首页 > 最新文献

The Language of Ontology最新文献

英文 中文
Collapse and the Varieties of Quantifier Variance 崩溃与量词方差的变化
Pub Date : 2021-06-03 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0004
Matti Eklund
The aim of this chapter is to bring clarity regarding the doctrine of quantifier variance (due to Eli Hirsch), and two prominent arguments against this doctrine, the collapse argument and the Eklund-Hawthorne argument. Different versions of the doctrine of quantifier variance are distinguished, and it is shown that the effectiveness of the arguments against it depends on what version of the doctrine is at issue. The metaontological significance of the different versions of the doctrine is also assessed. Roughly, quantifier variance concerns there being different possible existential quantifier meanings, and often the doctrine involves a claim to the effect there is no unique “best” quantifier meaning. Much of the discussion in the chapter concerns what it is to be an existential quantifier meaning in the sense at issue.
本章的目的是澄清量词变异学说(由伊莱·赫希提出),以及反对这一学说的两个重要论点,即崩溃论点和埃克伦德-霍桑论点。量词变异学说的不同版本被区分开来,并表明反对它的论点的有效性取决于争论的是哪个版本的学说。本文还评估了不同版本的学说的形而上学意义。粗略地说,量词差异涉及存在不同可能的量词含义,并且通常学说涉及到没有唯一的“最佳”量词含义的主张。本章的大部分讨论都是关于存在量词在争议意义上的意义。
{"title":"Collapse and the Varieties of Quantifier Variance","authors":"Matti Eklund","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0004","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0004","url":null,"abstract":"The aim of this chapter is to bring clarity regarding the doctrine of quantifier variance (due to Eli Hirsch), and two prominent arguments against this doctrine, the collapse argument and the Eklund-Hawthorne argument. Different versions of the doctrine of quantifier variance are distinguished, and it is shown that the effectiveness of the arguments against it depends on what version of the doctrine is at issue. The metaontological significance of the different versions of the doctrine is also assessed. Roughly, quantifier variance concerns there being different possible existential quantifier meanings, and often the doctrine involves a claim to the effect there is no unique “best” quantifier meaning. Much of the discussion in the chapter concerns what it is to be an existential quantifier meaning in the sense at issue.","PeriodicalId":196928,"journal":{"name":"The Language of Ontology","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-06-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"129712427","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Levels of Ontology and Natural Language 本体与自然语言的层次
Pub Date : 2021-06-03 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0011
Friederike Moltmann
Two levels of ontology are commonly distinguished in metaphysics: the ontology of ordinary objects, or more generally ordinary ontology, and the ontology of what there really or fundamentally is. This chapter argues that natural language reflects not only the ordinary ontology but also a language-driven ontology, which is involved in the mass-count distinction and part-structure-sensitive semantic selection (as well as perhaps the light ontology of pleonastic entities in the sense of Schiffer). The language-driven ontology does not constitute another level of representation, but is taken to be a (selective) ontology of the real, given a plenitudinous or maximalist conception of reality. The language-driven ontology aligns closely with the functional part of grammar and a commitment to it is mandatory with the use of language. This gives rise to a novel view according to which part of ontology should be considered part of universal grammar on a broadened understanding. The chapter recasts the author’s older theory of situated part structures without situations, in purely ontological terms, making use of a primitive notion of unity.
