{"title":"利用扭曲:科学中的解释、理想化和普遍性","authors":"H. K. Andersen","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10469551","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Questions about idealizations in science are often framed along the lines of, How can science be so effective when it gets so much wrong? Rice’s book, Leveraging Distortions: Explanation, Idealization, and Universality in Science offers a refinement on this framing, where we need not commit to the premise that idealizations are, in fact, wrong, that they need to be contained to the irrelevant parts of a model, or should be explained away as mere appearance. Rice takes a holist approach in which idealization is more like a process by which models as a whole are leveraged into better fit with their targets. Idealizations should not be carved out one by one on this approach; they make sense in the context of the models in which they figure, and they distort in ways that illuminate features like universal behavior in the systems being modeled. This is a refreshing approach to how idealizations work, one that does not require the common presupposition that idealizations are simply false.By universality, Rice means “the stability of certain patterns or behaviors across systems that are heterogeneous in their features. Universality classes are, then, just the group of systems that will display those universal patterns or behaviors” (155). Universality enables a more abstract description of systems than what scientists may have started with, and this process of making the description of the behavior more universal serves to identify common causal structures implemented in very different physical mediums. Different descriptions of causal relata facilitate identification of more unifying patterns of behavior. Given how often philosophers think of abstraction as somehow eliminating causation, by identifying causation too strongly with microphysical details, universality is a helpful way to bring the process of abstracting description back into contact with the way in which models inevitably involve causal structure, and how that causal structure itself can be better understood by connecting classes of systems with heterogeneous physical media and similar behavior, by showing how the more abstract descriptions of causal structure are deployed in each.There are two specific features of his view that set Rice’s book apart from most other contemporary views on idealizations. The first is the explicit emphasis on holism. Often, idealizations are isolated from models and then assessed on their own after extraction from the modeling context in which they were made. In evaluating idealizations as individual propositions removed from surrounding context, it is somewhat unsurprising that many look inaccurate. Rice aptly shows how idealization plays a key role in identifying universality behavior by distorting a whole, undecomposed model. This focus on holism and the role idealizations play in a larger modeling context helps Rice’s treatment of idealizations stand apart from many others, including those he explicitly engages with, such as Angela Potochnik (2017), Michael Strevens (2011), and Kareem Khalifa (2017). This approach fits better with the usage of idealizations in science by not needing to explain away the widespread reliance on idealization in so many sciences. Even if one thinks the other accounts are successful in trying to explain why idealizations can be used in science despite falsity and misrepresentation, there is something uncomfortable about explaining such widespread use of them by framing it as apparently irrational. Rice’s account does not require starting from a framing where scientists rampantly engage in apparently irrational practices and then explain why it is not as bad as it looks. Instead of using idealizations despite falsity, idealizations are part of a coherent package that can be used for explanatory leverage.The second feature that sets his view apart follows from this: idealizations are a tool to be actively used, not peculiarities to be explained away or dubious commitments to be minimized. Too often, idealizations are treated as some kind of representational failure, a compensation for epistemic limitations. In a more epistemically perfect world, on such thinking, idealizations could be done away with. Rice turns this around: idealizations are not something we put up with or have to be resigned to; they are a key tool to be used in positive ways to generate explanations and for building bodies of understanding. This is where the “leveraging” part of the title comes in: idealizations are actively relied on to achieve modeling techniques that would be impossible otherwise. They are a lever by which to torque a model into better alignment. This positive feature of idealizations accounts for the advantageous character of idealizations as a feature, not a bug.While Rice is, in my view, exactly right to reject these background presuppositions about the falsity of idealizations, I would also add that he could go further in this regard; the book would benefit from more explicit discussion of what he means by truth or falsity. There are pragmatist versions of truth, for example, that are quite consonant with his final view, so that it need not be framed as a puzzle that false statements somehow work to return genuine knowledge. Idealizations