首页 > 最新文献

Life and Death in Early Modern Philosophy最新文献

英文 中文
Human Life as a State of Mediocrity in John Locke 约翰·洛克的《作为平庸状态的人类生活
Pub Date : 2021-09-07 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192843616.003.0005
G. D. Biase
This chapter investigates the genesis and evolution of Locke’s idea of human life as a “state of mediocrity”. While this idea had ancient roots going back to the early Church fathers, it remained current in the seventeenth century where mediocrity was generally equated with a condition of partial ignorance and imperfection. Locke’s account of it is original; while life is a time of mediocrity, death opens the way to the extremes of eternal misery or eternal happiness. Initially, inspired by the Church fathers, Locke conceived of human life as a condition of intellectual mediocrity. Subsequently, and arguably prompted by his reading of the pessimistic outlooks of Nicole and Pascal, he redefined the state of mediocrity in more optimistic terms: humans are naturally suited to their mediocre state. A further development of his conception of mediocrity, again involving a partial rethinking of the human condition, can be found in the Essay, where Locke represents mediocrity as an imperfect state of insatiable desire. It is redeemed, however, by the ability of living human beings to attain perfect knowledge of morality.
这一章考察了洛克关于人类生活是一种“平庸状态”的观点的起源和演变。虽然这种观念的根源可以追溯到早期的教父们,但它在17世纪仍然很流行,当时平庸通常被等同于部分无知和不完美的状态。洛克对它的描述是原创的;生命是一段平庸的时光,而死亡则开启了通往永恒痛苦或永恒幸福的极端之路。最初,受教父们的启发,洛克认为人类的生活是智力平庸的状态。随后,可以说是由于他阅读了尼科尔和帕斯卡的悲观观点,他以更乐观的方式重新定义了平庸的状态:人类天生就适合他们的平庸状态。他的平庸概念的进一步发展,再次涉及对人类状况的部分反思,可以在《随笔》中找到,洛克将平庸描述为一种贪得无厌的欲望的不完美状态。然而,它被活着的人获得完美的道德知识的能力所弥补。
{"title":"Human Life as a State of Mediocrity in John Locke","authors":"G. D. Biase","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780192843616.003.0005","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192843616.003.0005","url":null,"abstract":"This chapter investigates the genesis and evolution of Locke’s idea of human life as a “state of mediocrity”. While this idea had ancient roots going back to the early Church fathers, it remained current in the seventeenth century where mediocrity was generally equated with a condition of partial ignorance and imperfection. Locke’s account of it is original; while life is a time of mediocrity, death opens the way to the extremes of eternal misery or eternal happiness. Initially, inspired by the Church fathers, Locke conceived of human life as a condition of intellectual mediocrity. Subsequently, and arguably prompted by his reading of the pessimistic outlooks of Nicole and Pascal, he redefined the state of mediocrity in more optimistic terms: humans are naturally suited to their mediocre state. A further development of his conception of mediocrity, again involving a partial rethinking of the human condition, can be found in the Essay, where Locke represents mediocrity as an imperfect state of insatiable desire. It is redeemed, however, by the ability of living human beings to attain perfect knowledge of morality.","PeriodicalId":129974,"journal":{"name":"Life and Death in Early Modern Philosophy","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-09-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"123189221","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Consciousness of Being Alive as a Source of Knowledge 作为知识源泉的活着的意识
Pub Date : 2021-09-07 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192843616.003.0002
U. Renz
This chapter addresses the question whether our consciousness of being alive can be a source of knowledge, and if so, of what kind of knowledge. It examines this question as it is discussed by a sequence of early modern philosophers who all implicitly consider the issue. The chapter begins with a discussion of the early modern idea of consciousness, viewed as an epistemic relation. It goes on to show that interest in the notion that we are immediately aware of being alive arose in reaction to Descartes’ dualism. For example, the Cartesian Louis de La Forge attempted, but failed, to accommodate the feeling of being alive within a dualist framework. Against this background, the chapter turns to discuss Spinoza’s early attempts to appeal to our consciousness of being alive in order to refute Cartesian scepticism. It concludes that our consciousness of being alive can be considered a source of knowledge, and that, however simple this lesson appears, it may be of moral importance.