在形而上学中,本体论通常分为两种层次:一种是关于普通对象的本体论,或者更一般地说,关于普通对象的本体论,另一种是关于真实存在或根本存在的本体论。本章认为,自然语言不仅反映了普通的本体论,而且反映了语言驱动的本体论,它涉及质量计数区分和部分结构敏感的语义选择(也可能是Schiffer意义上的pleonastic实体的轻本体论)。语言驱动的本体论并不构成表征的另一个层次,但被认为是现实的(选择性)本体论,给出了丰富的或最大的现实概念。语言驱动的本体与语法的功能部分密切相关,并且在使用语言时必须对其作出承诺。这就产生了一种新的观点,根据这种观点,本体论的一部分应该被认为是普遍语法的一部分。这一章重塑了作者的旧理论的位置部分结构没有情况下,在纯粹的本体论的条款,利用统一的原始概念。
{"title":"Levels of Ontology and Natural Language","authors":"Friederike Moltmann","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0011","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0011","url":null,"abstract":"Two levels of ontology are commonly distinguished in metaphysics: the ontology of ordinary objects, or more generally ordinary ontology, and the ontology of what there really or fundamentally is. This chapter argues that natural language reflects not only the ordinary ontology but also a language-driven ontology, which is involved in the mass-count distinction and part-structure-sensitive semantic selection (as well as perhaps the light ontology of pleonastic entities in the sense of Schiffer). The language-driven ontology does not constitute another level of representation, but is taken to be a (selective) ontology of the real, given a plenitudinous or maximalist conception of reality. The language-driven ontology aligns closely with the functional part of grammar and a commitment to it is mandatory with the use of language. This gives rise to a novel view according to which part of ontology should be considered part of universal grammar on a broadened understanding. The chapter recasts the author’s older theory of situated part structures without situations, in purely ontological terms, making use of a primitive notion of unity.","PeriodicalId":196928,"journal":{"name":"The Language of Ontology","volume":"70 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-06-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"127713772","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Structural Pluralism 结构多元化
Pub Date : 2021-06-03 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0010
Alessandro Torza
The chapter introduces and defends structural pluralism: the view that there is a plurality of ways of carving nature at the joints. The first part of the chapter argues that structural pluralism is able to meet a challenge to Ted Sider’s monism about joint-carving. The second part spells out the metaontological consequences of adopting structural pluralism, and shows that the view is compatible with a moderate form of deflationism about ontological disagreement. The third and last part fleshes out a number of consequences of adopting structural pluralism, and suggests further applications of that view, including a reassessment of an influential argument against vague existence.
这一章介绍并捍卫了结构多元论:即在接合处有多种雕刻自然的方式的观点。本章第一部分论述了结构多元主义对泰德·西德关于关节雕刻的一元论的挑战。第二部分阐述了采用结构多元主义的元本体论后果,并表明这种观点与关于本体论分歧的适度形式的通货紧缩主义是相容的。第三部分和最后一部分充实了采用结构多元主义的一些后果,并建议进一步应用这一观点,包括重新评估反对模糊存在的有影响力的论点。
{"title":"Structural Pluralism","authors":"Alessandro Torza","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0010","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0010","url":null,"abstract":"The chapter introduces and defends structural pluralism: the view that there is a plurality of ways of carving nature at the joints. The first part of the chapter argues that structural pluralism is able to meet a challenge to Ted Sider’s monism about joint-carving. The second part spells out the metaontological consequences of adopting structural pluralism, and shows that the view is compatible with a moderate form of deflationism about ontological disagreement. The third and last part fleshes out a number of consequences of adopting structural pluralism, and suggests further applications of that view, including a reassessment of an influential argument against vague existence.","PeriodicalId":196928,"journal":{"name":"The Language of Ontology","volume":"49 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-06-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"124018763","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Why Our Natural Languages Are Ideal Languages for Metaphysics 为什么我们的自然语言是形而上学的理想语言
Pub Date : 2021-06-03 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0006
Thomas Hofweber
The chapter argues that our human natural languages are ideal languages for metaphysics and perfectly suited to represent all the facts that metaphysics might aim to find out. It presents an argument for this conclusion from considerations about language alone, without assuming anything about what metaphysics aims to do other than that it is concerned with questions of fact, and without assuming anything about what reality in general is like. A crucial consideration in support of this argument concerns the possibility of facts ineffable for us human beings. We can see from reflecting on our own talk about facts that ineffable facts are ruled out, and thus that our languages are ideal languages for representing reality. After discussing how an argument of this kind could possibly work, the chapter outlines some larger metaphysical issues that all this is related to.