are usually presupposed to be false; authors like Potochnik (2017), in fact, define them as false, such that if it is an idealization, then by definition, it could not be true. Rice does not seem to endorse this, yet accurate representation is left hanging somewhat. A discussion of epistemic standards of veridicality that should be used for the holistic evaluation the of models, and the ways in which various identifiable components of those models accomplish this without decomposition, would strengthen his overall push toward a more explicit and foregrounded holism about models and his claims in chapter 8 about realism.That is quite mild, as critical remarks go, and most of the book is full of detailed examples and other discussions that don’t require a further discussion of truth. There is a lot covered in this book, much of which Rice has written about elsewhere and some of which he extends, refines, or adds to in new ways in the book. In the introduction, Rice stakes the main claim that pervasive distortion doesn’t just happen in science; it is central to science working as well as it does that such distortion take place. This sets up the later chapters on universality as a behavior that can be instantiated in physically heterogeneous systems and identified with more abstract (and distorting) descriptions of those systems. This introduction does a good job of situating why this alternative stance toward idealizations as pervasive distortions that are used for purposes that cannot be served with other tools differs from approaches where idealizations are considered after isolating them from modeling contexts and then evaluating them as false yet useful.Chapter 2 discusses what Rice calls the causal or causal-mechanical paradigm in literature on explanation. The causal approach, as he characterizes it, explains an event by giving the relevant factors in the event’s causal history. Wesley Salmon, James Woodward, Michael Strevens, Angela Potochnik, and the wide range of authors working in the ‘new mechanisms’ discussion are highlighted as examples of this. Rice is right to highlight how widespread discussions of causation are in discussions of explanation, and it is great to see Salmon given more credit. At the same time, this chapter lumps together some heterogeneous approaches, like Woodward’s (2005) account of causal explanation, for example. Woodward gives an account of those explanations that are causal without claiming that this is exhaustive of all explanation; there could be noncausal explanations, but he just isn’t discussing this possibility. Strevens (2011), in contrast, takes himself to be providing a complete account of explanation based on causation; Potochnik (2017), as well, offers an account of explanation in which causation, in the form of causal patterns, plays a necessary role.Chapter 3 follows this up by demonstrating with a series of examples a number of explanations that do not involve causation. This chapter may be overkill if the goal was to demonstrate that not all explanations need be causal explanations, since some of the apparent targets, like Woodward, already agree with this, and there is a lot of interesting work on distinctively mathematical explanations that highlights how they contrast with and complement causal explanations that he does not engage with. But as a collection of examples of noncausal explanation, this chapter has new material to add to existing examples, especially to the examples of distinctively statistical explanations given by Marc Lange (2016).In chapter 4, Rice lays out his own counterfactual account of explanation and contrasts it with other such accounts. He offers three criteria that any such account should meet that will be useful in these discussions (93), even if one does not want to adopt Rice’s own particular account. The details of Rice’s own account here seem compressed, and if one just reads this chapter, it is hard to see how this is supposed to work and be a genuine move forward. The later chapters, especially chapters 6, 7, and 9, show how the account works when applied, which is illuminating. It would thus be useful, for instance if teaching from the book in a seminar, to pair chapter 4 with one of these further chapters, especially chapter 6.Chapter 5 is brief, focused on how decomposition of models into subcomponents that are then treated separately simply doesn’t work for most models. Rice makes some very clear points about why models must be treated holistically, solidifying his point about idealizations as distortions in those models that don’t make sense when taken out of that context through attempts at decomposition.Universality, a term of art here that follows on Rice’s other work (see, e.g., Rice 2018, 2019; Batterman and Rice 2014), is given detailed treatment in chapter 6. This chapter lays out some detailed case studies and illustrates how the holistic distortion involved in idealization is what conveys or captures the specifically modal information in a model. Chapter 7 continues with themes Rice has written about elsewhere: multiscale models and how universality fits into considerations of scale and renormalization.Chapter 8 moves on to consider how models can provide understanding even when they do not do so by providing explanations. Rice’s examples involve cases where scientists have incomplete explanations, so some might consider