of view we can make better and worse hypotheses about which bodies are really moving. Leibniz can thus coherently insist that from a geometrical point of view Copernicanism is merely one among many possible systems, while still maintaining that from a causal point of view the Copernican system is our best hypothesis, that the planets really move, that the sun is really at rest. On Arthur’s reading, even if Leibniz’s language is conciliatory, there is nothing faint-hearted about his commitment to Copernicanism.Leibniz On Time, Space, and Relativity is a masterpiece of scholarship. It is historically, philosophically, and technically rich. (Did I mention that it includes a series of appendixes containing formal expositions, detailed explications of Arthur’s background views, and original translations? There is even a glossary of technical terms!) It is not, it should be conceded, an easy book. Although clearly written and organized, it is long and detailed. There is enough material between its covers for at least three important books, one on each of its principal subjects. Indeed, it is so chock-full of arguments, textual notes, and scholarly details that one might be tempted to suppose that it is dense in the mathematician’s sense, that between any two philosophical arguments, notes, or scholarly details, one will always be able to find another argument, note, or scholarly detail. For those with a taste for virtuosic scholarship and an interest in Leibniz, early modern philosophy, or the philosophy of space and time, Arthur’s masterpiece promises a dense but endless series of delights. Treat yourself.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW PHILOSOPHY-
CiteScore
7.40
自引率
0.00%
发文量
17
期刊介绍: In continuous publication since 1892, the Philosophical Review has a long-standing reputation for excellence and has published many papers now considered classics in the field, such as W. V. O. Quine"s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” Thomas Nagel"s “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” and the early work of John Rawls. The journal aims to publish original scholarly work in all areas of analytic philosophy, with an emphasis on material of general interest to academic philosophers, and is one of the few journals in the discipline to publish book reviews.
期刊最新文献
Reasons First Dark Matters: Pessimism and the Problem of Suffering Democratic Law Sustaining Democracy: What We Owe to the Other Side Mind and World in Aristotle’s De Anima
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1