这一章认为,我们人类的自然语言是形而上学的理想语言,非常适合代表形而上学可能旨在发现的所有事实。它为这个结论提供了一个论证,仅从对语言的考虑出发,没有对形而上学的目的做任何假设,除了它所关心的事实问题,也没有对一般的现实是什么样子做任何假设。支持这一论点的一个关键考虑是,我们人类无法描述的事实的可能性。通过反思我们自己对事实的谈论,我们可以看到,不可言喻的事实被排除在外,因此我们的语言是代表现实的理想语言。在讨论了这种论证可能如何运作之后,本章概述了与所有这些相关的一些更大的形而上学问题。
{"title":"Why Our Natural Languages Are Ideal Languages for Metaphysics","authors":"Thomas Hofweber","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0006","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0006","url":null,"abstract":"The chapter argues that our human natural languages are ideal languages for metaphysics and perfectly suited to represent all the facts that metaphysics might aim to find out. It presents an argument for this conclusion from considerations about language alone, without assuming anything about what metaphysics aims to do other than that it is concerned with questions of fact, and without assuming anything about what reality in general is like. A crucial consideration in support of this argument concerns the possibility of facts ineffable for us human beings. We can see from reflecting on our own talk about facts that ineffable facts are ruled out, and thus that our languages are ideal languages for representing reality. After discussing how an argument of this kind could possibly work, the chapter outlines some larger metaphysical issues that all this is related to.","PeriodicalId":196928,"journal":{"name":"The Language of Ontology","volume":"97 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-06-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"115328225","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
What Counts as a ‘Good’ Metaphysical Language? 什么是“好的”形而上学语言?
Pub Date : 2021-06-03 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0007
J. T. Miller
The objectively best language is intended to refer to some metaphysically privileged language that ‘carves reality at its joints’ perfectly. That is, it is the kind of language that various ‘metaphysical deflationists’ have argued is impossible. One common line of argument amongst deflationists is that we have no means to compare languages that all express true facts about the world in such a way to decide which is ‘better’. For example, the language is physics is not objectively better than the language of economics, as each language has the semantic purpose of expressing some domain of truths about the world inexpressible in the other language, and therefore neither could be ‘objectively best’. This chapter argues that metaphysical deflationists have failed to recognize a distinction between fine- and coarse-grained semantic purposes of languages, and that a recognition of that distinction provides us grounds to compare languages to see which is objectively best. It argues that once we recognize the distinction between fine- and coarse-grained semantic purposes, then we can see that it is relative to the coarse-grained purpose that we must compare putative objectively best ontological languages.
客观上最好的语言是指一些形而上学上的特权语言,它完美地“刻画了现实”。也就是说,这是各种“形而上学通缩论者”认为不可能的语言。通缩论者的一个常见论点是,我们没有办法以这种方式比较所有表达世界真实事实的语言,以决定哪种语言“更好”。例如,物理语言在客观上并不比经济学语言更好,因为每种语言都有表达另一种语言无法表达的世界真理领域的语义目的,因此两者都不可能是“客观上最好的”。本章认为,形而上学的紧缩主义者未能认识到语言的细粒度和粗粒度语义目的之间的区别,并且认识到这种区别为我们提供了比较语言的基础,以了解客观上最好的语言。它认为,一旦我们认识到细粒度和粗粒度语义目的之间的区别,那么我们就可以看到,相对于粗粒度目的,我们必须比较假定的客观上最好的本体论语言。
{"title":"What Counts as a ‘Good’ Metaphysical Language?","authors":"J. T. Miller","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0007","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0007","url":null,"abstract":"The objectively best language is intended to refer to some metaphysically privileged language that ‘carves reality at its joints’ perfectly. That is, it is the kind of language that various ‘metaphysical deflationists’ have argued is impossible. One common line of argument amongst deflationists is that we have no means to compare languages that all express true facts about the world in such a way to decide which is ‘better’. For example, the language is physics is not objectively better than the language of economics, as each language has the semantic purpose of expressing some domain of truths about the world inexpressible in the other language, and therefore neither could be ‘objectively best’. This chapter argues that metaphysical deflationists have failed to recognize a distinction between fine- and coarse-grained semantic purposes of languages, and that a recognition of that distinction provides us grounds to compare languages to see which is objectively best. It argues that once we recognize the distinction between fine- and coarse-grained semantic purposes, then we can see that it is relative to the coarse-grained purpose that we must compare putative objectively best ontological languages.","PeriodicalId":196928,"journal":{"name":"The Language of Ontology","volume":"14 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-06-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"114463525","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Questions of Ontology 本体论问题