these to be explanations already, since one need not require that an explanation be fully complete in order to count as an explanation. This chapter also connects understanding to realism and scientific progress. Idealizations have often been treated as failures for realism, where an otherwise successful model is purportedly decomposed into elements, some of which are clearly not literally representationally accurate in the way one might suppose necessary to be a realist about that component (another way in which naive correspondence treatments of truth sneak into philosophy of science by way of assuming that bits of models should map one-to-one to bits of the world and that realism about a model fails if there are idealizations that don’t map in this simplified way). He draws on his own account of factive understanding, in the first part of the chapter, to lay out an alternative approach to realism where the focus is not on isolated model components but on the body of understanding that models produce for scientists. This body of understanding, which again requires holism, can serve as an epistemic basis for realism about the behavior thus understood.Finally, in chapter 9, Rice brings together all the themes in the book and makes the clearest case yet for how idealizations are used as “holistic distortions” that are not merely part of science but central and positively contributory to the success of modeling techniques in providing both explanation and understanding. This chapter is a great conclusion to bring together the different topics in the book. Many of the other topics are ones Rice has written about elsewhere, and this concluding chapter helps make sense of the synoptic project into which all this work fits. If one were teaching with this this text, this might be a good chapter to start with rather than to end with.Overall, this book does a nice job of bringing together Rice’s previous work while also extending that work with new examples and ones worked out in more detail, and connecting the different topics in a cohesive way around the orientation toward holism and idealizations as holistic model distortions. This makes it a great addition to a range of contemporary discussions around explanation, models, understanding, and realism, and a good starting point for graduate students to get into these topics.","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"75 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":2.8000,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"2","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"<i>Leveraging Distortions: Explanation, Idealization, and Universality in Science</i>\",\"authors\":\"H. K. Andersen\",\"doi\":\"10.1215/00318108-10469551\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Questions about idealizations in science are often framed along the lines of, How can science be so effective when it gets so much wrong? Rice’s book, Leveraging Distortions: Explanation, Idealization, and Universality in Science offers a refinement on this framing, where we need not commit to the premise that idealizations are, in fact, wrong, that they need to be contained to the irrelevant parts of a model, or should be explained away as mere appearance. Rice takes a holist approach in which idealization is more like a process by which models as a whole are leveraged into better fit with their targets. Idealizations should not be carved out one by one on this approach; they make sense in the context of the models in which they figure, and they distort in ways that illuminate features like universal behavior in the systems being modeled. This is a refreshing approach to how idealizations work, one that does not require the common presupposition that idealizations are simply false.By universality, Rice means “the stability of certain patterns or behaviors across systems that are heterogeneous in their features. Universality classes are, then, just the group of systems that will display those universal patterns or behaviors” (155). Universality enables a more abstract description of systems than what scientists may have started with, and this process of making the description of the behavior more universal serves to identify common causal structures implemented in very different physical mediums. Different descriptions of causal relata facilitate identification of more unifying patterns of behavior. Given how often philosophers think of abstraction as somehow eliminating causation, by identifying causation too strongly with microphysical details, universality is a helpful way to bring the process of abstracting description back into contact with the way in which models inevitably involve causal structure, and how that causal structure itself can be better understood by connecting classes of systems with heterogeneous physical media and similar behavior, by showing how the more abstract descriptions of causal structure are deployed in each.There are two specific features of his view that set Rice’s book apart from most other contemporary views on idealizations. The first is the explicit emphasis on holism. Often, idealizations are isolated from models and then assessed on their own after extraction from the modeling context in which they were made. In evaluating idealizations as individual propositions removed from surrounding context, it is somewhat unsurprising that