这一章讨论的问题是,我们活着的意识是否可以成为知识的来源,如果可以,是什么样的知识。它考察了这个问题,因为它是由一系列早期现代哲学家讨论的,他们都含蓄地考虑这个问题。这一章首先讨论了早期现代的意识概念,将其视为一种认知关系。它继续表明,人们对“我们立即意识到自己活着”这一概念的兴趣是对笛卡尔二元论的回应。例如,笛卡尔学派的路易斯·德·拉·福吉(Louis de La Forge)试图在二元论框架内容纳活着的感觉,但失败了。在此背景下,本章转而讨论斯宾诺莎早期试图诉诸我们的活着意识,以驳斥笛卡尔的怀疑主义。它的结论是,我们活着的意识可以被认为是知识的来源,而且,无论这个教训看起来多么简单,它可能具有道德重要性。
{"title":"The Consciousness of Being Alive as a Source of Knowledge","authors":"U. Renz","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780192843616.003.0002","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192843616.003.0002","url":null,"abstract":"This chapter addresses the question whether our consciousness of being alive can be a source of knowledge, and if so, of what kind of knowledge. It examines this question as it is discussed by a sequence of early modern philosophers who all implicitly consider the issue. The chapter begins with a discussion of the early modern idea of consciousness, viewed as an epistemic relation. It goes on to show that interest in the notion that we are immediately aware of being alive arose in reaction to Descartes’ dualism. For example, the Cartesian Louis de La Forge attempted, but failed, to accommodate the feeling of being alive within a dualist framework. Against this background, the chapter turns to discuss Spinoza’s early attempts to appeal to our consciousness of being alive in order to refute Cartesian scepticism. It concludes that our consciousness of being alive can be considered a source of knowledge, and that, however simple this lesson appears, it may be of moral importance.","PeriodicalId":129974,"journal":{"name":"Life and Death in Early Modern Philosophy","volume":"48 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-09-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"131354361","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Banishment of Death 死神的放逐
Pub Date : 2021-09-07 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192843616.003.0004
M. F. Camposampiero
Leibniz upholds immortalism in its extreme form. Nothing ever really dies, for animals (and not only their souls) are indestructible except by God’s power. Eighteenth-century philosophers described Leibniz’s doctrine as exilium mortis or “the banishment of death”, which most of them rejected as an implausible, ridiculous, or even scandalous notion. In order to understand this negative reaction, this chapter reconstructs the German debate among Leibniz’s contemporaries and immediate posterity on such issues as: Is the banishment of death a novelty or just an updated version of some traditional belief? How can the living body preserve its own identity through the dramatic transformations caused by death? On the other hand, the general hostility that surrounded the banishment-of-death doctrine suggests that the denial of natural mortality was actually perceived as a threat to Christian dogma – which challenges the naive assumption that immortalist claims are mere expression of a philosopher’s pious concerns.