Pub Date : 2021-06-03 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0008
Richard Woodward
Despite its enduring influence, Quine’s account of how we should both understand and go about answering ontological questions has come under increasing fire in the recent metaontological literature. The focus here is on one important and influential critique of Quine’s views, due to Kit Fine (2009), who argues that Quine’s picture of ontology is thoroughly misguided insofar as it both misidentifies the subject matter of ontological questions and misconceives the appropriate methodology for pursuing ontological inquiry. Taking up the defence on behalf of Quine, the chapter argues that Fine’s central objections to the Quinean approach are unsuccessful since the Quinean is well positioned to both explain the apparent triviality of many existential questions and explain how ontological questions might remain open, even once everyday existence questions have been answered in the ordinary business of life.
尽管其持久的影响,奎因关于我们应该如何理解和回答本体论问题的描述在最近的元本体论文献中受到越来越多的抨击。这里的重点是对奎因观点的一个重要而有影响力的批评,这是由Kit Fine(2009)提出的,他认为奎因的本体论观点完全被误导了,因为它既错误地识别了本体论问题的主题,也错误地理解了追求本体论探究的适当方法。本章为奎因辩护,认为费恩对奎因方法的主要反对是不成功的,因为奎因方法既能很好地解释许多存在主义问题的明显琐碎,又能很好地解释本体论问题如何保持开放,即使日常存在问题在日常生活中得到了回答。
{"title":"The Questions of Ontology","authors":"Richard Woodward","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0008","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0008","url":null,"abstract":"Despite its enduring influence, Quine’s account of how we should both understand and go about answering ontological questions has come under increasing fire in the recent metaontological literature. The focus here is on one important and influential critique of Quine’s views, due to Kit Fine (2009), who argues that Quine’s picture of ontology is thoroughly misguided insofar as it both misidentifies the subject matter of ontological questions and misconceives the appropriate methodology for pursuing ontological inquiry. Taking up the defence on behalf of Quine, the chapter argues that Fine’s central objections to the Quinean approach are unsuccessful since the Quinean is well positioned to both explain the apparent triviality of many existential questions and explain how ontological questions might remain open, even once everyday existence questions have been answered in the ordinary business of life.","PeriodicalId":196928,"journal":{"name":"The Language of Ontology","volume":"16 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-06-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"132443984","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Are Ontological Questions Really Meaningless? 本体论问题真的无意义吗?
Pub Date : 2021-06-03 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0003
Delia Belleri
An influential critique of ontology, traditionally linked to Rudolf Carnap, logical empiricism, and verificationism, has it that ontological questions and statements are meaningless. In recent years, Amie Thomasson has revived this Carnapian critique, albeit in a non-verificationist version. This chapter argues that the meaningfulness of ontological statements can be vindicated by appealing to considerations compatible with Thomasson’s Carnapian approach. Two possible avenues are explored. The first is that of specifying the assertibility conditions of ontological statements like ‘There are Fs’, by providing an adequate rule of use. The second is that of spelling out the truth-conditions of the same ontological statements by means of a T-schema where the right-hand side is a sentence formulated in a language specifically introduced for doing ontology—what several authors call ‘Ontologese’. It is proposed that Ontologese be introduced as a bona-fide Carnapian framework, and this option is defended against a number of objections.