many look inaccurate. Rice aptly shows how idealization plays a key role in identifying universality behavior by distorting a whole, undecomposed model. This focus on holism and the role idealizations play in a larger modeling context helps Rice’s treatment of idealizations stand apart from many others, including those he explicitly engages with, such as Angela Potochnik (2017), Michael Strevens (2011), and Kareem Khalifa (2017). This approach fits better with the usage of idealizations in science by not needing to explain away the widespread reliance on idealization in so many sciences. Even if one thinks the other accounts are successful in trying to explain why idealizations can be used in science despite falsity and misrepresentation, there is something uncomfortable about explaining such widespread use of them by framing it as apparently irrational. Rice’s account does not require starting from a framing where scientists rampantly engage in apparently irrational practices and then explain why it is not as bad as it looks. Instead of using idealizations despite falsity, idealizations are part of a coherent package that can be used for explanatory leverage.The second feature that sets his view apart follows from this: idealizations are a tool to be actively used, not peculiarities to be explained away or dubious commitments to be minimized. Too often, idealizations are treated as some kind of representational failure, a compensation for epistemic limitations. In a more epistemically perfect world, on such thinking, idealizations could be done away with. Rice turns this around: idealizations are not something we put up with or have to be resigned to; they are a key tool to be used in positive ways to generate explanations and for building bodies of understanding. This is where the “leveraging” part of the title comes in: idealizations are actively relied on to achieve modeling techniques that would be impossible otherwise. They are a lever by which to torque a model into better alignment. This positive feature of idealizations accounts for the advantageous character of idealizations as a feature, not a bug.While Rice is, in my view, exactly right to reject these background presuppositions about the falsity of idealizations, I would also add that he could go further in this regard; the book would benefit from more explicit discussion of what he means by truth or falsity. There are pragmatist versions of truth, for example, that are quite consonant with his final view, so that it need not be framed as a puzzle that false statements somehow work to return genuine knowledge. Idealizations are usually presupposed to be false; authors like Potochnik (2017), in fact, define them as false, such that if it is an idealization, then by definition, it could not be true. Rice does not seem to endorse this, yet accurate representation is left hanging somewhat. A discussion of epistemic standards of veridicality that should be used for the holistic evaluation the of models, and the ways in which various identifiable components of those models accomplish this without decomposition, would strengthen his overall push toward a more explicit and foregrounded holism about models and his claims in chapter 8 about realism.That is quite mild, as critical remarks go, and most of the book is full of detailed examples and other discussions that don’t require a further discussion of truth. There is a lot covered in this book, much of which Rice has written about elsewhere and some of which he extends, refines, or adds to in new ways in the book. In the introduction, Rice stakes the main claim that pervasive distortion doesn’t just happen in science; it is central to science working as well as it does that such distortion take place. This sets up the later chapters on universality as a behavior that can be instantiated in physically heterogeneous systems and identified with more abstract (and distorting) descriptions of those systems. This introduction does a good job of situating why this alternative stance toward idealizations as pervasive distortions that are used for purposes that cannot be served with other tools differs from approaches where idealizations are considered after isolating them from modeling contexts and then evaluating them as false yet useful.Chapter 2 discusses what Rice calls the causal or causal-mechanical paradigm in literature on explanation. The causal approach, as he characterizes it, explains an event by giving the relevant factors in the event’s causal history. Wesley Salmon, James Woodward, Michael Strevens, Angela Potochnik, and the wide range of authors working in the ‘new mechanisms’ discussion are highlighted as examples of this. Rice is right to highlight how widespread discussions of causation are in discussions of explanation, and it is great to see Salmon given more credit. At the same time, this chapter lumps together some heterogeneous approaches, like Woodward’s (2005) account of causal explanation, for example. Woodward gives an account of those explanations that are causal without claiming that this is exhaustive of all explanation; there could be noncausal explanations, but he just isn’t discussing this possibility. Strevens (2011), in contrast, takes himself to be providing a complete account of explanation based on causation; Potochnik (2017), as well, offers an account of explanation in which