莱布尼茨支持极端形式的不朽主义。没有什么是真正死亡的,因为动物(不仅是它们的灵魂)是坚不可摧的,除非是上帝的力量。18世纪的哲学家将莱布尼茨的学说描述为“放逐死亡”,他们中的大多数人认为这是一个不可信的、荒谬的、甚至是可耻的概念。为了理解这种负面反应,本章重构了莱布尼茨的同时代人和直接后代之间的德国辩论,这些问题包括:驱逐死亡是一种新鲜事物还是仅仅是一些传统信仰的更新版本?活着的身体如何通过死亡所造成的戏剧性变化来保持自己的身份?另一方面,对死亡驱逐论的普遍敌意表明,对自然死亡的否认实际上被视为对基督教教义的威胁——这挑战了人们天真的假设,即永生论者的主张仅仅是哲学家虔诚关切的表达。
{"title":"The Banishment of Death","authors":"M. F. Camposampiero","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780192843616.003.0004","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192843616.003.0004","url":null,"abstract":"Leibniz upholds immortalism in its extreme form. Nothing ever really dies, for animals (and not only their souls) are indestructible except by God’s power. Eighteenth-century philosophers described Leibniz’s doctrine as exilium mortis or “the banishment of death”, which most of them rejected as an implausible, ridiculous, or even scandalous notion. In order to understand this negative reaction, this chapter reconstructs the German debate among Leibniz’s contemporaries and immediate posterity on such issues as: Is the banishment of death a novelty or just an updated version of some traditional belief? How can the living body preserve its own identity through the dramatic transformations caused by death? On the other hand, the general hostility that surrounded the banishment-of-death doctrine suggests that the denial of natural mortality was actually perceived as a threat to Christian dogma – which challenges the naive assumption that immortalist claims are mere expression of a philosopher’s pious concerns.","PeriodicalId":129974,"journal":{"name":"Life and Death in Early Modern Philosophy","volume":"141 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-09-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"128994668","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Vitalism and the Metaphysics of Life 活力论与生命的形而上学
Pub Date : 2021-09-07 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192843616.003.0016
C. Wolfe
I examine a series of definitions, defences and rejections of early modern vitalism. This yields a broad distinction between more or less metaphysically committed forms of vitalism. Given the plurivocity of the term, I suggest that we restrict the term ‘vitalist’ to thinkers who are actively concerned with the distinction between life and non-life (whether or not they substantialize this distinction), with special reference to the case of eighteenth-century Montpellier vitalism – where the term was first explicitly used. Further, I discuss the association of vitalism with a (potentially problematic) metaphysics of life as partly a polemical construct – which is internal to the process of defining projects and programs in life science, where one vital(istical)ly oriented author will, almost desperately, seek to brand a predecessor or a rival as a vitalist in order to legitimize her own apparently more ‘experimental’ brand of organicism. But perhaps metaphysics is endemic to vitalism?
我考察了一系列对早期现代活力论的定义、辩护和拒绝。这就产生了生机论或多或少的形而上学形式之间的广泛区别。考虑到这个词的多样性,我建议我们将“生机论者”这个词限制在那些积极关注生命与非生命之间区别的思想家(无论他们是否将这种区别具体化),特别参考18世纪蒙彼利埃生机论者的案例——这个词第一次被明确使用。此外,我还讨论了活力论与生命形而上学(潜在的问题)之间的联系,这在一定程度上是一种争论性的结构——这是生命科学中定义项目和计划的过程的内部,在这个过程中,一个充满活力的(统计的)导向的作者将几乎绝望地寻求将一个前任或对手标记为活力论者,以使她自己明显更“实验性”的有机论品牌合法化。但也许形而上学是活力论的特色?
