首页 > 最新文献

George Berkeley and Early Modern Philosophy最新文献

英文 中文
Berkeley on God 贝克莱论上帝
Pub Date : 2021-03-23 DOI: 10.1093/OSO/9780192893895.003.0015
S. Daniel
Berkeley’s use of a posteriori arguments supports a view of God that is accessible and persuasive for finite minds. However, those arguments ultimately support belief only in a God who is finite. This chapter shows how, by appealing to an a priori argument for God’s existence, Berkeley emphasizes God’s infinity. This does not undermine other arguments, for it does not aim to challenge how those arguments support belief in a God who accounts for all we experience. It only indicates that another kind of argument is needed to show how our knowledge of the existence of an infinite God does not depend a posteriori on our experience of things in the world.
柏克莱使用的后验论证支持了一种对于有限的头脑来说是可以理解和有说服力的上帝观。然而,这些论点最终只支持上帝是有限的信仰。本章展示了贝克莱是如何通过对上帝存在的先验论证来强调上帝的无限性的。这并没有破坏其他的论点,因为它的目的并不是挑战这些论点是如何支持对上帝的信仰的,上帝解释了我们所经历的一切。它只是表明,需要另一种论证来证明,我们对无限上帝的存在的认识,并不事后依赖于我们对世界上事物的经验。
{"title":"Berkeley on God","authors":"S. Daniel","doi":"10.1093/OSO/9780192893895.003.0015","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/OSO/9780192893895.003.0015","url":null,"abstract":"Berkeley’s use of a posteriori arguments supports a view of God that is accessible and persuasive for finite minds. However, those arguments ultimately support belief only in a God who is finite. This chapter shows how, by appealing to an a priori argument for God’s existence, Berkeley emphasizes God’s infinity. This does not undermine other arguments, for it does not aim to challenge how those arguments support belief in a God who accounts for all we experience. It only indicates that another kind of argument is needed to show how our knowledge of the existence of an infinite God does not depend a posteriori on our experience of things in the world.","PeriodicalId":268491,"journal":{"name":"George Berkeley and Early Modern Philosophy","volume":"23 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-03-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"126263828","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Berkeley on God’s Knowledge of Pain 柏克莱论上帝对痛苦的知识
Pub Date : 2018-02-15 DOI: 10.1093/OSO/9780198755685.003.0009
S. Daniel
Since nothing about God is passive, and the perception of pain is inherently passive, then it seems that God does not know what it is like to experience pain. Nor would he be able to cause us to experience pain, for his experience would then be a sensation (which he does not have). My suggestion is that Berkeley avoids this situation by describing how God knows about pain “among other things” (i.e. as something whose identity is intelligible in terms of the integrated network of things). This avoids having to assume that God has ideas (including pain) apart from his willing that there be perceivers who have specific ideas that are in harmony or not in harmony with one another.
既然上帝不是被动的,对痛苦的感知本身就是被动的,那么上帝似乎不知道经历痛苦是什么感觉。他也不能使我们体验到痛苦,因为这样他的体验就会变成一种感觉(他没有这种感觉)。我的建议是,伯克利通过描述上帝如何“在其他事物中”了解疼痛来避免这种情况(即,作为某种事物的身份在事物的综合网络中是可理解的)。这就避免了必须假定上帝除了有他的意愿之外还有一些想法(包括痛苦),这些想法彼此和谐或不和谐的感知者。
{"title":"Berkeley on God’s Knowledge of Pain","authors":"S. Daniel","doi":"10.1093/OSO/9780198755685.003.0009","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/OSO/9780198755685.003.0009","url":null,"abstract":"Since nothing about God is passive, and the perception of pain is inherently passive, then it seems that God does not know what it is like to experience pain. Nor would he be able to cause us to experience pain, for his experience would then be a sensation (which he does not have). My suggestion is that Berkeley avoids this situation by describing how God knows about pain “among other things” (i.e. as something whose identity is intelligible in terms of the integrated network of things). This avoids having to assume that God has ideas (including pain) apart from his willing that there be perceivers who have specific ideas that are in harmony or not in harmony with one another.","PeriodicalId":268491,"journal":{"name":"George Berkeley and Early Modern Philosophy","volume":"48 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-02-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"121464711","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Berkeley and Spinoza 伯克利和斯宾诺莎
Pub Date : 2010-02-23 DOI: 10.3917/RPHI.101.0123
S. Daniel
There is a widespread assumption that Berkeley and Spinoza have little in common, even though early Jesuit critics in France often linked them. Later commentators have also recognized their similarities. This chapter focuses on how Berkeley’s comments on the Arnauld–Malebranche debate regarding objective and formal reality, and on his treatment of God’s creation of finite minds within nature relate his theory of knowledge to his doctrine in a way similar to that of Spinoza.