causation, in the form of causal patterns, plays a necessary role.Chapter 3 follows this up by demonstrating with a series of examples a number of explanations that do not involve causation. This chapter may be overkill if the goal was to demonstrate that not all explanations need be causal explanations, since some of the apparent targets, like Woodward, already agree with this, and there is a lot of interesting work on distinctively mathematical explanations that highlights how they contrast with and complement causal explanations that he does not engage with. But as a collection of examples of noncausal explanation, this chapter has new material to add to existing examples, especially to the examples of distinctively statistical explanations given by Marc Lange (2016).In chapter 4, Rice lays out his own counterfactual account of explanation and contrasts it with other such accounts. He offers three criteria that any such account should meet that will be useful in these discussions (93), even if one does not want to adopt Rice’s own particular account. The details of Rice’s own account here seem compressed, and if one just reads this chapter, it is hard to see how this is supposed to work and be a genuine move forward. The later chapters, especially chapters 6, 7, and 9, show how the account works when applied, which is illuminating. It would thus be useful, for instance if teaching from the book in a seminar, to pair chapter 4 with one of these further chapters, especially chapter 6.Chapter 5 is brief, focused on how decomposition of models into subcomponents that are then treated separately simply doesn’t work for most models. Rice makes some very clear points about why models must be treated holistically, solidifying his point about idealizations as distortions in those models that don’t make sense when taken out of that context through attempts at decomposition.Universality, a term of art here that follows on Rice’s other work (see, e.g., Rice 2018, 2019; Batterman and Rice 2014), is given detailed treatment in chapter 6. This chapter lays out some detailed case studies and illustrates how the holistic distortion involved in idealization is what conveys or captures the specifically modal information in a model. Chapter 7 continues with themes Rice has written about elsewhere: multiscale models and how universality fits into considerations of scale and renormalization.Chapter 8 moves on to consider how models can provide understanding even when they do not do so by providing explanations. Rice’s examples involve cases where scientists have incomplete explanations, so some might consider these to be explanations already, since one need not require that an explanation be fully complete in order to count as an explanation. This chapter also connects understanding to realism and scientific progress. Idealizations have often been treated as failures for realism, where an otherwise successful model is purportedly decomposed into elements, some of which are clearly not literally representationally accurate in the way one might suppose necessary to be a realist about that component (another way in which naive correspondence treatments of truth sneak into philosophy of science by way of assuming that bits of models should map one-to-one to bits of the world and that realism about a model fails if there are idealizations that don’t map in this simplified way). He draws on his own account of factive understanding, in the first part of the chapter, to lay out an alternative approach to realism where the focus is not on isolated model components but on the body of understanding that models produce for scientists. This body of understanding, which again requires holism, can serve as an epistemic basis for realism about the behavior thus understood.Finally, in chapter 9, Rice brings together all the themes in the book and makes the clearest case yet for how idealizations are used as “holistic distortions” that are not merely part of science but central and positively contributory to the success of modeling techniques in providing both explanation and understanding. This chapter is a great conclusion to bring together the different topics in the book. Many of the other topics are ones Rice has written about elsewhere, and this concluding chapter helps make sense of the synoptic project into which all this work fits. If one were teaching with this this text, this might be a good chapter to start with rather than to end with.Overall, this book does a nice job of bringing together Rice’s previous work while also extending that work with new examples and ones worked out in more detail, and connecting the different topics in a cohesive way around the orientation toward holism and idealizations as holistic model distortions. This makes it a great addition to a range of contemporary discussions around explanation, models, understanding, and realism, and a good starting point for graduate students to get into these topics.\",\"PeriodicalId\":48129,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW\",\"volume\":\"75 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":2.8000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-07-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"2\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10469551\",\"RegionNum\":1,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"0\",\"JCRName\":\"PHILOSOPHY\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10469551","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