传统上与鲁道夫·卡尔纳普、逻辑经验主义和验证主义联系在一起的对本体论的一个有影响力的批判认为,本体论的问题和陈述是没有意义的。近年来,艾米·托马森(Amie Thomasson)重新提出了卡纳普式的批评,尽管是以一种非核查主义的方式。本章认为本体论陈述的意义可以通过诉诸与托马森的卡尔纳普方法相容的考虑来证明。探索了两种可能的途径。第一个是指定本体论陈述的断言性条件,比如"有f ",通过提供一个适当的使用规则。第二种是通过t模式来阐明相同本体论陈述的真值条件,其中右手边是用专门用于本体论的语言表述的句子——一些作者称之为“本体论”。有人建议将本体论作为一个真正的卡纳普框架引入,这个选项受到了许多反对意见的辩护。
{"title":"Are Ontological Questions Really Meaningless?","authors":"Delia Belleri","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0003","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0003","url":null,"abstract":"An influential critique of ontology, traditionally linked to Rudolf Carnap, logical empiricism, and verificationism, has it that ontological questions and statements are meaningless. In recent years, Amie Thomasson has revived this Carnapian critique, albeit in a non-verificationist version. This chapter argues that the meaningfulness of ontological statements can be vindicated by appealing to considerations compatible with Thomasson’s Carnapian approach. Two possible avenues are explored. The first is that of specifying the assertibility conditions of ontological statements like ‘There are Fs’, by providing an adequate rule of use. The second is that of spelling out the truth-conditions of the same ontological statements by means of a T-schema where the right-hand side is a sentence formulated in a language specifically introduced for doing ontology—what several authors call ‘Ontologese’. It is proposed that Ontologese be introduced as a bona-fide Carnapian framework, and this option is defended against a number of objections.","PeriodicalId":196928,"journal":{"name":"The Language of Ontology","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-06-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"130602807","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Ontology by Stipulation 约定本体论
Pub Date : 2021-06-03 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0002
E. Hirsch
In previous work the author suggested that many ontological disputes can be viewed as merely verbal, in that each side can be charitably interpreted as speaking the truth in its own language. Critics have objected that it is more plausible to view the disputants as speaking the same language, perhaps even a special philosophy-room language, sometimes called Ontologese. This chapter suggests a different kind of deflationary move, in a way more extreme (possibly more Carnapian) than the author’s previous suggestion. The chapter supposes we encounter an ontological dispute between two sides, the A-side and the B-side, and we assume that they are speaking the same language so that (at least) one of them is mistaken (perhaps the common language is Ontologese). The author’s suggestion is that we can introduce by stipulation two languages, one for each side, such that in speaking the A-side stipulated language we capture whatever facts might be expressed in the A-side’s position, and in speaking the B-side stipulated language we capture whatever facts might be expressed in the B-side’s position. In this way we get whatever facts there might be in this ontological area without risking falsehood. A further part of the argument consists in explaining why the stipulation maneuver applies to questions of ontology but not to questions of mathematics (such as the Goldbach conjecture). One basic point is that mathematics has application to contingencies in a way that ontology doesn’t.