人们普遍认为伯克利和斯宾诺莎没有什么共同之处,尽管法国早期的耶稣会批评家经常把他们联系在一起。后来的评论家也认识到了他们的相似之处。这一章的重点是伯克利如何评论关于客观和形式现实的arnaud - malebranche辩论,以及他对上帝在自然中创造有限心灵的处理,以一种类似于斯宾诺莎的方式将他的知识理论与他的学说联系起来。
{"title":"Berkeley and Spinoza","authors":"S. Daniel","doi":"10.3917/RPHI.101.0123","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3917/RPHI.101.0123","url":null,"abstract":"There is a widespread assumption that Berkeley and Spinoza have little in common, even though early Jesuit critics in France often linked them. Later commentators have also recognized their similarities. This chapter focuses on how Berkeley’s comments on the Arnauld–Malebranche debate regarding objective and formal reality, and on his treatment of God’s creation of finite minds within nature relate his theory of knowledge to his doctrine in a way similar to that of Spinoza.","PeriodicalId":268491,"journal":{"name":"George Berkeley and Early Modern Philosophy","volume":"31 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2010-02-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"133056220","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Harmony of the Leibniz–Berkeley Juxtaposition 莱布尼茨和伯克利并置的和谐
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192893895.003.0014
S. Daniel
The juxtaposition of the views of Leibniz and Berkeley indicate how the very points mistakenly cited to differentiate them are clarified precisely by appreciating their similarities, particularly in terms of understanding how minds differentiate and relate bodies. Such a strategy is especially useful for understanding how their accounts of perception, substance, and contingency depend on their mutual commitment to the harmony of all things and on their sensitivity to distinguishing the different domains of natural philosophy and metaphysics.
莱布尼茨和伯克利的观点的并列表明,通过欣赏他们的相似性,特别是在理解心灵如何区分和联系身体方面,错误地引用来区分他们的观点是如何精确地澄清的。这种策略对于理解他们对感知、实体和偶然性的描述是如何依赖于他们对万物和谐的共同承诺,以及他们对区分自然哲学和形而上学不同领域的敏感性,是特别有用的。
{"title":"The Harmony of the Leibniz–Berkeley Juxtaposition","authors":"S. Daniel","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780192893895.003.0014","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192893895.003.0014","url":null,"abstract":"The juxtaposition of the views of Leibniz and Berkeley indicate how the very points mistakenly cited to differentiate them are clarified precisely by appreciating their similarities, particularly in terms of understanding how minds differentiate and relate bodies. Such a strategy is especially useful for understanding how their accounts of perception, substance, and contingency depend on their mutual commitment to the harmony of all things and on their sensitivity to distinguishing the different domains of natural philosophy and metaphysics.","PeriodicalId":268491,"journal":{"name":"George Berkeley and Early Modern Philosophy","volume":"96 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"131584012","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Berkeley, Suárez, and the Esse–Existere Distinction 伯克利,Suárez,和本质-存在的区别
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192893895.003.0004
S. Daniel
For Berkeley, a thing’s existence (esse) is nothing more than its being perceived “as that thing”. It makes no sense to ask (with Samuel Johnson) about the esse of the mind or the specific act of perception, for that would be like asking what it means for existence to exist. Berkeley’s “existere is percipi or percipere” thus carefully adopts the scholastic distinction between esse and existere ignored by Locke and others committed to a substantialist notion of mind. Following the Stoics, Berkeley proposes that, as the existence of ideas, minds “subsist” rather than “exist” and thus cannot be identified as independently existing things.
对于贝克莱来说,一个事物的存在(esse)只不过是它被感知为“那个事物”。问(塞缪尔·约翰逊的)心灵的存在或特定的感知行为是没有意义的,因为这就像问存在的存在意味着什么。因此,贝克莱的“存在即感知或感知”谨慎地采用了洛克和其他致力于心灵实体主义概念的人所忽略的存在和存在之间的学术区别。继斯多葛学派之后,伯克利提出,作为观念的存在,心灵“生存”而不是“存在”,因此不能被认定为独立存在的事物。
{"title":"Berkeley, Suárez, and the Esse–Existere Distinction","authors":"S. Daniel","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780192893895.003.0004","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192893895.003.0004","url":null,"abstract":"For Berkeley, a thing’s existence (esse) is nothing more than its being perceived “as that thing”. It makes no sense to ask (with Samuel Johnson) about the esse of the mind or the specific act of perception, for that would be like asking what it means for existence to exist. Berkeley’s “existere is percipi or percipere” thus carefully adopts the scholastic distinction between esse and existere ignored by Locke and others committed to a substantialist notion of mind. Following the Stoics, Berkeley proposes that, as the existence of ideas, minds “subsist” rather than “exist” and thus cannot be identified as independently existing things.","PeriodicalId":268491,"journal":{"name":"George Berkeley and Early Modern Philosophy","volume":"39 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"125674767","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
How Berkeley’s Works Are Interpreted 如何解读伯克利的作品
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.1007/978-90-481-9243-4_1
S. Daniel
{"title":"How Berkeley’s Works Are Interpreted","authors":"S. Daniel","doi":"10.1007/978-90-481-9243-4_1","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-9243-4_1","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":268491,"journal":{"name":"George Berkeley and Early Modern Philosophy","volume":"15 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"128510661","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Berkeley’s Stoic Notion of Spiritual Substances 伯克利的斯多葛派精神物质观
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192893895.003.0002
S. Daniel
For Berkeley, minds are not Cartesian spiritual substances because they cannot be said to exist (even if only conceptually) abstracted from their activities. Similarly, Berkeley’s notion of mind differs from Locke’s in that, for Berkeley, minds are not abstract substrata in which ideas inhere. Instead, a mind is a substance in a way consistent with the Stoic logic of the seventeenth-century Ramists on which Leibniz and Jonathan Edwards draw. The Stoic character of Berkeley’s philosophy is recognizable only when we see how it is based on a doctrine in which perceptions or ideas are intelligible precisely because they are always embedded in the propositions of a discourse or language.