摘要
关于科学中理想化的问题通常是这样的,当科学有这么多错误时,它怎么能如此有效?赖斯的书《利用扭曲:科学中的解释、理想化和普遍性》对这一框架进行了改进,我们不需要坚持理想化实际上是错误的前提,不需要将理想化包含在模型的无关部分中,也不需要将其解释为仅仅是表面现象。Rice采用了一种整体的方法,在这种方法中,理想化更像是一个过程,通过这个过程,模型作为一个整体被杠杆化,以更好地适应它们的目标。在这种方法上不应该一个接一个地进行理想化;它们在它们所处的模型环境中是有意义的,它们以扭曲的方式阐明了被建模系统中的普遍行为等特征。这是一种令人耳目一新的理想化工作方式,它不需要通常的假设,即理想化是完全错误的。Rice所说的普适性指的是“某些模式或行为的稳定性,这些模式或行为跨越了具有异质特征的系统”。那么,普遍性类就是将显示这些普遍模式或行为的一组系统”(155)。普适性使得对系统的描述比科学家开始时的描述更加抽象,这种使行为描述更加普适性的过程有助于识别在非常不同的物理介质中实现的共同因果结构。对因果关系的不同描述有助于识别更统一的行为模式。考虑到哲学家经常认为抽象是某种程度上消除因果关系,通过将因果关系过于强烈地与微观物理细节联系起来,普遍性是一种有用的方式,可以将抽象描述的过程重新与模型不可避免地涉及因果结构的方式联系起来,以及如何通过将具有异质物理介质和相似行为的系统类联系起来,更好地理解因果结构本身。通过展示因果结构的更抽象的描述是如何被部署在每个。他的观点有两个特点,使赖斯的书与大多数同时代的理想化观点不同。首先是明确强调整体论。通常,理想化是从模型中分离出来的,然后在从创建理想化的建模环境中提取出来之后,对理想化进行自己的评估。在评估理想化作为从周围环境中移除的单个命题时,许多看起来不准确并不令人惊讶。Rice恰当地展示了理想化如何通过扭曲一个完整的、未分解的模型,在识别普遍性行为方面发挥关键作用。这种对整体主义和理想化在更大的建模背景下所扮演的角色的关注,有助于Rice对理想化的处理与许多其他人区别开来,包括他明确参与的人,如Angela Potochnik (2017), Michael Strevens(2011)和Kareem Khalifa(2017)。这种方法更适合理想化在科学中的应用,因为它不需要解释许多科学中对理想化的广泛依赖。即使有人认为其他的描述成功地解释了为什么理想化可以在科学中被使用,尽管存在虚假和歪曲,但通过将其描述为明显的非理性来解释它们的广泛使用,也会让人感到不舒服。赖斯的描述并不需要从科学家猖獗地从事显然不合理的实践的框架开始,然后解释为什么它不像看起来那么糟糕。而不是不顾错误地使用理想化,理想化是可以用于解释杠杆的连贯包的一部分。使他的观点与众不同的第二个特征是:理想化是一种积极使用的工具,而不是用来解释的怪癖,也不是用来最小化的可疑承诺。通常,理想化被视为某种代表性的失败,是对认知局限性的一种补偿。在一个认识论上更完美的世界里,根据这种思维,理想化可以被废除。赖斯把这一点颠倒过来:理想化不是我们必须忍受或顺从的东西;它们是一个关键的工具,可以积极地用于产生解释和建立理解体系。这就是标题中“利用”部分的由来:积极地依赖理想化来实现建模技术,否则这是不可能的。它们是一个杠杆,通过它可以使模型更好地对齐。理想化的这种积极特性说明了理想化作为一种特性而不是缺陷的优势。 Rice提出了一些非常明确的观点,说明为什么必须从整体上看待模型,并巩固了他的观点,即理想化是那些模型中的扭曲,当通过尝试分解而脱离上下文时,这些模型就没有意义了。普遍性,这是Rice的其他工作之后的一个艺术术语(例如,Rice 2018, 2019;Batterman and Rice 2014),在第6章给出了详细的处理。本章列出了一些详细的案例研究,并说明了在理想化中所涉及的整体扭曲是如何在模型中传达或捕获特定模态信息的。第7章继续讨论Rice在其他地方写过的主题:多尺度模型以及如何将普适性纳入尺度和重整化的考虑。第8章继续考虑模型如何提供理解,即使它们没有通过提供解释来提供理解。赖斯的例子涉及到一些科学家解释不完整的情况,所以有些人可能认为这些已经是解释了,因为人们不需要一个解释完全完整才能算作一个解释。本章还将理解与现实主义和科学进步联系起来。理想化常常被视为现实主义的失败,在现实主义中,一个原本成功的模型被分解成元素,其中一些显然在字面上不具有表征上的准确性人们可能会认为这是一个现实主义者对这一组成部分的必要方式(另一种方式是对真理的朴素对应处理通过假设模型的部分应该一对一地映射到世界的部分如果理想化没有以这种简化的方式映射,那么关于模型的现实主义就会失败)。在本章的第一部分,他利用自己对实际理解的描述,提出了一种替代现实主义的方法,这种方法的重点不是孤立的模型组件,而是模型为科学家产生的理解主体。这种理解主体,同样需要整体主义,可以作为关于由此理解的行为的实在论的认识基础。最后,在第9章中,Rice汇集了书中的所有主题,并提出了迄今为止最清晰的案例,说明理想化如何被用作“整体扭曲”,这不仅是科学的一部分,而且是建模技术在提供解释和理解方面的成功的核心和积极贡献。这一章是一个很好的结论,汇集了书中的不同主题。许多其他主题是Rice在其他地方写过的,这一结语有助于理解所有这些工作所适合的概要性项目。如果有人用这段经文来教学,这可能是一个很好的开始,而不是结束的章节。总的来说,这本书做得很好,汇集了Rice以前的工作,同时也扩展了新的例子和更详细的工作,并以一种有凝聚力的方式将不同的主题联系起来,围绕整体主义和理想化作为整体模型扭曲的方向。这使得它成为一系列关于解释、模型、理解和现实主义的当代讨论的一个很好的补充,也是研究生进入这些主题的一个很好的起点。
Leveraging Distortions: Explanation, Idealization, and Universality in Science
Questions about idealizations in science are often framed along the lines of, How can science be so effective when it gets so much wrong? Rice’s book, Leveraging Distortions: Explanation, Idealization, and Universality in Science offers a refinement on this framing, where we need not commit to the premise that idealizations are, in fact, wrong, that they need to be contained to the irrelevant parts of a model, or should be explained away as mere appearance. Rice takes a holist approach in which idealization is more like a process by which models as a whole are leveraged into better fit with their targets. Idealizations should not be carved out one by one on this approach; they make sense in the context of the models in which they figure, and they distort in ways that illuminate features like universal behavior in the systems being modeled. This is a refreshing approach to how idealizations work, one that does not require the common presupposition that idealizations are simply false.By universality, Rice means “the stability of certain patterns or behaviors across systems that are heterogeneous in their features. Universality classes are, then, just the group of systems that will display those universal patterns or behaviors” (155). Universality enables a more abstract description of systems than what scientists may have started with, and this process of making the description of the behavior more universal serves to identify common causal structures implemented in very different physical mediums. Different descriptions of causal relata facilitate identification of more unifying patterns of behavior. Given how often philosophers think of abstraction as somehow eliminating causation, by identifying causation too strongly with microphysical details, universality is a helpful way to bring the process of abstracting description back into contact with the way in which models inevitably involve causal structure, and how that causal structure itself can be better understood by connecting classes of systems with heterogeneous physical media and similar behavior, by showing how the more abstract descriptions of causal structure are deployed in each.There are two specific features of his view that set Rice’s book apart from most other contemporary views on idealizations. The first is the explicit emphasis on holism. Often, idealizations are isolated from models and then assessed on their own after extraction from the modeling context in which they were made. In evaluating idealizations as individual propositions removed from surrounding context, it is somewhat unsurprising that many look inaccurate. Rice aptly shows how idealization plays a key role in identifying universality behavior by distorting a whole, undecomposed model. This focus on holism and