在之前的工作中,作者提出,许多本体论的争论可以被视为仅仅是口头上的,因为每一方都可以被仁慈地解释为用自己的语言说出真理。批评者反对说,将争论者视为使用同一种语言更为合理,甚至可能是一种特殊的哲学教室语言,有时被称为本体论。这一章提出了一种不同的通缩举措,比作者之前的建议更极端(可能更卡纳帕式)。这一章假设我们遇到了a面和b面双方的本体论争论,我们假设他们说的是同一种语言,所以(至少)他们中的一个是错误的(也许共同的语言是本体论)。作者的建议是,我们可以通过规定引入两种语言,每一方一种语言,这样,在说a方规定的语言时,我们捕捉到可能以a方立场表达的任何事实,在说b方规定的语言时,我们捕捉到可能以b方立场表达的任何事实。通过这种方式,我们可以得到本体论领域中可能存在的任何事实,而不会有错误的风险。论证的进一步部分在于解释为什么规定策略适用于本体论问题,而不适用于数学问题(如哥德巴赫猜想)。一个基本的观点是数学可以应用于偶然性而本体论却不能。
{"title":"Ontology by Stipulation","authors":"E. Hirsch","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0002","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0002","url":null,"abstract":"In previous work the author suggested that many ontological disputes can be viewed as merely verbal, in that each side can be charitably interpreted as speaking the truth in its own language. Critics have objected that it is more plausible to view the disputants as speaking the same language, perhaps even a special philosophy-room language, sometimes called Ontologese. This chapter suggests a different kind of deflationary move, in a way more extreme (possibly more Carnapian) than the author’s previous suggestion. The chapter supposes we encounter an ontological dispute between two sides, the A-side and the B-side, and we assume that they are speaking the same language so that (at least) one of them is mistaken (perhaps the common language is Ontologese). The author’s suggestion is that we can introduce by stipulation two languages, one for each side, such that in speaking the A-side stipulated language we capture whatever facts might be expressed in the A-side’s position, and in speaking the B-side stipulated language we capture whatever facts might be expressed in the B-side’s position. In this way we get whatever facts there might be in this ontological area without risking falsehood. A further part of the argument consists in explaining why the stipulation maneuver applies to questions of ontology but not to questions of mathematics (such as the Goldbach conjecture). One basic point is that mathematics has application to contingencies in a way that ontology doesn’t.","PeriodicalId":196928,"journal":{"name":"The Language of Ontology","volume":"110 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-06-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"122609332","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Ontological Expressivism
Pub Date : 2021-06-03 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0005
Vera Flocke
Ontological expressivism is the view that ontological existence claims express noncognitive mental states. The chapter develops a version of ontological expressivism that is modeled after Gibbard’s (2003) norm-expressivism. It argues that, when speakers assess whether, say, composite objects exist, they rely on assumptions with regard to what is required for composition to occur. These assumptions guide their assessment, similar to how norms may guide the assessment of normative propositions. Against this backdrop, the chapter argues that “some objects have parts”, uttered in the context of an ontological disagreement, expresses a noncognitive disposition to assess the truth of propositions by using only rules of assessment according to which the proposition that some objects have parts is to be evaluated as true.
本体论表现主义认为本体论的存在主张表达了非认知的心理状态。本章以吉巴德(2003)的规范表现主义为蓝本,发展了本体论表现主义的一个版本。它认为,当说话者评估,比如说,合成物体是否存在时,他们依赖于关于合成发生所需条件的假设。这些假设指导他们的评估,类似于规范如何指导规范性命题的评估。在此背景下,本章认为,在本体论分歧的背景下,“一些物体有部分”表达了一种非认知倾向,即通过仅使用评估规则来评估命题的真性,根据评估规则,一些物体有部分的命题将被评估为真。
{"title":"Ontological Expressivism","authors":"Vera Flocke","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0005","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192895332.003.0005","url":null,"abstract":"Ontological expressivism is the view that ontological existence claims express noncognitive mental states. The chapter develops a version of ontological expressivism that is modeled after Gibbard’s (2003) norm-expressivism. It argues that, when speakers assess whether, say, composite objects exist, they rely on assumptions with regard to what is required for composition to occur. These assumptions guide their assessment, similar to how norms may guide the assessment of normative propositions. Against this backdrop, the chapter argues that “some objects have parts”, uttered in the context of an ontological disagreement, expresses a noncognitive disposition to assess the truth of propositions by using only rules of assessment according to which the proposition that some objects have parts is to be evaluated as true.","PeriodicalId":196928,"journal":{"name":"The Language of Ontology","volume":"12 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-06-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"128719606","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
期刊
The Language of Ontology
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1