{"title":"Vitalism and the Metaphysics of Life","authors":"C. Wolfe","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780192843616.003.0016","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192843616.003.0016","url":null,"abstract":"I examine a series of definitions, defences and rejections of early modern vitalism. This yields a broad distinction between more or less metaphysically committed forms of vitalism. Given the plurivocity of the term, I suggest that we restrict the term ‘vitalist’ to thinkers who are actively concerned with the distinction between life and non-life (whether or not they substantialize this distinction), with special reference to the case of eighteenth-century Montpellier vitalism – where the term was first explicitly used. Further, I discuss the association of vitalism with a (potentially problematic) metaphysics of life as partly a polemical construct – which is internal to the process of defining projects and programs in life science, where one vital(istical)ly oriented author will, almost desperately, seek to brand a predecessor or a rival as a vitalist in order to legitimize her own apparently more ‘experimental’ brand of organicism. But perhaps metaphysics is endemic to vitalism?","PeriodicalId":129974,"journal":{"name":"Life and Death in Early Modern Philosophy","volume":"14 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-09-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"128774414","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Affect and Effect Affect和Effect
Pub Date : 2021-09-07 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192843616.003.0015
S. Marston
Spinoza argues that all entities are animated. Nonetheless, his philosophy provides a systematic grounding for our everyday distinction between living and non-living things. While all bodies in motion bring about transitive effects, living things share a further capacity for bringing about transformative effects, making real changes in themselves and in other entities. Further, this capacity in living things derives from their acting in virtue of their inadequate ideas. Inadequate ideas in Spinoza’s philosophy are thus intrinsic to living things’ being the kinds of things they are, underpinning both the everyday distinction between living and non-living things and the observable varying repertoires of effect among living things themselves.
斯宾诺莎认为所有的实体都是有生命的。尽管如此,他的哲学为我们日常区分生物和非生物提供了系统的基础。虽然所有运动中的物体都带来传递效应,但生物具有带来变革效应的进一步能力,使自己和其他实体发生真正的变化。此外,生物的这种能力来自于它们凭借不充分的观念而采取的行动。因此,斯宾诺莎哲学中的不充分观念是生物作为它们的种类所固有的,支撑着生物和非生物之间的日常区别,以及生物本身可观察到的不同效果。
{"title":"Affect and Effect","authors":"S. Marston","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780192843616.003.0015","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192843616.003.0015","url":null,"abstract":"Spinoza argues that all entities are animated. Nonetheless, his philosophy provides a systematic grounding for our everyday distinction between living and non-living things. While all bodies in motion bring about transitive effects, living things share a further capacity for bringing about transformative effects, making real changes in themselves and in other entities. Further, this capacity in living things derives from their acting in virtue of their inadequate ideas. Inadequate ideas in Spinoza’s philosophy are thus intrinsic to living things’ being the kinds of things they are, underpinning both the everyday distinction between living and non-living things and the observable varying repertoires of effect among living things themselves.","PeriodicalId":129974,"journal":{"name":"Life and Death in Early Modern Philosophy","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-09-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"131191305","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
‘The Thought of Death Changes all our Ideas and Condemns all our Plans’ “死亡的想法改变了我们所有的想法,谴责了我们所有的计划”
Pub Date : 2021-09-07 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192843616.003.0003
M. Moriarty
The chapter highlights the variety of specifically Christian philosophical approaches to the question of the soul’s immortality. Leonard Lessius and Jean de Silhon, working within a broadly Aristotelian framework, argue that the purposiveness universally apparent in nature would be frustrated if humans were mortal. Descartes eschews such appeals to the divine purpose, but his dualist metaphysics offers grounds for belief in the soul’s capacity to survive death. He and Elisabeth of Bohemia discuss how far belief in a happier life after death should affect our pursuit of earthly happiness. Pascal rejects philosophical proofs of immortality, while insisting that we must take an existential stance that admits it as a possibility. Malebranche seeks to highlight the unreality of earthly goods, but, by distinguishing the physical from the intelligible body, he investigates the possibility of post-mortem forms of experience (sensations and attachments) that are in some sense continuous with those of this life.