the role idealizations play in a larger modeling context helps Rice’s treatment of idealizations stand apart from many others, including those he explicitly engages with, such as Angela Potochnik (2017), Michael Strevens (2011), and Kareem Khalifa (2017). This approach fits better with the usage of idealizations in science by not needing to explain away the widespread reliance on idealization in so many sciences. Even if one thinks the other accounts are successful in trying to explain why idealizations can be used in science despite falsity and misrepresentation, there is something uncomfortable about explaining such widespread use of them by framing it as apparently irrational. Rice’s account does not require starting from a framing where scientists rampantly engage in apparently irrational practices and then explain why it is not as bad as it looks. Instead of using idealizations despite falsity, idealizations are part of a coherent package that can be used for explanatory leverage.The second feature that sets his view apart follows from this: idealizations are a tool to be actively used, not peculiarities to be explained away or dubious commitments to be minimized. Too often, idealizations are treated as some kind of representational failure, a compensation for epistemic limitations. In a more epistemically perfect world, on such thinking, idealizations could be done away with. Rice turns this around: idealizations are not something we put up with or have to be resigned to; they are a key tool to be used in positive ways to generate explanations and for building bodies of understanding. This is where the “leveraging” part of the title comes in: idealizations are actively relied on to achieve modeling techniques that would be impossible otherwise. They are a lever by which to torque a model into better alignment. This positive feature of idealizations accounts for the advantageous character of idealizations as a feature, not a bug.While Rice is, in my view, exactly right to reject these background presuppositions about the falsity of idealizations, I would also add that he could go further in this regard; the book would benefit from more explicit discussion of what he means by truth or falsity. There are pragmatist versions of truth, for example, that are quite consonant with his final view, so that it need not be framed as a puzzle that false statements somehow work to return genuine knowledge. Idealizations are usually presupposed to be false; authors like Potochnik (2017), in fact, define them as false, such that if it is an idealization, then by definition, it could not be true. Rice does not seem to endorse this, yet accurate representation is left hanging somewhat. A discussion of epistemic standards of veridicality that should be used for the holistic evaluation the of models, and the ways in which various identifiable components of those models accomplish this without decomposition, would strengthen his overall push toward a more explicit and foregrounded holism about models and his claims in chapter 8 about realism.That is quite mild, as critical remarks go, and most of the book is full of detailed examples and other discussions that don’t require a further discussion of truth. There is a lot covered in this book, much of which Rice has written about elsewhere and some of which he extends, refines, or adds to in new ways in the book. In the introduction, Rice stakes the main claim that pervasive distortion doesn’t just happen in science; it is central to science working as well as it does that such distortion take place. This sets up the later chapters on universality as a behavior that can be instantiated in physically heterogeneous systems and identified with more abstract (and distorting) descriptions of those systems. This introduction does a good job of situating why this alternative stance toward idealizations as pervasive distortions that are used for purposes that cannot be served with other tools differs from approaches where idealizations are considered after isolating them from modeling contexts and then evaluating them as false yet useful.Chapter 2 discusses what Rice calls the causal or causal-mechanical paradigm in literature on explanation. The causal approach, as he characterizes it, explains an event by giving the relevant factors in the event’s causal history. Wesley Salmon, James Woodward, Michael Strevens, Angela Potochnik, and the wide range of authors working in the ‘new mechanisms’ discussion are highlighted as examples of this. Rice is right to highlight how widespread discussions of causation are in discussions of explanation, and it is great to see Salmon given more credit. At the same time, this chapter lumps together some heterogeneous approaches, like Woodward’s (2005) account of causal explanation, for example. Woodward gives an account of those explanations that are causal without claiming that this is exhaustive of all explanation; there could be noncausal explanations, but he just isn’t discussing this possibility. Strevens (2011), in contrast, takes himself to be providing a complete account of explanation based on causation; Potochnik (2017), as well, offers an account of explanation in which causation, in the form of causal patterns, plays a necessary role.Chapter 3 follows this up by demonstrating with a series of examples a number of explanations that do not involve