对于伯克利来说,心灵不是笛卡尔式的精神实体,因为它们不能被说成是从活动中抽象出来的存在(即使只是概念上的)。同样,贝克莱的心灵概念与洛克的不同之处在于,对于贝克莱来说,心灵不是抽象的基础,而观念则在其中。相反,心灵是一种物质,在某种程度上与莱布尼茨和乔纳森·爱德华兹所借鉴的十七世纪拉米主义者的斯多葛派逻辑是一致的。贝克莱哲学的斯多葛主义特征,只有当我们看到它是如何建立在这样一种学说的基础上时,我们才能认识到,在这种学说中,知觉或观念是可以理解的,因为它们总是嵌入在话语或语言的命题中。
{"title":"Berkeley’s Stoic Notion of Spiritual Substances","authors":"S. Daniel","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780192893895.003.0002","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192893895.003.0002","url":null,"abstract":"For Berkeley, minds are not Cartesian spiritual substances because they cannot be said to exist (even if only conceptually) abstracted from their activities. Similarly, Berkeley’s notion of mind differs from Locke’s in that, for Berkeley, minds are not abstract substrata in which ideas inhere. Instead, a mind is a substance in a way consistent with the Stoic logic of the seventeenth-century Ramists on which Leibniz and Jonathan Edwards draw. The Stoic character of Berkeley’s philosophy is recognizable only when we see how it is based on a doctrine in which perceptions or ideas are intelligible precisely because they are always embedded in the propositions of a discourse or language.","PeriodicalId":268491,"journal":{"name":"George Berkeley and Early Modern Philosophy","volume":"205 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"123048801","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Ramist Context of Berkeley’s Philosophy 伯克利哲学的Ramist语境
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192893895.003.0003
S. Daniel
Berkeley’s doctrines about mind, the language of nature, substance, minima sensibilia, notions, abstract ideas, inference, and freedom appropriate principles developed by the sixteenth-century logician Peter Ramus and his seventeenth-century followers (e.g. Alexander Richardson, William Ames, John Milton). Even though Berkeley expresses himself in Cartesian or Lockean terms, he relies on a Ramist way of thinking that is not a form of mere rhetoric or pedagogy but a logic and ontology grounded in Stoicism. This chapter summarizes the central features of Ramism, indicates how Berkeley adapts Ramist concepts and strategies, and chronicles Ramism’s pervasiveness in Berkeley’s education, especially at Trinity College Dublin.
伯克利关于心灵、自然语言、物质、最小感性、概念、抽象观念、推理和自由的学说,是16世纪逻辑学家彼得·拉莫斯及其17世纪追随者(如亚历山大·理查森、威廉·埃姆斯、约翰·弥尔顿)发展起来的原则。尽管贝克莱用笛卡尔或洛克的术语来表达自己,但他依靠的是一种Ramist的思维方式,这种思维方式不仅仅是一种修辞或教育学形式,而是一种基于斯多葛主义的逻辑和本体论。本章总结了拉米主义的主要特征,指出了伯克利如何适应拉米主义的概念和策略,并记录了拉米主义在伯克利教育中的普及,特别是在都柏林三一学院。
{"title":"The Ramist Context of Berkeley’s Philosophy","authors":"S. Daniel","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780192893895.003.0003","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192893895.003.0003","url":null,"abstract":"Berkeley’s doctrines about mind, the language of nature, substance, minima sensibilia, notions, abstract ideas, inference, and freedom appropriate principles developed by the sixteenth-century logician Peter Ramus and his seventeenth-century followers (e.g. Alexander Richardson, William Ames, John Milton). Even though Berkeley expresses himself in Cartesian or Lockean terms, he relies on a Ramist way of thinking that is not a form of mere rhetoric or pedagogy but a logic and ontology grounded in Stoicism. This chapter summarizes the central features of Ramism, indicates how Berkeley adapts Ramist concepts and strategies, and chronicles Ramism’s pervasiveness in Berkeley’s education, especially at Trinity College Dublin.","PeriodicalId":268491,"journal":{"name":"George Berkeley and Early Modern Philosophy","volume":"48 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"133509581","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
George Berkeley and Early Modern Philosophy
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1