这一章强调了基督教哲学对灵魂不朽问题的各种具体方法。莱纳德·莱西乌斯和让·德·席隆在宽泛的亚里士多德框架下进行研究,他们认为,如果人类终有一死,自然界普遍存在的合意性将会受到挫折。笛卡尔回避了这种对神圣目的的呼吁,但他的二元论形而上学为相信灵魂在死亡中幸存的能力提供了依据。他和波西米亚的伊丽莎白讨论了对死后更幸福生活的信仰应该在多大程度上影响我们对世俗幸福的追求。帕斯卡拒绝不朽的哲学证明,同时坚持认为我们必须采取一种存在主义的立场,承认它是一种可能性。Malebranche试图突出世俗事物的非现实性,但是,通过将物质与可理解的身体区分开来,他研究了死后体验形式(感觉和依恋)的可能性,这些形式在某种意义上与今生的体验是连续的。
{"title":"‘The Thought of Death Changes all our Ideas and Condemns all our Plans’","authors":"M. Moriarty","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780192843616.003.0003","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192843616.003.0003","url":null,"abstract":"The chapter highlights the variety of specifically Christian philosophical approaches to the question of the soul’s immortality. Leonard Lessius and Jean de Silhon, working within a broadly Aristotelian framework, argue that the purposiveness universally apparent in nature would be frustrated if humans were mortal. Descartes eschews such appeals to the divine purpose, but his dualist metaphysics offers grounds for belief in the soul’s capacity to survive death. He and Elisabeth of Bohemia discuss how far belief in a happier life after death should affect our pursuit of earthly happiness. Pascal rejects philosophical proofs of immortality, while insisting that we must take an existential stance that admits it as a possibility. Malebranche seeks to highlight the unreality of earthly goods, but, by distinguishing the physical from the intelligible body, he investigates the possibility of post-mortem forms of experience (sensations and attachments) that are in some sense continuous with those of this life.","PeriodicalId":129974,"journal":{"name":"Life and Death in Early Modern Philosophy","volume":"63 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-09-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"122125864","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
‘Meditatio Mortis’
Pub Date : 2021-09-07 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192843616.003.0008
Michael Jaworzyn
The Cartesian Johannes Clauberg (1622-1665) sometimes refers to philosophy as meditatio mortis, which he understands as the separation of the mind from the body. This chapter outlines the ways that Clauberg amends the Cartesian accounts of the union of mind and body and of the nature of life and death in such a way as to be able to accommodate this view of philosophy. It argues that Clauberg adopts a broader account of life and death than Descartes, and alters the nature and extent of the mind’s and body’s respective causal powers to that end. Finally, the chapter looks at the implications of this conception of philosophy in Clauberg’s broader philosophical and theological context. Not only does philosophical contemplation provide no guidance in the practical sphere – including in theology – but it can be detrimental to our everyday lives.
笛卡尔学派的约翰内斯·克劳伯格(1622-1665)有时将哲学称为冥思,他将其理解为精神与肉体的分离。这一章概述了克劳伯格如何修正笛卡尔关于身心结合以及生与死的本质的解释以适应他的哲学观点。它认为,克劳伯格采用了比笛卡尔更广泛的生与死解释,并为此改变了心灵和身体各自因果力量的性质和程度。最后,本章着眼于克劳伯格在更广泛的哲学和神学背景下这一哲学概念的含义。哲学思考不仅不能在实践领域(包括神学领域)提供指导,而且可能对我们的日常生活有害。
{"title":"‘Meditatio Mortis’","authors":"Michael Jaworzyn","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780192843616.003.0008","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192843616.003.0008","url":null,"abstract":"The Cartesian Johannes Clauberg (1622-1665) sometimes refers to philosophy as meditatio mortis, which he understands as the separation of the mind from the body. This chapter outlines the ways that Clauberg amends the Cartesian accounts of the union of mind and body and of the nature of life and death in such a way as to be able to accommodate this view of philosophy. It argues that Clauberg adopts a broader account of life and death than Descartes, and alters the nature and extent of the mind’s and body’s respective causal powers to that end. Finally, the chapter looks at the implications of this conception of philosophy in Clauberg’s broader philosophical and theological context. Not only does philosophical contemplation provide no guidance in the practical sphere – including in theology – but it can be detrimental to our everyday lives.","PeriodicalId":129974,"journal":{"name":"Life and Death in Early Modern Philosophy","volume":"17 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-09-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"121500086","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Life and Death in Early Modern Philosophy
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1