causation. This chapter may be overkill if the goal was to demonstrate that not all explanations need be causal explanations, since some of the apparent targets, like Woodward, already agree with this, and there is a lot of interesting work on distinctively mathematical explanations that highlights how they contrast with and complement causal explanations that he does not engage with. But as a collection of examples of noncausal explanation, this chapter has new material to add to existing examples, especially to the examples of distinctively statistical explanations given by Marc Lange (2016).In chapter 4, Rice lays out his own counterfactual account of explanation and contrasts it with other such accounts. He offers three criteria that any such account should meet that will be useful in these discussions (93), even if one does not want to adopt Rice’s own particular account. The details of Rice’s own account here seem compressed, and if one just reads this chapter, it is hard to see how this is supposed to work and be a genuine move forward. The later chapters, especially chapters 6, 7, and 9, show how the account works when applied, which is illuminating. It would thus be useful, for instance if teaching from the book in a seminar, to pair chapter 4 with one of these further chapters, especially chapter 6.Chapter 5 is brief, focused on how decomposition of models into subcomponents that are then treated separately simply doesn’t work for most models. Rice makes some very clear points about why models must be treated holistically, solidifying his point about idealizations as distortions in those models that don’t make sense when taken out of that context through attempts at decomposition.Universality, a term of art here that follows on Rice’s other work (see, e.g., Rice 2018, 2019; Batterman and Rice 2014), is given detailed treatment in chapter 6. This chapter lays out some detailed case studies and illustrates how the holistic distortion involved in idealization is what conveys or captures the specifically modal information in a model. Chapter 7 continues with themes Rice has written about elsewhere: multiscale models and how universality fits into considerations of scale and renormalization.Chapter 8 moves on to consider how models can provide understanding even when they do not do so by providing explanations. Rice’s examples involve cases where scientists have incomplete explanations, so some might consider these to be explanations already, since one need not require that an explanation be fully complete in order to count as an explanation. This chapter also connects understanding to realism and scientific progress. Idealizations have often been treated as failures for realism, where an otherwise successful model is purportedly decomposed into elements, some of which are clearly not literally representationally accurate in the way one might suppose necessary to be a realist about that component (another way in which naive correspondence treatments of truth sneak into philosophy of science by way of assuming that bits of models should map one-to-one to bits of the world and that realism about a model fails if there are idealizations that don’t map in this simplified way). He draws on his own account of factive understanding, in the first part of the chapter, to lay out an alternative approach to realism where the focus is not on isolated model components but on the body of understanding that models produce for scientists. This body of understanding, which again requires holism, can serve as an epistemic basis for realism about the behavior thus understood.Finally, in chapter 9, Rice brings together all the themes in the book and makes the clearest case yet for how idealizations are used as “holistic distortions” that are not merely part of science but central and positively contributory to the success of modeling techniques in providing both explanation and understanding. This chapter is a great conclusion to bring together the different topics in the book. Many of the other topics are ones Rice has written about elsewhere, and this concluding chapter helps make sense of the synoptic project into which all this work fits. If one were teaching with this this text, this might be a good chapter to start with rather than to end with.Overall, this book does a nice job of bringing together Rice’s previous work while also extending that work with new examples and ones worked out in more detail, and connecting the different topics in a cohesive way around the orientation toward holism and idealizations as holistic model distortions. This makes it a great addition to a range of contemporary discussions around explanation, models, understanding, and realism, and a good starting point for graduate students to get into these topics.
期刊介绍:
In continuous publication since 1892, the Philosophical Review has a long-standing reputation for excellence and has published many papers now considered classics in the field, such as W. V. O. Quine"s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” Thomas Nagel"s “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” and the early work of John Rawls. The journal aims to publish original scholarly work in all areas of analytic philosophy, with an emphasis on material of general interest to academic philosophers, and is one of the few journals in the discipline to publish book reviews.